Results for 'right way risk'

975 found
Order:
  1.  68
    Rights and Risk.Dennis McKerlie - 1986 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16 (2):239 - 251.
    Robert Nozick has suggested that risky actions are a problem for a moral view based on rights. We ordinarily think that some actions are too dangerous to be permissible, taking into account both the harm risked and the degree of the risk. Other actions, although they run some risk of serious harm, are thought permissible. The problem is to draw this distinction in a principled way by looking to rights.I think that Nozick's argument about risk can be (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  2. Probability, Normalcy, and the Right against Risk Imposition.Martin Smith - 2024 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 27 (3).
    Many philosophers accept that, as well as having a right that others not harm us, we also have a right that others not subject us to a risk of harm. And yet, when we attempt to spell out precisely what this ‘right against risk imposition’ involves, we encounter a series of notorious puzzles. Existing attempts to deal with these puzzles have tended to focus on the nature of rights – but I propose an approach that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  43
    On the Alleged Right to Participate in High‐Risk Research.Joanna Różyńska - 2015 - Bioethics 29 (7):451-461.
    Reigning regulatory frameworks for biomedical research impose on researchers and research ethics committees an obligation to protect research participants from risks that are unnecessary, disproportionate to potential research benefits, and non-minimized. Where the research has no potential to produce results of direct benefit to the subjects and the subjects are unable to give consent, these requirements are strengthened by an additional condition, that risks should not exceed a certain minimal threshold. In this article, I address the question of whether there (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  4.  17
    Contestations in urban mobility: rights, risks, and responsibilities for Urban AI.Nitin Sawhney - 2023 - AI and Society 38 (3):1083-1098.
    Cities today are dynamic urban ecosystems with evolving physical, socio-cultural, and technological infrastructures. Many contestations arise from the effects of inequitable access and intersecting crises currently faced by cities, which may be amplified by the algorithmic and data-centric infrastructures being introduced in urban contexts. In this article, I argue for a critical lens into how inter-related urban technologies, big data and policies, constituted as Urban AI, offer both challenges and opportunities. I examine scenarios of contestations in _urban mobility_, defined broadly (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  7
    Measuring Environmental Health Risks: The Negotiation of a Public Right-to-Know Law.Joshua Dunsby - 2004 - Science, Technology, and Human Values 29 (3):269-290.
    Quantitative health risk assessment is a procedure for estimating the likelihood that exposure to environmental contaminants will produce certain adverse health effects, most commonly cancer. One instance of its use has been a California air toxics public “right-to-know” law. This article examines the ways in which credible health risk measurements were produced and challenged during the implementation of the California public policy. Fieldwork and documentary analysis finds that stakeholders negotiated within the formal constraints of the risk (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  6.  24
    Technology, individual rights and the ethical evaluation of risk.Lanre-Abass Bolatito Asiata - 2010 - Journal of Information, Communication and Ethics in Society 8 (4):308-322.
    PurposeThe purpose of this paper is to examine the risk arising from technological devices, such as closed circuit television and nuclear power plants and the consequent effect on the rights to privacy and security of individuals.Design/methodology/approachThe paper presents critical and conceptual analyses of CCTV, nuclear power plants and the rights of individuals. It also analyses how communitarianism and liberal individualism would respond to right‐infringements and risk‐imposition. It draws on W.D. Ross's prima facie and actual duties to explain (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  44
    “On a supposed right to lie [to the public] from benevolent motives” Communicating health risks to the public.Darren Shickle - 2000 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 3 (3):241-249.
    There are three main categories of rationale for withholding information or telling lies: if overwhelming harm can only be averted through deceit; complete triviality such that it is irrelevant whether the truth is told; a duty to protect the interests of others. Public health authorities are frequently having to form judgements about the public interest, whether to release information or issue warnings. In June 1992, routine surveillance detected patulin levels (a known carcinogen) in samples of apple juice exceeding safety threshold. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  36
    Risk and Luck in Medical Ethics.R. Tong - 2004 - Journal of Medical Ethics 30 (4):423-424.
