Results for 'preference probability'

959 found
Order:
  1.  27
    Preference probability between gambles as a step function of event probability.R. Duncan Luce & Elizabeth F. Shipley - 1962 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 63 (1):42.
  2.  53
    Why do we prefer probabilities relative to many data?J. Hosiasson - 1931 - Mind 40 (157):23-36.
  3.  98
    Subjective Probability Weighting and the Discovered Preference Hypothesis.Gijs van de Kuilen - 2009 - Theory and Decision 67 (1):1-22.
    Numerous studies have convincingly shown that prospect theory can better describe risky choice behavior than the classical expected utility model because it makes the plausible assumption that risk aversion is driven not only by the degree of sensitivity toward outcomes, but also by the degree of sensitivity toward probabilities. This article presents the results of an experiment aimed at testing whether agents become more sensitive toward probabilities over time when they repeatedly face similar decisions, receive feedback on the consequences of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  36
    High-probabilities, model-preference and default arguments.Hector Geffner - 1992 - Minds and Machines 2 (1):51-70.
    In this paper we analyze two recent conditional interpretations of defaults, one based on probabilities, and the other, on models. We study what makes them equivalent, explore their limitations and develop suitable extensions. The resulting framework ties together a number of important notions in default reasoning, like high-probabilities and model-preference, default priorities and argument systems, and independence assumptions and minimality considerations.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  5. Incomplete Preference and Indeterminate Comparative Probabilities.Yang Liu - 2022 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 73 (3):795-810.
    The notion of comparative probability defined in Bayesian subjectivist theory stems from an intuitive idea that, for a given pair of events, one event may be considered “more probable” than the other. Yet it is conceivable that there are cases where it is indeterminate as to which event is more probable, due to, e.g., lack of robust statistical information. We take that these cases involve indeterminate comparative probabilities. This paper provides a Savage-style decision-theoretic foundation for indeterminate comparative probabilities.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  20
    Right-response preference in probability learning and reversal.Marilyn E. Miller - 1966 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 71 (5):776.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Axiomatization of a Preference for Most Probable Winner.Pavlo R. Blavatskyy - 2006 - Theory and Decision 60 (1):17-33.
    In binary choice between discrete outcome lotteries, an individual may prefer lottery L1 to lottery L2 when the probability that L1 delivers a better outcome than L2 is higher than the probability that L2 delivers a better outcome than L1. Such a preference can be rationalized by three standard axioms (solvability, convexity and symmetry) and one less standard axiom (a fanning-in). A preference for the most probable winner can be represented by a skew-symmetric bilinear utility function. (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8.  16
    Subjective Probability Weighting and the Discovered Preference Hypothesis.Gijs Kuilen - 2009 - Theory and Decision 67 (1):1-22.
    Numerous studies have convincingly shown that prospect theory can better describe risky choice behavior than the classical expected utility model because it makes the plausible assumption that risk aversion is driven not only by the degree of sensitivity toward outcomes, but also by the degree of sensitivity toward probabilities. This article presents the results of an experiment aimed at testing whether agents become more sensitive toward probabilities over time when they repeatedly face similar decisions, receive feedback on the consequences of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  41
    Perspectives, preferences, and probabilities.D. E. Over & K. I. Manktelow - 1995 - Thinking and Reasoning 1 (4):364 – 371.
  10. Reasoning about outcome probabilities and values in preference reversals.Marcus Selart, Ole Boe & Tommy Garling - 1999 - Thinking and Reasoning 5 (2):175 – 188.
    Research on preference reversals has demonstrated a disproportionate influence of outcome probability on choices between monetary gambles. The aim was to investigate the hypothesis that this is a prominence effect originally demonstrated for riskless choice. Another aim was to test the structure compatibility hypothesis as an explanation of the effect. The hypothesis implies that probability should be the prominent attribute when compared with value attributes both in a choice and a preference rating procedure. In Experiment 1, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  11.  17
    Condorcet efficiency of the preference approval voting and the probability of selecting the Condorcet loser.Eric Kamwa - 2019 - Theory and Decision 87 (3):299-320.
