Results for 'Natural Goodness'

974 found
Order:
  1. Natural goodness, rightness, and the intersubjectivity of reason: Reply to Arroyo, Cummiskey, Moland, and Bird-pollan.Christine M. Korsgaard - 2011 - Metaphilosophy 42 (4):381-394.
    Abstract: In response to Arroyo, I explain my position on the concept of “natural goodness” and how my use of that concept compares to that of Geach and Foot. An Aristotelian or functional notion of goodness provides the material for Kantian endorsement in a theory of value that avoids a metaphysical commitment to intrinsic values. In response to Cummiskey, I review reasons for thinking Kantianism and consequentialism incompatible, especially those objections to aggregation that arise from the notion (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  2.  25
    ‘Normal’, ‘natural’, ‘good’ or ‘good‐enough’ birth: examining the concepts.Susanne Darra - 2009 - Nursing Inquiry 16 (4):297-305.
    In the face of increasing intervention in childbirth, ‘normal birth’ is currently being promoted by the World Health Organization, national governments, professional bodies and other organisations throughout the world. This paper takes a postmodernist stance and explores the idea of the ‘normal’ before going on to analyse normal childbirth, referring to concepts of the normal and the natural. It refers to historical developments in childbearing and lay organisations along with research relating to women’s views of childbirth, to question the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  25
    Nature-of-science literacy in benchmarks and standards: Post-modern/relativist or modern/realist?Ron Good & James Shymansky - 2001 - Science & Education 10 (1-2):173-185.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  4. Natural goodness without natural history.Parisa Moosavi - 2020 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research:78-100.
    Neo‐Aristotelian ethical naturalism purports to show that moral evaluation of human action and character is an evaluation of natural goodness—a kind of evaluation that applies to living things in virtue of their nature and based on their form of life. The standard neo‐Aristotelian view defines natural goodness by way of generic statements describing the natural history, or the ‘characteristic’ life, of a species. In this paper, I argue that this conception of natural goodness (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  5. Natural Goodness, Sex, and the Perverted Faculty Argument.Christopher Arroyo - 2021 - Philosophy 97 (1):115-142.
    There is a longstanding and widely held view, often associated with Catholicism, that intrinsically nonprocreative human sex acts are intrinsically immoral. Some philosophers who hold this view, such as Edward Feser, claim that they can defend the view on purely philosophical grounds by relying on the perverted faculty argument. This paper argues that Feser's defense of the perverted faculty argument does not work because Feser fails to recognize the full implications of the species-dependence of natural goodness. By drawing (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6. (1 other version)Natural Goodness.Philippa Foot - 2001 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 64 (3):604-606.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   381 citations  
  7.  38
    Natural Goodness and the Normativity Challenge: Happiness Across Cultures.Sebastian Purcell - 2013 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 87:183-194.
    The present essay aims to respond to one of the most recent empirical challenges posed to an Aristotelian based virtue ethics. In the course of the debate concerning the existence of character traits a second and more recent challenge has emerged, which Jesse Prinz has called The Normativity Challenge. The argument in this case is that the empirical study of happiness undertaken by psychologists, sociologists and anthropologists, reveals that the end which virtues are supposed to support, namely happiness, is so (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8. Natural goodness and natural evil.Joseph Millum - 2006 - Ratio 19 (2):199–213.
    In Natural Goodness Philippa Foot gives an analysis of the concepts we use to describe the characteristics of living things. She suggests that we describe them in functional terms, and this allows us to judge organisms as good or defective depending on how well they perform their distinctive functions. Foot claims that we can judge intentional human actions in the same way: the virtues contribute in obvious ways to good human functioning, and this provides us with grounds for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  9.  46
    Natural Goodness[REVIEW]Jennifer Welchman - 2003 - Review of Metaphysics 56 (4):874-875.