    In Risk and Luck in Medical Ethics Donna Dickenson explains in brilliant fashion the tension between ethics and luck, be it luck in outcomes of action on the one hand or luck in antecedent circumstances, in the problems that have to be faced, or character on the other. According to Dickenson, most of the philosophical debate so far has focused on how luck in outcomes affects agents’ ability to act as morally responsible people. But Dickenson thinks it is equally (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  96
    Risk, Ignorance, and What We Ought to Do.Danny Frederick - manuscript
    I consider cases in which risk or ignorance create barriers to our discovery of what we ought to do. I argue that neither expected utility theory, nor the maximin principle, nor a timid gambling temperament, is relevant to discovering what we ought to do in one-off or infrequently recurring types of decisions involving risk, or to decisions involving ignorance. I argue, contra Kolodny and MacFarlane, that the miners case does not require us to give up any classical logical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Brain Data in Context: Are New Rights the Way to Mental and Brain Privacy?Daniel Susser & Laura Y. Cabrera - 2023 - American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience 15 (2):122-133.
    The potential to collect brain data more directly, with higher resolution, and in greater amounts has heightened worries about mental and brain privacy. In order to manage the risks to individuals posed by these privacy challenges, some have suggested codifying new privacy rights, including a right to “mental privacy.” In this paper, we consider these arguments and conclude that while neurotechnologies do raise significant privacy concerns, such concerns are—at least for now—no different from those raised by other well-understood data (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  11. probability And Risk Assessment: Taking A Chance On 'terrorism'.James Roper - 2002 - Florida Philosophical Review 2 (2):23-44.
    Beginning with an analysis of the "reluctant gambler problem"—in which the notion of guiding one's life by probability seems to conflict with the preferences of rational people—we draw a distinction between rule and act probabilism. Arguing that humans are rule probabilists by default, we show that reluctant gamblers can be viewed as rule probabilists. If so viewed, their reluctance to gamble is consistent with their rational use of probability judgments to guide their lives.The distinction between rule and act probabilism suggests (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Responsibility and compensation rights.Peter Vallentyne - 2009 - In Stephen De Wijze, Matthew H. Kramer & Ian Carter (eds.), Hillel Steiner and the Anatomy of Justice: Themes and Challenges. New York: Routledge.
    I address an issue that arises for rights theories that recognize rights to compensation for rightsintrusions. Do individuals who never pose any risk of harm to others have a right, against a rightsintruder, to full compensation for any resulting intrusion-harm, or is the right limited in some way by the extent to which the intruder was agent-responsible for the intrusion-harm (e.g., the extent to which the harm was a foreseeable result of her autonomous choices)? Although this general (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  13.  38
    Survey of risks and benefits communication strategies by research nurses.Lika Nusbaum, Brenda Douglas, Neenah Estrella-Luna, Michael Paasche-Orlow & Karla Damus - 2019 - Nursing Ethics 26 (3):937-950.
    Background: An ethical, informed consent process requires that potential participants understand the study, their rights, and the risks and benefits. Yet, despite strategies to improve communication, many participants still lack understanding of potential risks and benefits. Investigating attitudes and practices of research nurses can identify ways to improve the informed consent process. Research question: What are the attitudes, practices, and preparedness of nurses involved in the informed consent process regarding communication of risks and benefits? Research design: A survey was developed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  33
    Health Security and Risk Aversion.Jonathan Herington - 2016 - Bioethics 30 (7):479-489.
    Health security has become a popular way of justifying efforts to control catastrophic threats to public health. Unfortunately, there has been little analysis of the concept of health security, nor the relationship between health security and other potential aims of public health policy. In this paper I develop an account of health security as an aversion to risky policy options. I explore three reasons for thinking risk avoidance is a distinctly worthwhile aim of public health policy: that security is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15.  60
    How we can make sense of control-based intuitions for limited access-conceptions of the right to privacy.Björn Lundgren - 2021 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 20 (3).
    Over the years, several counterexamples arguably establish the limits of control-based conceptions of privacy and the right to privacy. Some of these counterexamples focus only on privacy, while the control-based conception of the right to privacy is rejected because of conceptual consistency between privacy and the right to privacy. Yet, these counterexamples do not deny the intuitions of control-based conceptions of the right to privacy. This raises the question whether conceptual consistency is more important than intuitions (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  12
    The Risks and Benefits of National Stories.Rogers M. Smith - 2022 - Ethics and International Affairs 36 (4):413-425.