    Under approval voting, each voter just distinguishes the candidates he approves of from those appearing as unacceptable. The preference approval voting is a hybrid version of the approval voting first introduced by Brams and Sanver The mathematics of preference, choice and order. Springer, Berlin, pp 215–237, 2009). Under PAV, each voter ranks all the candidates and then indicates the ones he approves. In this paper, we provide an analytical representation of the limiting probability that PAV elects the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Chisholm, Keim, Preferability and Probability.Nicholas Lapara - 1975 - Ratio (Misc.) 17 (1):82.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  63
    The preferability of probable beliefs.Frederick L. Will - 1965 - Journal of Philosophy 62 (3):57-67.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14. Beyond risk preferences in sequential decision-making: How probability representation, sequential structure and choice perseverance bias optimal search.Christiane Baumann, René Schlegelmilch & Bettina von Helversen - 2025 - Cognition 254 (C):106001.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  9
    Value and Probability in Theories of Preference.John M. Vickers - 1995 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 76 (2):168-182.
  16.  8
    Probability in the Sciences.Evandro Agazzi - 2011 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    Probability has become one of the most characteristic con cepts of modern culture, and a 'probabilistic way of thinking' may be said to have penetrated almost every sector of our in tellectual life. However it would be difficult to determine an explicit list of 'positive' features, to be proposed as identifica tion marks of this way of thinking. One would rather say that it is characterized by certain 'negative' features, i. e. by certain at titudes which appear to be (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  40
    Choice among equal expected value alternatives: Sequential effects of winning probability level on risk preferences.Louis Miller, David E. Meyer & John T. Lanzetta - 1969 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 79 (3p1):419.
  18.  48
    The Axioms of Subjective Probability.Peter C. Fishburn - 1986 - Statistical Science 1 (3):335-358.
  19.  33
    Components of risk in decision making: Probability and variance preferences.C. H. Coombs & D. G. Pruitt - 1960 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 60 (5):265.
  20.  41
    Inconsistent preferences among gambles.Harold R. Lindman - 1971 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 89 (2):390.
  21. Objective probabilities and subjective risks.В. С Диев - 2024 - Siberian Journal of Philosophy 22 (1):5-15.
    The article shows, using elementary examples, that risk assessment depends both on the probability of future events and on their results. Various approaches to the integration of probabilities and numerical estimates of possible outcomes are shown and analyzed. The subjective nature of risk is substantiated. An interdisciplinary definition of risk is proposed, not associated with any science or group of sciences. The definition is based on the idea that risk is a consequence of decisions made by the subject, who (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  33
    Risk preferences of Australian academics: where retirement funds are invested tells the story.Pavlo R. Blavatskyy - 2016 - Theory and Decision 80 (3):411-426.
    Risk preferences of Australian academics are elicited by analyzing the aggregate distribution of their retirement funds across available investment options. Not more than 10 % of retirement funds are invested as if their owners maximize expected utility under the assumption of constant relative risk aversion with an empirically plausible level of risk aversion. An implausibly high level of risk aversion is required to rationalize any investment into bonds when stocks are available. Not more than 36.54 % of all investments can (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  83
    Probability in Relativistic Bohmian Mechanics of Particles and Strings.Hrvoje Nikolić - 2008 - Foundations of Physics 38 (9):869-881.
    Even though the Bohmian trajectories given by integral curves of the conserved Klein-Gordon current may involve motions backwards in time, the natural relativistic probability density of particle positions is well-defined. The Bohmian theory predicts subtle deviations from the statistical predictions of more conventional formulations of quantum theory, but it seems that no present experiment rules this theory out. The generalization to the case of many particles or strings is straightforward, provided that a preferred foliation of spacetime is given.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24.  55
    Indeterminate Preferences.Martin Peterson - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 130 (2):297-320.
    It is commonly assumed that preferences are determinate; that is, that an agent who has a preference knows that she has the preference in question and is disposed to act upon it. This paper argues the dubiousness of that assumption. An account of indeterminate preferences in terms of self-predicting subjective probabilities is given, and a decision rule for choices involving indeterminate preferences is proposed. Wolfgang Spohn’s and Isaac Levi ’s arguments against self-predicting probabilities are also considered, in light (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  25.  41
    The effects of probability ambiguity on preferences for uncertain two-outcome prospects.Mark F. Stasson, William G. Hawkes, H. David Smith & Walter M. Lakey - 1993 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 31 (6):624-626.