    Natural Goodness is an important new book from Phillippa Foot, a central figure in the revival of ethical naturalism and character-based ethics. A longstanding critic of the emotivist and prescriptivist theories that arose following twentieth-century analytic philosophy’s linguistic turn, Foot attacked reigning versions of noncognitivism according to which moral language and judgment made no meaningful claims about moral agents or their actions but were instead misleading expressions of a speaker’s attitudes. In classic papers such as “Moral Beliefs,” “Virtues (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. The natural goodness of humanity.Joshua Cohen - 1997 - In Andrews Reath, Barbara Herman & Christine M. Korsgaard (eds.), Reclaiming the History of Ethics: Essays for John Rawls. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 102--39.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  11. Natural goodness.Philippa Foot - 2001 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Philippa Foot has for many years been one of the most distinctive and influential thinkers in moral philosophy. Long dissatisfied with the moral theories of her contemporaries, she has gradually evolved a theory of her own that is radically opposed not only to emotivism and prescriptivism but also to the whole subjectivist, anti-naturalist movement deriving from David Hume. Dissatisfied with both Kantian and utilitarian ethics, she claims to have isolated a special form of evaluation that predicates goodness and defect (...)
  12. Is Nature Good? A Conversation.John Dewey - 1908 - Hibbert Journal 7:827.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  2
    Nature, Every Last Drop, is Good.Alan Holland & British Association of Nature Conservationists - 1996 - Department of Philosophy, Lancaster University.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  17
    Natural goodness and the political form of human life.Jan Müller - 2015 - Filozofija I Društvo 26 (3):565-592.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  67
    Moral Reasoning as Naturally Good: A Qualified Defense of Foot's Conception of Practical Rationality.Steven Hendley - 2015 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 53 (4):427-449.
    Philippa Foot 's version of ethical naturalism, centered on the idea of “natural goodness,” has received a good deal of critical scrutiny. One pervasive criticism contends that less than virtuous modes of conduct may be described as naturally good or, at least, not naturally defective on her account. If true, this contradicts the most ambitious aspect of Foot 's naturalistic approach to ethics: to show that judgments of moral goodness are a subclass of judgments of natural (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  25
    The natural goodness of man: On the system of Rousseau's thought.Susan M. Shell - 1994 - History of European Ideas 18 (4):623-624.
  17.  14
    The Predictive Value of the NEO-FFI Items: Parsing the Nature of Social Anhedonia Using the Revised Social Anhedonia Scale and the ACIPS.Diane C. Gooding, Emily R. Padrutt & Madeline J. Pflum - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  66
    Natural Goods in the Eudemian Ethics.Giulia Bonasio - 2021 - Ancient Philosophy 41 (1):123-142.
  19.  24
    Philippa Foot’s ‘Natural Goodness’.Patrick Gorevan - 2008 - Maynooth Philosophical Papers 5:9-15.
    Philippa Foot, with the help of her friend and colleague Elizabeth Anscombe, discovered that Summa Theologiae, II-II of Thomas Aquinas was a powerful resource in seeking objectivism in ethics. Foot’s aim was to produce an ethics of natural goodness, in which moral evil, for example, came to be seen as a ‘natural defect’ rather than the expression of a taste or preference. This brought her to develop a concrete ethics of virtue with a broad sweep, dealing with (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  45
    The natural goodness of man: on the system of Rousseau's thought.Arthur M. Melzer - 1990 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    The true key to all the perplexities of the human condition, Rousseau boldly claims, is the “natural goodness of man.” It is also the key to his own notoriously contradictory writings, which, he insists, are actually the disassembled parts of a rigorous philosophical system rooted in that fundamental principle. What if this problematic claim—so often repeated, but as often dismissed—were resolutely followed and explored? Arthur M. Melzer adopts this approach in The Natural Goodness of Man. The (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  21.  44
    "Natural Goodness" di Philippa Foot. Discussione.Piergiorgio Donatelli, Mario Ricciardi & Michael Thompson - 2003 - Iride: Filosofia e Discussione Pubblica 16 (1):179-200.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  8
    Experiment and the Making of Meaning: Human Agency in Scientific Observation and Experiment.D. C. Gooding - 1994 - Springer.
    ... the topic of 'meaning' is the one topic discussed in philosophy in which there is literally nothing but 'theory' - literally nothing that can be labelled or even ridiculed as the 'common sense view'. Putnam, 'The Meaning of Meaning' This book explores some truths behind the truism that experimentation is a hallmark of scientific activity. Scientists' descriptions of nature result from two sorts of encounter: they interact with each other and with nature. Philosophy of science has, by and large, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  23. Nothing in ethics makes sense except in the light of evolution? Natural goodness, normativity, and naturalism.Jay Odenbaugh - 2017 - Synthese 194 (4):1031-1055.