    Authoritarian nationalism is on the rise in many countries around the world, threatening liberal democracies. Many on the left rightly fear that any and all celebrations of national identities risk heightening these dangers. It is questionable, however, whether illiberal nationalism can be defeated politically without some reliance on progressive stories of national identity that advance themes of equality, freedom, and inclusion in ways that resonate with many of the traditions in which those whom progressives seek to mobilize have been (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Responsible risking, forethought, and the case of germline gene editing.Madeleine Hayenhjelm - 2023 - In Adriana Placani & Stearns Broadhead (eds.), _Risk and Responsibility in Context_. New York: Routledge. pp. 149-169.
    This chapter addresses a general question: What is responsible risking? It explores the notion of "responsible risking" as a thick moral concept, and it argues that the notion can be given moral content that could be action-guiding and add an important tool to our moral toolbox. To impose risks responsibly, on this view, is to take on responsibility in a good way. A core part of responsible risking, this chapter argues, is some version of a Forethought Condition. Such a condition (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  20
    Farmers’ Rights: Intellectual Property Regimes and the Struggle over Seeds.Craig Borowiak - 2004 - Politics and Society 32 (4):511-543.
    This article analyzes “farmers’ rights” as a strategy of resistance against the perceived inequities of intellectual property rights regimes for plant varieties. As commercial models of intellectual property have made their way into agriculture, farmers’ traditional seed-saving practices have been increasingly delegitimized. In response, farmers have adopted the language of farmers’ rights to demand greater material recognition of their contributions and better measures to protect their autonomy. This campaign has mixed implications. On one hand, farmers’rights are a unique form of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  20
    Stakeholder Perceptions of Risk in Mandatory Corporate Responsibility Disclosure.Lisa Baudot, Zhongwei Huang & Dana Wallace - 2020 - Journal of Business Ethics 172 (1):151-174.
    The extraction of natural resources is a controversial business practice that has profound ethical and economic risk implications for both firms involved in extractive activities and society at large. In response to these implications, the Dodd–Frank Act of 2010 directed the Securities and Exchange Commission to create the first ever rules requiring annual corporate responsibility disclosures. The two proposed rules, requiring disclosure of the source of “conflict minerals” and of payments to foreign governments by extractive firms, conjured intense debate (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  84
    The right to believe truth paradoxes of moral regret for no belief and the role(s) of logic in philosophy of religion.Billy Joe Lucas - 2012 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 72 (2):115-138.
    I offer you some theories of intellectual obligations and rights (virtue Ethics): initially, RBT (a Right to Believe Truth, if something is true it follows one has a right to believe it), and, NDSM (one has no right to believe a contradiction, i.e., No right to commit Doxastic Self-Mutilation). Evidence for both below. Anthropology, Psychology, computer software, Sociology, and the neurosciences prove things about human beliefs, and History, Economics, and comparative law can provide evidence of value (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  18
    Explaining rule of rescue obligations in healthcare allocation: allowing the patient to tell the right kind of story about their life.Sean Sinclair - 2021 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 25 (1):31-46.
    I consider various principles which might explain our intuitive obligation to rescue people from imminent death at great cost, even when the same resources could produce more benefit elsewhere. Our obligation to rescue is commonly explained in terms of the identifiability of the rescuee, but I reject this account. Instead, I offer two considerations which may come into play. Firstly, I explain the seeming importance of identifiability in terms of an intuitive obligation to prioritise life-extending interventions for people who face (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  39
    Natural ways are better: Adolescents and the 'anti-obesity' Gene.Mairi Levitt - 1997 - Science and Engineering Ethics 3 (3):305-315.