  26. Sets of probability distributions, independence, and convexity.Fabio G. Cozman - 2012 - Synthese 186 (2):577-600.
    This paper analyzes concepts of independence and assumptions of convexity in the theory of sets of probability distributions. The starting point is Kyburg and Pittarelli’s discussion of “convex Bayesianism” (in particular their proposals concerning E-admissibility, independence, and convexity). The paper offers an organized review of the literature on independence for sets of probability distributions; new results on graphoid properties and on the justification of “strong independence” (using exchangeability) are presented. Finally, the connection between Kyburg and Pittarelli’s results and (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  27.  23
    Visual and motor components of an experimentally induced position preference in multiple probability learning.Stanford H. Simon - 1966 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 71 (3):469.
  28. Probability Out Of Determinism.Michael Strevens - 2011 - In Claus Beisbart & Stephan Hartmann (eds.), Probabilities in Physics. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press. pp. 339--364.
    This paper offers a metaphysics of physical probability in (or if you prefer, truth conditions for probabilistic claims about) deterministic systems based on an approach to the explanation of probabilistic patterns in deterministic systems called the method of arbitrary functions. Much of the appeal of the method is its promise to provide an account of physical probability on which probability assignments have the ability to support counterfactuals about frequencies. It is argued that the eponymous arbitrary functions are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  29. Adaptive Preferences and the Hellenistic Insight.Hugh Breakey - 2010 - Australian Journal of Professional and Applied Ethics 12 (1):29-39.
    Adaptive preferences are preferences formed in response to circumstances and opportunities – paradigmatically, they occur when we scale back our desires so they accord with what is probable or at least possible. While few commentators are willing to wholly reject the normative significance of such preferences, adaptive preferences have nevertheless attracted substantial criticism in recent political theory. The groundbreaking analysis of Jon Elster charged that such preferences are not autonomous, and several other commentators have since followed Elster’s lead. On a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30. Preference for equivalent random variables: A price for unbounded utilities.Teddy Seidenfeld, Mark J. Schervish & Joseph B. Kadane - 2009 - Journal of Mathematical Economics 45:329-340.
    When real-valued utilities for outcomes are bounded, or when all variables are simple, it is consistent with expected utility to have preferences defined over probability distributions or lotteries. That is, under such circumstances two variables with a common probability distribution over outcomes – equivalent variables – occupy the same place in a preference ordering. However, if strict preference respects uniform, strict dominance in outcomes between variables, and if indifference between two variables entails indifference between their difference (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  31.  45
    Statistical models for the induction and use of selectional preferences.Marc Light & Warren Greiff - 2002 - Cognitive Science 26 (3):269-281.
    Selectional preferences have a long history in both generative and computational linguistics. However, since the publication of Resnik's dissertation in 1993, a new approach has surfaced in the computational linguistics community. This new line of research combines knowledge represented in a pre‐defined semantic class hierarchy with statistical tools including information theory, statistical modeling, and Bayesian inference. These tools are used to learn selectional preferences from examples in a corpus. Instead of simple sets of semantic classes, selectional preferences are viewed as (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  32.  48
    Luck, Knowledge, and Epistemic Probability.Gregory Stoutenburg - 2020 - Logos and Episteme 11 (1):97-109.
    Epistemic probability theories of luck come in two versions. They are easiest to distinguish by the epistemic property they claim eliminates luck. One view says that the property is knowledge. The other view says that the property is being guaranteed by a subject’s evidence. Asbjørn Steglich-Petersen defends the Knowledge Account (KA). He has recently argued that his view is preferable to my Epistemic Analysis of Luck (EAL), which defines luck in terms of evidential probability. In this paper, I (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  38
    Preferences Representable by a Lower Expectation: Some Characterizations. [REVIEW]Andrea Capotorti, Giulianella Coletti & Barbara Vantaggi - 2008 - Theory and Decision 64 (2-3):119-146.
