Results for 'dogmatism paradox'

949 found
Order:
  1. The Dogmatism Paradox and the problem of misleading evidence.Hamid Vahid - 2012 - Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 31 (1):47-58.
  2. Kripke and the dogmatism paradox.Kaave Lajevardi - manuscript
    I aim at dissolving Kripke's dogmatism paradox by arguing that, with respect to any particular proposition p which is known by a subject A, it is not irrational for A to ignore all evidence against p. Along the way, I offer a definition of 'A is dogmatic with respect to p', and make a distinction between an objective and a subjective sense of 'should' in the statement 'A should ignore all the evidence against p'. For the most part, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  67
    Non-dogmatism and ethical paradoxes.Brenda Cohen - 1972 - Mind 81 (323):432-433.
  4.  38
    Dogmatism” and Dogmatism.John Biro - 2024 - Episteme 21 (2):540-544.
    The so-called paradox of dogmatism has it that it seems that one is both entitled and not entitled to ignore evidence against what one knows. By knowing something, one knows it to be true, and one also knows that there can be no non-misleading evidence against what is true. But to ignore evidence against what one believes – and, surely, one believes what one knows – is to be dogmatic, something one should not be. I argue that there (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5. (2 other versions)The perils of dogmatism.Crispin Wright - 2007 - In Susana Nuccetelli & Gary Seay (eds.), Themes from G. E. Moore: New Essays in Epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press.
    "Dogmatism" is a term renovated by James Pryor [2000] to stand for a certain kind of neo-Moorean response to Scepticism and an associated conception of the architecture of basic perceptual warrant. Pryor runs the response only for (some kinds of) perceptual knowledge but here I will be concerned with its general structure and potential as a possible global anti-sceptical strategy. Something like it is arguably also present in recent writings of Burge 1 and Peacocke.2 If the global strategy could (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  6.  93
    Self-knowledge and the Paradox of Belief Revision.Giovanni Merlo - 2022 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 13 (1):65-83.
    To qualify as a fully rational agent, one must be able rationally to revise one’s beliefs in the light of new evidence. This requires, not only that one revise one’s beliefs in the right way, but also that one do so as a result of appreciating the evidence on the basis of which one is changing one’s mind. However, the very nature of belief seems to pose an obstacle to the possibility of satisfying this requirement – for, insofar as one (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  45
    A new paradox of belief.Benoit Gaultier - forthcoming - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy.
    In this paper I raise a paradox of belief inspired by Kripke’s ‘paradox of knowledge', which states that knowledge seems to make permissible an intuitively unacceptable form of dogmatism. This paradox of belief is based on an intuitively correct principle of doxastic coherence. My aim is to show that this paradox contributes to elucidating the puzzling nature of belief.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. On Two Paradoxes of Knowledge.Saul Kripke - 2011 - In Saul A. Kripke (ed.), Philosophical Troubles: Collected Papers, Volume 1. , US: Oup Usa. pp. 27-51.
  9.  59
    Knowledge without dogmatism.Earl Conee - 2024 - Philosophical Studies 181 (8):1925-1945.
    Rachel Fraser, Gilbert Harman, Saul Kripke, and Maria Lasonen-Aarnio have offered arguments for paradoxical implications of knowledge. The arguments contend that knowing a proposition justifies believing it dogmatically, or dogmatically maintaining confidence in it, or dogmatically intending to continue to believe it. Yet it is quite doubtful that knowing could justify any sort of dogmatism. The arguments will be assessed. We will see why knowledge does not justify being dogmatic. The reason is essentially that deferring to our evidence is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  39
    Habermas and Dummett: Beyond dogmatism and scepticism.Anat Matar - 2001 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 9 (3):417 – 430.
    In this article I suggest a way of overcoming the traditional dichotomy between analytic and continental philosophy by pointing at some similarities between apparently disparate philosophical approaches, viz. those of Michael Dummett and Jürgen Habermas. The comparison revolves around the so-called 'paradox of analysis', which poses a dilemma concerning philosophical propositions: these are allegedly shown to be either trivial or unsecured. Both Dummett and Habermas offer ways out of the dilemma, through recognition of the intersection of analysis with life. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Perceptual evidence and the new dogmatism.Ram Neta - 2004 - Philosophical Studies 119 (1-2):199-214.
    What is the epistemological value of perceptual experience? In his recently influential paper, “The Skeptic and the Dogmatist”1, James Pryor develops a seemingly plausible answer to this question. Pryor’s answer comprises the following three theses: (F) “Our perceptual justification for beliefs about our surroundings is always defeasible – there are always possible improvements in our epistemic state which would no longer support those beliefs.” (517) (PK) “This justification that you get merely by having an experience as of p can sometimes (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  12. XI—Śrīharṣa on Two Paradoxes of Inquiry.Nilanjan Das - 2023 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 123 (3):275-304.