    Empirical research with young people in Finland, Germany, Spain and Britain was carried out as part of the BIOCULT project funded by the European Union. The project focused on their attitudes to biotechnology and, in particular, the formation of arguments about risk and safety. This paper looks at the responses of 14–18 year olds to a story about the so called anti-obesity gene, in the form of advice to a friend who is taking it. The majority advised against taking (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  41
    Health and Human Rights: Old Wine in New Bottles?Gerald M. Oppenheimer, Ronald Bayer & James Colgrove - 2002 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 30 (4):522-532.
    It is one of the remarkable and significant consequence of the AIDS epidemic that out of the context of enormous suffering and death there emerged a forceful set of ideas linking the domains of health and human rights. At first, the effort centered on the observation that protecting individuals from discrimination and unwarranted intrusions on liberty were, contrary to previous epidemics, crucial to protecting the public health and interrupting the spread of HIV But in fairly short order, the scope of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  24.  56
    Human rights strategies for corporations.David Rice - 2002 - Business Ethics, the Environment and Responsibility 11 (2):134–136.
    This paper presents BP’s approach to ethical corporate governance. The author suggests that corporate social responsibility is in the interests of both business and the people at large. In this context co‐operation between business, NGOs and activity is the best way to proceed, with each party focusing on their own field of engagement; doing business in a way that respects human rights for the companies, and campaigning and advocacy for the NGOs. Increasing transparency and risks to reputation require business to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. How Procreation Generates Parental Rights and Obligations.Michael Cholbi - 2016 - In Jaime Ahlberg & Michael Cholbi (eds.), Procreation, Parenthood, and Educational Rights: Ethical and Philosophical Issues. Routledge.
    Philosophical defenses of parents’ rights typically appeal to the interests of parents, the interests of children, or some combination of these. Here I propose that at least in the case of biological, non-adoptive parents, these rights have a different normative basis: namely, these rights should be accorded to biological parents because of the compensatory duties such parents owe their children by virtue of having brought them into existence. Inspried by Seana Shiffrin, I argue that procreation inevitably encumbers the wills of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  53
    Rights, duties, liabilities, and hohfeld.Andrew Halpin - 2007 - Legal Theory 13 (1):23-39.
    This article engages with Jaffey's recent contribution on the nature of no-prior-duty remedial obligations. Jaffey's use of a right-liability relation and his challenge to Hohfeld's analytical scheme are rejected as unsound. An alternative model distinguishing three pathways to account for remedial obligations and other legal consequences is proposed. This draws on the Hohfeldian scheme but extends it to permit the full expression of reflexive liabilities, mutually correlative liabilities, and the operation of nonhuman conditions. The proposed approach also recognizes a (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  28
    Right to health and social justice in Bangladesh: ethical dilemmas and obligations of state and non-state actors to ensure health for urban poor.Sohana Shafique, Dipika S. Bhattacharyya, Iqbal Anwar & Alayne Adams - 2018 - BMC Medical Ethics 19 (S1).
    Background The world is urbanizing rapidly; more than half the world’s population now lives in urban areas, leading to significant transition in lifestyles and social behaviours globally. While offering many advantages, urban environments also concentrate health risks and introduce health hazards for the poor. In Bangladesh, although many public policies are directed towards equity and protecting people’s rights, these are not comprehensively and inclusively applied in ways that prioritize the health rights of citizens. The country is thus facing many issues (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  35
    Are There Any Environmental Rights?Aaron Lercher - 2007 - Environmental Values 16 (3):355 - 368.
    This paper extends the argument in H.L.A. Hart's 'Are there any natural rights?' to argue that there is an environmental moral right against pollution. This right is composed of a right against negligent, reckless or intentional risk imposition, together with the liberty to act in a way that does not negligently, recklessly or intentionally impose risks on others. This right is understood as overrideable or prima facie, and this paper does not claim that this (...) is the only basis of moral judgment in the cases it considers. The hypothesis that there is a right against pollution does, however, explain some moral reasoning about pollution that otherwise is difficult to explain. (shrink)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  21
    No right answer: officials need discretion on whether to allow natural immunity exemptions.Dorit Reiss - 2022 - Journal of Medical Ethics 48 (6):380-381.