    We propose two different characterizations for preference relations representable by lower (upper) expectations with the aim of removing either fair price or completeness requirements. Moreover, we give an explicit characterization for comparative degrees of belief on a finite algebra of events representable by lower probabilities.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Probability in GRW theory.Roman Frigg & Carl Hoefer - 2007 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 38 (2):371-389.
    GRW Theory postulates a stochastic mechanism assuring that every so often the wave function of a quantum system is `hit', which leaves it in a localised state. How are we to interpret the probabilities built into this mechanism? GRW theory is a firmly realist proposal and it is therefore clear that these probabilities are objective probabilities (i.e. chances). A discussion of the major theories of chance leads us to the conclusion that GRW probabilities can be understood only as either single (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  35. Social Preference Under Twofold Uncertainty.Philippe Mongin & Marcus Pivato - 2016 - Economic Theory.
    We investigate the conflict between the ex ante and ex post criteria of social welfare in a new framework of individual and social decisions, which distinguishes between two sources of uncertainty, here interpreted as an objective and a subjective source respectively. This framework makes it possible to endow the individuals and society not only with ex ante and ex post preferences, as is usually done, but also with interim preferences of two kinds, and correspondingly, to introduce interim forms of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  36. From Classical to Intuitionistic Probability.Brian Weatherson - 2003 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 44 (2):111-123.
    We generalize the Kolmogorov axioms for probability calculus to obtain conditions defining, for any given logic, a class of probability functions relative to that logic, coinciding with the standard probability functions in the special case of classical logic but allowing consideration of other classes of "essentially Kolmogorovian" probability functions relative to other logics. We take a broad view of the Bayesian approach as dictating inter alia that from the perspective of a given logic, rational degrees of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  37.  18
    Phonotactically probable word shapes represent attractors in the cultural evolution of sound patterns.Nikolaus Ritt & Theresa Matzinger - 2022 - Cognitive Linguistics 33 (2):415-446.
    Words are processed more easily when they have canonical phonotactic shapes, i.e., shapes that are frequent both in the lexicon and in usage. We explore whether this cognitively grounded constraint or preference implies testable predictions about the implementation of sound change. Specifically, we hypothesise that words with canonical shapes favour, or ‘select for’, sound changes that produce words with the same shapes. To test this, we investigate a Middle English sound change known as Open Syllable Lengthening. OSL lengthened vowels (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  79
    Revealed Preference and Expected Utility.Stephen A. Clark - 2000 - Theory and Decision 49 (2):159-174.
    This essay gives necessary and sufficient conditions for recovering expected utility from choice behavior in several popular models of uncertainty. In particular, these techniques handle a finite state model; a model for which the choice space consists of probability densities and the expected utility representation requires bounded, measurable utility; and a model for which the choice space consists of Borel probability measures and the expected utility representation requires bounded, continuous utility. The key result is the identification of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  95
    Preferences over consumption and status.Alexander Vostroknutov - 2013 - Theory and Decision 74 (4):509-537.
    Experimental evidence suggests that individual consumption has not only personal value but also enters the social part of the utility. Existing models of social preferences make ad hoc parametric assumptions about the nature of this duality. This creates a problem of experimental identification of preferences since without such assumptions it is impossible to distinguish whether consumption or social concerns are driving the behavior. Given observed choice, the Axiomatic model of preferences in this article makes it possible to unambiguously determine personal (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  32
    Dinsmoor's selective observing hypothesis probably cannot account for a preference for unpredictable rewards: DMOD can.Helen B. Daly - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):365-367.
  41. (1 other version)Measurement outcomes and probability in Everettian quantum mechanics.David J. Baker - 2007 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 38 (1):153-169.
    The decision-theoretic account of probability in the Everett or many-worlds interpretation, advanced by David Deutsch and David Wallace, is shown to be circular. Talk of probability in Everett presumes the existence of a preferred basis to identify measurement outcomes for the probabilities to range over. But the existence of a preferred basis can only be established by the process of decoherence, which is itself probabilistic.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  42. Conceptual fallacies in subjective probability.Roger M. Cooke - 1986 - Topoi 5 (1):21-27.
    Subjective probability considered as a logic of partial belief succumbs to three fundamental fallacies. These concern the representation of preference via expectation, the measurability of partial belief, and the normalization of belief.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43. Better Foundations for Subjective Probability.Sven Neth - forthcoming - Australasian Journal of Philosophy.