    In A Confection of Refutation (Khaṇḍanakhaṇḍakhādya), the twelfth-century philosopher and poet Śrīharṣa addresses a version of Meno’s paradox. This version of the paradox was well known in first millennium South Asia through the writings of two earlier Sanskrit philosophers, Śabarasvāmin (4th–5th century ce) and Śaṃkara (8th century ce). Both these thinkers proposed a solution to the paradox. I show how Śrīharṣa rejects this solution, and splits the old paradox into two new ones: the paradox of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. How to Believe Long Conjunctions of Beliefs: Probability, Quasi-Dogmatism and Contextualism.Stefano Bonzio, Gustavo Cevolani & Tommaso Flaminio - 2021 - Erkenntnis 88 (3):965-990.
    According to the so-called Lockean thesis, a rational agent believes a proposition just in case its probability is sufficiently high, i.e., greater than some suitably fixed threshold. The Preface paradox is usually taken to show that the Lockean thesis is untenable, if one also assumes that rational agents should believe the conjunction of their own beliefs: high probability and rational belief are in a sense incompatible. In this paper, we show that this is not the case in general. More (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14. Knowability Relative to Information.Peter Hawke & Franz Berto - 2021 - Mind 130 (517):1-33.
    We present a formal semantics for epistemic logic, capturing the notion of knowability relative to information (KRI). Like Dretske, we move from the platitude that what an agent can know depends on her (empirical) information. We treat operators of the form K_AB (‘B is knowable on the basis of information A’) as variably strict quantifiers over worlds with a topic- or aboutness- preservation constraint. Variable strictness models the non-monotonicity of knowledge acquisition while allowing knowledge to be intrinsically stable. Aboutness-preservation models (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  15.  11
    Philosophy and theology in a burlesque mode: John Toland and "the way of paradox".Daniel Clifford Fouke - 2007 - Amherst, NY: Humanity Books.
    Philosopher Daniel C. Fouke sheds the light of rhetorical analysis on a subversive thinker whose challenges to institutional authority have awakened recent scholarly interest. John Toland was a controversial Irish-born British freethinker, satirist, and critic of traditional Christianity. His work Christianity Not Mysterious, now considered a classic exposition of deism, provoked outrage in its time, but eventually led to a healthy skepticism regarding the historical reliability of the biblical canon. Though little known today, Toland was an acquaintance of Gottfried Wilhelm (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16. Inquiry beyond knowledge.Bob Beddor - 2023 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 109 (1):330-356.
    Why engage in inquiry? According to many philosophers, the goal of inquiring into some question is to come to know its answer. While this view holds considerable appeal, this paper argues that it stands in tension with another highly attractive thesis: knowledge does not require absolute certainty. Forced to choose between these two theses, I argue that we should reject the idea that inquiry aims at knowledge. I go on to develop an alternative view, according to which inquiry aims at (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  17.  36
    Attributing Knowledge: What It Means to Know Something.Jody Azzouni - 2020 - New York, NY, United States of America: Oup Usa.
    In this book Jody Azzouni challenges existing epistemological conventions about knowledge: what it means to know something, who or what is seen as knowing, and how we talk about it. He argues that the classic restrictive conditions philosophers routinely place on knowers only hold in special cases, and suggests that knowledge can be equally attributed to children, sophisticated animals, unsophisticated animals, and machinery or devices. Through this perspective and a close examination of its relation to linguistics and psychology, Azzouni freshly (...)
    No categories
  18. Bifurcated Sceptical Invariantism: Between Gettier Cases and Saving Epistemic Appearances.Christos Kyriacou - 2017 - Journal of Philosophical Research 42:27-44.
    I present an argument for a sophisticated version of sceptical invariantism that has so far gone unnoticed: Bifurcated Sceptical Invariantism (BSI). I argue that it can, on the one hand, (dis)solve the Gettier problem, address the dogmatism paradox and, on the other hand, show some due respect to the Moorean methodological incentive of ‘saving epistemic appearances’. A fortiori, BSI promises to reap some other important explanatory fruit that I go on to adduce (e.g. account for concessive knowledge attributions). (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  19.  57
    Artificial intelligence: Walking the boundary.Anne Foerst - 1996 - Zygon 31 (4):681-693.