    In their thoughtful, nuanced and interesting discussion, Jonathan Pugh, Julian Savulescu, Rebecca Brown and Dom Wilkinson argued that officials should recognise proof of prior infection as a valid exemption from vaccination requirements.1 This commentary agrees with parts of their analysis, but argues that the case for the exemption is less clear than the authors suggest, and the better approach is to allow officials flexibility: an exemption for natural immunity may be appropriate or may not. In part, the disagreements may stem (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  14
    States, Citizen Rights and Global Warming.Richard Lachmann - 2016 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 275 (1):15-35.
    How will citizen rights be affected by global warming and related environmental disasters? Citizen rights have been demanded of and conferred by nation states. As a result, the benefits of citizenship remain highly variable across nations. Several schools of scholarship argue that nations states are weakening due to neoliberalism (Harvey), the rise of a world culture (Meyer), or privileged individuals’ ability to shield themselves from risk (Beck, Giddens). This article addresses those claims against the likely consequences of global warming. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  60
    Research participation and the right to withdraw.Sarah J. L. Edwards - 2005 - Bioethics 19 (2):112–130.
    Most ethics committees which review research protocols insist that potential research participants reserve unconditional or absolute ‘right’ of withdrawal at any time and without giving any reason. In this paper, I examine what consent means for research participation and a sense of commitment in relation to this right to withdraw. I suggest that, once consent has been given (and here I am excluding incompetent minors and adults), participants should not necessarily have unconditional or absolute rights to withdraw.This does (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  32.  31
    Balancing professional obligations and risks to providers in learning healthcare systems.Jan Piasecki & Vilius Dranseika - 2021 - Journal of Medical Ethics 47 (6):413-416.
    Clinicians and administrators have a professional obligation to contribute (OTC) to improvement of healthcare quality. At the same time, participation in embedded research poses risks to healthcare institutions. Disclosure of an institution’s sensitive information could endanger relationships with patients and undermine its reputation. The existing ethical framework (EF) for learning healthcare systems (LHSs) does not address the conflict between the OTC and institutional interests. Ethical guidance and policy regulation are needed to create a safe environment for embedded research. In this (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  33.  11
    The right to choose: A comparative analysis of patient autonomy and body integrity dysphoria among Czech healthcare professionals.Leandro Loriga - 2024 - Ethics and Bioethics (in Central Europe) 14 (1-2):41-60.
    The bioethical principle of autonomy is of paramount importance within medical practice. The extent to which a patient’s autonomy overlaps or conflicts with the physician’s duty of beneficence and non-maleficence, however, is not so clear cut, especially for those cases in which the patient’s request for medical intervention goes against the physician’s advice, either because of personal belief or because there is uncertainty regarding the therapeutic approach. Body integrity dysphoria (BID) is a condition that has been included recently in the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  47
    Public policy and environmental risk: Political theory, human agency, and the imprisoned rider.John Martin Gillroy - 1992 - Environmental Ethics 14 (3):217-237.
    In this essay, I argue that environmental risk is a strategic situation that places the individual citizen in the position of an imprisoned rider who is being exploited without his or her knowledge by the preferences of others. I contend that what is at stake in policy decisions regarding environmental risk is not numerical probabilities or consistent, complete, transitive preferences for individual welfare, but rather respect for the human agency of the individual. Human agency is a prerequisite to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  50
    Justice and third party risk: The ethics of xenotransplantation.Jonathan Hughes - 2007 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 24 (2):151–168.
    The question of when it is permissible to inflict risks on others without their consent is one that we all face in our everyday lives, but which is often brought to our attention in contexts of technological innovation and scientific uncertainty. Xenotransplantation, the transplantation of organs or tissues from animals to humans, has the potential to save or improve the lives of many patients but gives rise to the possibility of infectious agents being transferred from donor animals into the human (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  20
    Autonomy requires more curiosity less deference to risk.Johnna Wellesley & Emma Tumilty - 2023 - Journal of Medical Ethics 49 (11):749-750.