    How do we ascribe subjective probability? In decision theory, this question is often addressed by representation theorems, going back to Ramsey (1926), which tell us how to define or measure subjective probability by observable preferences. However, standard representation theorems make strong rationality assumptions, in particular expected utility maximization. How do we ascribe subjective probability to agents which do not satisfy these strong rationality assumptions? I present a representation theorem with weak rationality assumptions which can be used to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  38
    Weighted sets of probabilities and minimax weighted expected regret: a new approach for representing uncertainty and making decisions.Joseph Y. Halpern & Samantha Leung - 2015 - Theory and Decision 79 (3):415-450.
    We consider a setting where a decision maker’s uncertainty is represented by a set of probability measures, rather than a single measure. Measure-by-measure updating of such a set of measures upon acquiring new information is well known to suffer from problems. To deal with these problems, we propose using weighted sets of probabilities: a representation where each measure is associated with a weight, which denotes its significance. We describe a natural approach to updating in such a situation and a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45. On the preference for more specific reference classes.Paul D. Thorn - 2017 - Synthese 194 (6):2025-2051.
    In attempting to form rational personal probabilities by direct inference, it is usually assumed that one should prefer frequency information concerning more specific reference classes. While the preceding assumption is intuitively plausible, little energy has been expended in explaining why it should be accepted. In the present article, I address this omission by showing that, among the principled policies that may be used in setting one’s personal probabilities, the policy of making direct inferences with a preference for frequency information (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  46. Exploiting Cyclic Preference.Arif Ahmed - 2017 - Mind 126 (504):975-1022.
    Probably many people have cyclic preferences: they prefer A to B, B to C and C to A for some objects of choice A, B and C. Recent work has resurrected the objection to cyclic preference that agents possessing them are open to exploitation by means of ‘money pumps’. The paper briefly reviews this work and proposes a general approach to problems of sequential choice that makes cyclic preference immune to exploitation by means of these new mechanisms.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  47. probability And Risk Assessment: Taking A Chance On 'terrorism'.James Roper - 2002 - Florida Philosophical Review 2 (2):23-44.
    Beginning with an analysis of the "reluctant gambler problem"—in which the notion of guiding one's life by probability seems to conflict with the preferences of rational people—we draw a distinction between rule and act probabilism. Arguing that humans are rule probabilists by default, we show that reluctant gamblers can be viewed as rule probabilists. If so viewed, their reluctance to gamble is consistent with their rational use of probability judgments to guide their lives.The distinction between rule and act (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  52
    Probability Zero in Bohm’s Theory.Meir Hemmo & Orly Shenker - 2013 - Philosophy of Science 80 (5):1148-1158.
    We describe two anomalies in Bohm’s quantum theory that shed light on the notion of probability zero in quantum mechanics. In one anomaly the preferred reference frame may be discovered.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49. On the appropriate and inappropriate uses of probability distributions in climate projections and some alternatives.Joel Katzav, Erica L. Thompson, James Risbey, David A. Stainforth, Seamus Bradley & Mathias Frisch - 2021 - Climatic Change 169 (15).
    When do probability distribution functions (PDFs) about future climate misrepresent uncertainty? How can we recognise when such misrepresentation occurs and thus avoid it in reasoning about or communicating our uncertainty? And when we should not use a PDF, what should we do instead? In this paper we address these three questions. We start by providing a classification of types of uncertainty and using this classification to illustrate when PDFs misrepresent our uncertainty in a way that may adversely affect decisions. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  50.  48
    Using imprecise probabilities to address the questions of inference and decision in randomized clinical trials.Lyle C. Gurrin, Peter D. Sly & Paul R. Burton - 2002 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 8 (2):255-268.
    Randomized controlled clinical trials play an important role in the development of new medical therapies. There is, however, an ethical issue surrounding the use of randomized treatment allocation when the patient is suffering from a life threatening condition and requires immediate treatment. Such patients can only benefit from the treatment they actually receive and not from the alternative therapy, even if it ultimately proves to be superior. We discuss a novel new way to analyse data from such clinical trials based (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 959