    Theology and science generally conduct research independently, with no interchange. The possibility for mutual enrichment often is thwarted because people working in the two fields have very different worldviews, which are mostly held subconsciously. In this paper I will try to establish a dialogue of mutual enrichment. I have chosen artificial intelligence (AI) as an exemplary scientific discipline and the theology of Paul Tillich as a complement. I reinterpret Tillich's concept of sin to introduce a framework for a dialogue between (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  64
    What Do You Do with Misleading Evidence&quest.Michael Veber - 2004 - Philosophical Quarterly 54 (217):557-569.
    Gilbert Harman has presented an argument to the effect that if S knows that p then S knows that any evidence for not-p is misleading. Therefore S is warranted in being dogmatic about anything he happens to know. I explain, and reject, Sorensen's attempt to solve the paradox via Jackson's theory of conditionals. S is not in a position to disregard evidence even when.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  21. Mere faith and entitlement.Yuval Avnur - 2012 - Synthese 189 (2):297-315.
    The scandal to philosophy and human reason, wrote Kant, is that we must take the existence of material objects on mere faith . In contrast, the skeptical paradox that has scandalized recent philosophy is not formulated in terms of faith, but rather in terms of justification, warrant, and entitlement. I argue that most contemporary approaches to the paradox (both dogmatist/liberal and default/conservative) do not address the traditional problem that scandalized Kant, and that the status of having a warrant (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  22.  32
    (1 other version)Common Sense as Evidence: Against Revisionary Ontology and Skepticism.Thomas Kelly - 1981 - In Felicia Ackerman (ed.), Midwest Studies in Philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. pp. 53–78.
    This chapter contains sections titled: I II III References.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23. Problems for contrastive closure: resolved and regained.Michael Hughes - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 163 (3):577-590.
    The standard contextualist solution to the skeptical paradox is intended to provide a way to retain epistemic closure while avoiding the excessive modesty of radical skepticism and the immodesty of Moorean dogmatism. However, contextualism’s opponents charge that its solution suffers from epistemic immodesty comparable to Moorean dogmatism. According to the standard contextualist solution, all contexts where an agent knows some ordinary proposition to be true are contexts where she also knows that the skeptical hypotheses are false. It (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  24.  82
    What do you do with misleading evidence?By Michael Veber - 2004 - Philosophical Quarterly 54 (217):557–569.
    Gilbert Harman has presented an argument to the effect that if S knows that p then S knows that any evidence for not-p is misleading. Therefore S is warranted in being dogmatic about anything he happens to know. I explain, and reject, Sorensen's attempt to solve the paradox via Jackson's theory of conditionals. S is not in a position to disregard evidence even when he knows it to be misleading.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  25. David Miller's Defence of Bartley's Pan Critical Rationalism.Armando Cíntora - 2004 - Sorites 15:50-55.
    W. W. Bartley argued that Popper's original theory of rationality opened itself to a tu quoque argument from the irrationalist and to avoid this Bartley proposed an alternative theory of rationality: pancritical rationalism . Bartley's characterization of PCR leads, however, to self-referential paradox. David Miller outlaws self-reference by distinguishing between positions and statements, Miller's distinction looks, however, suspiciously like an ad hoc manoeuvre or as a stipulation that has to be accepted dogmatically. Furthermore, Miller's move is inadequate because it (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  20
    La religion comme expérience de la valeur.Louis Quéré - 2018 - ThéoRèmes 13 (13).
    This paper considers John Dewey’s philosophy of religion, which it relates to the contemporary debate about the “post-secular”. Dewey’s view is completely secularist, but, at the same time, it appeals to the growth of the religious attitude in experience. The attitude in question has to be liberated from the supernaturalism and dogmatism of the traditional religions. Such a paradoxical religious secularism is based on a naturalist conception of human experience and social life. Having reconstituted Dewey’s view, the paper discusses (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  11
    What Does It Mean to Be an Empiricist in Medicine? Baglivi’s De praxi medica.Raphaële Andrault - 2018 - In Anne-Lise Rey & Siegfried Bodenmann (eds.), What Does It Mean to Be an Empiricist?: Empiricisms in Eighteenth Century Sciences. Cham: Springer Verlag. pp. 169-188.