    In ‘Patients, doctors and risk attitudes,’ Makins argues for ‘straightforwardly’ (Makins1 p1) extending antipaternalistic views about medical decision-making to include deferential considerations of risk attitudes that a patient might endorse. Reflecting on Makins’ important contribution to higher order attitudes in decision theory, we seek to clarify the practical applicability of his argument to specific clinical settings, namely in mental health. We argue that considering low and higher order risk preferences are not only practically difficult, but also potentially (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  16
    Narratives of Choice: Marriage, Choosing Right and the Responsibility of Agency in Urban Middle-Class Sri Lanka.Asha L. Abeyasekera - 2016 - Feminist Review 113 (1):1-16.
    The shift to companionate marriage in South Asia and elsewhere is widely read as a move from ‘tradition’ to ‘modernity’ resulting in an expansion of individual agency, especially for women. This paper critically examines the narratives of urban middle-class women in Sri Lanka spanning three generations to illustrate that rather than indicating a radical shift in the way they negotiated between individual desires and social norms, the emphasis on ‘choice’ signals a shift in the narrative devices used in the presentation (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Response to Umbers: An Instability of the Duty and Right to Vote.Ten-Herng Lai - 2020 - Res Publica 26 (2):275-280.
    Lachlan Umbers defends democracy against Jason’s Brennan’s competence objection, by showing that voting even incompetently does not violate the rights of others, as the risk imposed is negligible, and furthermore lower than other permissible actions, e.g. driving. I show there are costs in taking this line of argument. Accepting it would make arguing for the duty to vote more difficult in two ways: since voting incompetently is permissible, and not voting imposes less risk than not voting, then not (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  51
    Rights, Capabilities, and the Good Society.Robin West - unknown
    In Part I this essay explores and then criticizes the two major arguments behind the conventional wisdom that rights undermine efforts to secure a state role in ensuring the material preconditions for a good society, and therefore, the material preconditions for the development of those human capabilities essential to a fully human life. I conclude in this part that this understanding of rights is mistaken. In Part II, I urge that the pragmatic argument put forward by rights critics and some (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. On Personal Responsibility and the Human Right to Healthcare.Yvonne Denier - 2005 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 14 (2):224-234.
    Does a human right to healthcare imply individual obligations to healthy behavior? Or put another way: Is a self-induced condition a relevant criterion for some sort of restriction of this right—like withholding or modifying treatment in circumstances where choices have to be made? For instance, should a drunk driver bear the costs of medical care that he needs after a car accident he has caused? Should there be a difference in healthcare entitlements between the smoker with a heart (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  41. In harm's way: AMA physicians and the duty to treat.Chalmers C. Clark - 2005 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 30 (1):65 – 87.
    In June 2001, the American Medical Association (AMA) issued a revised and expanded version of the Principles of Medical Ethics (last published in 1980). In light of the new and more comprehensive document, the present essay is geared to consideration of a longstanding tension between physician's autonomy rights and societal obligations in the AMA Code. In particular, it will be argued that a duty to treat overrides AMA autonomy rights in social emergencies, even in cases that involve personal risk (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  42.  16
    Decision-making about non-invasive prenatal testing: women’s moral reasoning in the absence of a risk of miscarriage in Germany.Stefan Reinsch, Anika König & Christoph Rehmann-Sutter - 2021 - New Genetics and Society 40 (2):199-215.
    This paper examines women’s experiences with decision-making about non-invasive prenatal testing (NIPT). Such tests offer knowledge about chromosomal disorders early in pregnancy, without the risk of miscarriage associated with invasive procedures such as amniocentesis. Based on qualitative interviews with women in Germany who used, or declined, NIPT, we show how some women, who would not consider amniocentesis due to the risk of miscarriage, welcome the knowledge provided by, and the additional agency resulting from, NIPT. For others, declining the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  16
    Saving Human Lives and Rights: Recommendations for Protecting Human Rights When Adopting COVID-19 Vaccine Passports.Emmie Hine, Jessica Morley, Mariarosaria Taddeo & Luciano Floridi - 2023 - In Francesca Mazzi (ed.), The 2022 Yearbook of the Digital Governance Research Group. Springer Nature Switzerland. pp. 117-130.