    How are we to connect the mechanist methodology used by Baglivi in his physiological treatises with the apparently strict empiricism that he promotes in his therapeutic work entitled Practice of Physick, reduc’d to the Ancient Way of Observations? In order to answer this question, we examine the methodological implications of the “history of diseases” that Baglivi promotes by using Bacon’s recommendations in the Novum organum. Then, we compare this result with the place that historians generally gave to Baglivi in the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  15
    Semiotics and Pragmatism: Theoretical Interfaces by Ivo Assad Ibri (review).Robert E. Innis - 2023 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 59 (2):257-261.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Semiotics and Pragmatism: Theoretical Interfaces by Ivo Assad IbriRobert E. InnisIvo Assad Ibri Semiotics and Pragmatism: Theoretical Interfaces Springer, 2022, xxvii + 341 pp., incl. indexIn the chapter on 'The Heuristic Power of Agapism in Peirce's Philosophy' in his recent book, Semiotics and Pragmatism: Theoretical Interfaces, Ivo Ibri points out that access to Peirce's work requires something on the part of the reader that is "not readily available (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  24
    Unternehmerische Verantwortung für Menschenrechte? – Embedding Human Rights in Business Practise.Axel Birk & Wolfram Heger - 2016 - Archiv Für Rechts- Und Sozialphilosphie 102 (1):128-152.
    Embedding Human Rights in business practice is a challenge many multinational companies have to deal with to avoid reputational risks or to comply with soft law requirements. However, in doing so, the normative concept of corporate human rights obligations is both legally and ethically imprecise and the “UN Guiding Principles on Business and Human Rights” are just partly helpful. Therefore, it is asked and analyzed, if legal respectively ethical dogmatism or specific sustainability market mechanisms can provide guidance and clarity. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  29
    Pragmatics of intercultural communication: The bounded openness of a contradictory perspective.Dominique Bouchet - 2010 - Pragmatics and Society 1 (1):138-154.
    This article explains why intercultural communication always should be studied in context and how even though misunderstanding is normally at stake in intercultural communication, one can argue that the promotion of mutual understanding actually is of mutual interest for all of humanity. Studying in context means paying attention to circumstances around the uses of signs as well as to the roles and moods of the users of signs. Promoting mutual understanding means avoiding a state of mind that implies the depreciation (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  2
    The Great Dissent: John Henry Newman and the Liberal Heresy by Robert Pattison.M. Jamie Ferreira - 1993 - The Thomist 57 (2):331-336.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:BOOK REVIEWS 331 The Great Dissent: John Henry Newman and the Liberal Heresy. By ROBERT PATTISON. New York: Oxford University Press, 1991. Pp. xiii +231. $29.95. This extremely provocative and elegantly written study of John Henry Newman's struggle with "liberalism" argues that Newman was a genuine rebel whose solitary voice needs to be heard, as much today as then, but whose project was, in the end, eminently unsuccessful. The (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. A multi-modal, cross-cultural study of the semantics of intellectual humility.Markus Christen, Mark Alfano & Brian Robinson - forthcoming - AI and Society.
    Intellectual humility can be broadly construed as being conscious of the limits of one’s existing knowledge and capable to acquire more knowledge, which makes it a key virtue of the information age. However, the claim “I am (intellectually) humble” seems paradoxical in that someone who has the disposition in question would not typically volunteer it. There is an explanatory gap between the meaning of the sentence and the meaning the speaker ex- presses by uttering it. We therefore suggest analyzing intellectual (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Meillassoux’s Virtual Future.Graham Harman - 2011 - Continent 1 (2):78-91.
    continent. 1.2 (2011): 78-91. This article consists of three parts. First, I will review the major themes of Quentin Meillassoux’s After Finitude . Since some of my readers will have read this book and others not, I will try to strike a balance between clear summary and fresh critique. Second, I discuss an unpublished book by Meillassoux unfamiliar to all readers of this article, except those scant few that may have gone digging in the microfilm archives of the École normale (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34. Supposing Truth is a Woman – What Then?Andrea Hurst - 2007 - South African Journal of Philosophy 26 (1):44-55.
    Nietzsche's analysis of the self-poisoning of ‘the will to power' and his insistence upon overcoming its ideological outcome (the dogmatist's fake ‘Truth') by recognizing the ‘un-truth' of a ‘logic of contamination,' demonstrates that he understands ‘truth' as a paradox. What may one accordingly expect in response to the question ‘Supposing truth is a woman – what then?', posed in the preface to Beyond Good and Evil (1966)? Supported by Derrida's Spurs: Nietzsche's Styles, I argue that Nietzsche could have drawn (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  19
    Justice. [REVIEW]A. R. E. - 1970 - Review of Metaphysics 24 (2):344-344.
    The five chapters in this volume were originally delivered in lecture form at the University of Genoa and have previously appeared in French, German, and English translations. An appendix, "What the Philosopher May Learn from the Study of Law," has also appeared before in English. The book is basically a digest, with some modifications, of Perelman's earlier work Justice et Raison. The chief modification involves a supposed shift away from positivism toward a greater emphasis on the cognitive status of primary (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. What’s the matter with epistemic circularity?David James Barnett - 2014 - Philosophical Studies 171 (2):177-205.