    The SARS-CoV-2 (COVID-19) pandemic has caused social and economic devastation. As the milestone of two years of ‘living with the virus’ approaches, governments and businesses are attempting to develop means of reopening society whilst still protecting public health. However, developing interventions – particularly technological interventions – that find a safe, socially acceptable, and ethically justifiable balance between these two seemingly opposing demands is extremely challenging. There is no one right solution, but the current most popular ‘solution’ is the so-called (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  28
    Between Civil Libertarianism and Executive Unilateralism: An Institutional Process Approach to Rights during Wartime.Richard H. Pildes & Samuel Issacharoff - 2004 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 5 (1):1-45.
    Times of heightened risk to the physical safety of their citizens inevitably cause democracies to recalibrate their institutions and processes and to reinterpret existing legal norms, with greater emphasis on security, and less on individual liberty, than in "normal" times. This article explores the ways in which the American courts have responded to the tension between civil liberties and national security in times of crises. This history illustrates that courts have rejected both of the two polar positions that characterize (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  31
    Should Animals Have Political Rights?Per-Anders Svärd - 2022 - Journal of Animal Ethics 12 (2):210-212.
    A common view of politics is that it is reducible to applied ethics. If politics, in a classic phrase, is about “who gets what, when, and how,” then the task of normative political theory would simply be to tell us who is morally entitled to get whatever the “what” is in that statement.This view, however, can easily reduce politics to a dizzying vortex of actions to assess from an ethical perspective. And while the task of moral philosophy may be precisely (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  21
    1945–1964 WHO’s Right to Health?Linda M. Richards - 2022 - NTM Zeitschrift für Geschichte der Wissenschaften, Technik und Medizin 30 (2):137-165.
    United States Atomic Energy Commission (USAEC) and UN agencies utilized techniques of power and negotiation to implement radiation exposure regulations. USAEC affiliated scientists’ expertise was cultivated while establishing a radiation protection regime based on classified experiments. World Health Organization (WHO) leadership sought to manifest a human right to health, including a right to protection from radiation contamination. The careers of a few technical experts and interagency UN correspondence shows how American risk models of radiation regulation traveled and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  93
    Understanding disability civil rights non-categorically: The Minority Body and the Americans with disabilities act.Leslie Francis - 2018 - Philosophical Studies 175 (5):1135-1149.
    A persistent paradox apparently infects disability civil rights claims. On the one hand, these rights claims are often understood to apply only to those who are sufficiently impaired in body or in mind to qualify for them because of the disadvantage they endure. On the other hand, asserting significant impairments threatens to undermine the plausibility of these claims as civil rights rather than as welfare for those who are dependent and in need of extra help. Behind this paradox lies a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  48.  89
    The sharing of risks and the risks of sharing: Solidarity and social justice in the welfare state. [REVIEW]Kees Schuyt - 1998 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 1 (3):297-311.
    Solidarity as a social phenomenon means a sharing of feelings, interests, risks and responsibilities. The Western-European Welfare State can be seen as an organized system of solidarity, historically grown from group solidarity among workers, later between workers and employers, moving towards solidarity between larger social groups: between healthy people and the sick, between the young and the elderly, between the employed and the unemployed. This sharing of risks at a societal level however, has revealed the risks of sharing. In the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  49.  40
    "Men of Feminine Courage": Thomas Hobbes and Life as a Right.Renato Janine Ribeiro - 2011 - Hobbes Studies 24 (1):44-61.
    In this article we examine the true scope of the right Hobbes recognizes, even for the subjects of a State, to life. We hold that the right to live includes the subject's right not to accept to be deprived not only of life but also of limb; a right not to have to kill; a right not to accept to be imprisoned. The sovereign of course has a right to kill, mutilate and arrest but (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  65
    Contrastive Evidence and Inductive Risk.Jaakko Kuorikoski - 2024 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 75 (1):61-76.
    I argue that non-epistemic values are necessarily embedded in the measure of evidential strength of contrastive evidence. When evidence is contrastive, evidence is stronger the more it favours a hypothesis over a set of plausible, mutually exclusive alternative hypotheses. In such a contrastive epistemic setting, evidence has an effect not only on a particular hypothesis, but on the whole probability distribution over the set of alternative hypotheses. A natural way of analysing the incremental impact of new evidence on a set (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 975