    If the reliability of a source of testimony is open to question, it seems epistemically illegitimate to verify the source’s reliability by appealing to that source’s own testimony. Is this because it is illegitimate to trust a questionable source’s testimony on any matter whatsoever? Or is there a distinctive problem with appealing to the source’s testimony on the matter of that source’s own reliability? After distinguishing between two kinds of epistemically illegitimate circularity—bootstrapping and self-verification—I argue for a qualified version of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  37. O jeho prekonanie (k tzv. Hermeneutizácii fenomenológie) Jozef piaček, katedra marxisticko-leninskej filozofie, ffuk, bratislava piacek, J.: Husserľs transcendental paradox and his attempt to.Husserlov Transcendentálny Paradox A. Pokus - 1982 - Filozofia 37:56.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Jaakko Hintikka.Paradoxes Of Confirmation - 1970 - In Carl G. Hempel, Donald Davidson & Nicholas Rescher (eds.), Essays in honor of Carl G. Hempel. Dordrecht,: D. Reidel. pp. 24.
  39. Contemporary views on the neo-bernoullian theory and the.Allais Paradox - 1977 - In Maurice Allais & Ole Hagen (eds.), Expected Utility Hypotheses and the Allais Paradox. D. Reidel. pp. 21--191.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. 'Non-Uniform Convergence'(joint paper with KG Denbigh).Gibbs Paradox - 1989 - Synthese 81:283-313.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  12
    " To be an object" means" to have properties." Thus, any object has at least one property. A good formalization of this simple conclusion is a thesis of second-order logic:(1) Vx3P (Px) This formalization is based on two assumptions:(a) object variables. [REVIEW]Russell'S. Paradox - 2006 - In J. Jadacki & J. Pasniczek (eds.), The Lvov-Warsaw School: The New Generation. Reidel. pp. 6--129.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  14
    Anstoss fur eine untypische version Des utilitarismus Fabian Fricke.Parfits Paradox der Blossen Hinzufugung - 2002 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 65 (1):175-207.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Rationality'.Lawrence Davis & Paradox Prisoners - 1977 - American Philosophical Quarterly 14.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44. 1. Zeno's Metrical Paradox. The version of Zeno's argument that points to possible trouble in measure theory may be stated as follows: 1. Composition. A line segment is an aggregate of points. 2. Point-length. Each point has length 0. 3. Summation. The sum of a (possibly infinite) collection of 0's is. [REVIEW]Zeno'S. Metrical Paradox Revisited - 1988 - Philosophy of Science 55:58-73.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45. Michael Davis.Some Paradoxes ofWhistleblowing 85 - 2003 - In William H. Shaw (ed.), Ethics at work: basic readings in business ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. A statistical paradox.D. V. Lindley - 1957 - Biometrika 44 (1/2):187-192.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  47.  7
    The Monstrosity of Christ: Paradox or Dialectic?Slavoj ŽI.žek & John Milbank - 2009 - MIT Press.
    A militant Marxist atheist and a "Radical Orthodox" Christian theologiansquare off on everything from the meaning of theology and Christ to the war machine of corporatemafia.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  48. The Paradox of Pain.Adam Bradley - 2021 - Philosophical Quarterly 71 (4):pqaa084.
    Bodily pain strikes many philosophers as deeply paradoxical. The issue is that pains seem to bear both physical characteristics, such as a location in the body, and mental characteristics, such being mind-dependent. In this paper I clarify and address this alleged paradox of pain. I begin by showing how a further assumption, Objectivism, the thesis that what one feels in one’s body when one is in pain is something mind-independent, is necessary for the generation of the paradox. Consequently, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  49. Naive Structure, Contraction and Paradox.Lionel Shapiro - 2015 - Topoi 34 (1):75-87.
    Rejecting structural contraction has been proposed as a strategy for escaping semantic paradoxes. The challenge for its advocates has been to make intuitive sense of how contraction might fail. I offer a way of doing so, based on a “naive” interpretation of the relation between structure and logical vocabulary in a sequent proof system. The naive interpretation of structure motivates the most common way of blaming Curry-style paradoxes on illicit contraction. By contrast, the naive interpretation will not as easily motivate (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  50. Disarming a Paradox of Validity.Hartry Field - 2017 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 58 (1):1-19.
    Any theory of truth must find a way around Curry’s paradox, and there are well-known ways to do so. This paper concerns an apparently analogous paradox, about validity rather than truth, which JC Beall and Julien Murzi call the v-Curry. They argue that there are reasons to want a common solution to it and the standard Curry paradox, and that this rules out the solutions to the latter offered by most “naive truth theorists.” To this end they (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
1 — 50 / 949