    Foot , Hursthouse , and Thompson , along with other philosophers, have argued for a metaethical position, the natural goodness approach, that claims moral judgments are, or are on a par with, teleological claims made in the biological sciences. Specifically, an organism’s flourishing is characterized by how well they function as specified by the species to which they belong. In this essay, I first sketch the Neo-Aristotelian natural goodness approach. Second, I argue that critics who claim (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  24. Why be a good Human Being? Natural Goodness, Reason, and the Authority of Human Nature.Micah Lott - 2014 - Philosophia 42 (3):761-777.
    The central claim of Aristotelian naturalism is that moral goodness is a kind of species-specific natural goodness. Aristotelian naturalism has recently enjoyed a resurgence in the work of philosophers such as Philippa Foot, Rosalind Hursthouse, and Michael Thompson. However, any view that takes moral goodness to be a type of natural goodness faces a challenge: Granting that moral goodness is natural goodness for human beings, why should we care about being good (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  25.  30
    The discovery of natural goods: Newton's vocation as an ‘experimental philosopher’.Michael Ben-Chaim - 2001 - British Journal for the History of Science 34 (4):395-416.
    While the study of Newton's religious views has been continuously expanding, it has not been brought to bear directly on Newton's career as an ‘experimental philosopher’. Historical perspectives on his optical experiments in particular affirm the historiographic separation between the religious and scientific aspects of his work. In this paper I examine the practical implication of Newton's theology of dominion on his early experiments on light and colours. While his predecessors had made experiments to collect evidence, I show that Newton (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26. From Biological Functions to Natural Goodness.Parisa Moosavi - 2019 - Philosophers' Imprint 19.
    Neo-Aristotelian ethical naturalism aims to place moral virtue in the natural world by showing that moral goodness is an instance of natural goodness—a kind of goodness supposedly also found in the biological realm of plants and non-human animals. One of the central issues facing neo-Aristotelian naturalists concerns their commitment to a kind of function ascription based on the concept of the flourishing of an organism that seems to have no place in modern biology. In this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  27.  37
    General Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture. Edited by Barry Barnes and Steven Shapin. London and Beverly Hills: Sage, 1979. pp. 225. £10.00/£4.25. [REVIEW]David Gooding - 1981 - British Journal for the History of Science 14 (1):84-86.
  28.  38
    The Uses of Experiment: Studies in the Natural Sciences.David Gooding, Trevor Pinch & Simon Schaffer - 1989 - Cambridge University Press. Edited by David Gooding, Trevor Pinch & Simon Schaffer.
    Contributors; Preface; Introduction; Part I. Instruments in Experiments: 1. Scientific instruments: models of brass and aids to discovery; 2. Glass works: Newton’s prisms and the uses of experiment; 3. A viol of water or a wedge of glass; Part II. Experiment and Argument: 4. Galileo’s experimental discourse; 5. Fresnel, Poisson and the white spot: the role of successful predictions in the acceptance of scientific theories; 6. The rhetoric of experiment; Part III. Representing and Realising: 7. ’Magnetic curves’ and the magnetic (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  29. (1 other version)Three degrees of natural goodness.Michael Thompson - manuscript
    Philippa Foot’s Natural Goodness is among the most beautiful and moving works of moral philosophy yet produced in the analytic tradition. It is so much an integral whole that it will seem barbaric to do as I propose briefly to do, and put it to the scalpel. But Natural Goodness propounds a complex theory with many levels or strata, some of which even the author fails completely to distinguish. I will distinguish three strata, each depending logically (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  30.  18
    Introduction: From Natural Goodness to Morality.John Hacker-Wright - 2018 - In Philippa Foot on Goodness and Virtue. Springer Verlag. pp. 1-23.
    This introductory chapter will frame the volume by discussing Foot’s work on goodness in terms of her approach to morality. It is often assumed that Foot’s approach to morality is that of a virtue ethicist in the contemporary sense of this view. Yet Foot distances herself from such approaches. Morality, for Foot, is closely associated with a system of moral norms adopted by a society. These codes do not follow straightforwardly from reflection on the virtues. There are norms for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Species Concepts and Natural Goodness.Judith K. Crane & Ronald Sandler - 2011 - In Joseph Keim Campbell, Michael O'Rourke & Matthew H. Slater (eds.), Carving nature at its joints: natural kinds in metaphysics and science. Cambridge, MA, USA: MIT Press. pp. 289.
    This chapter defends a pluralist understanding of species on which a normative species concept is viable and can support natural goodness evaluations. The central question here is thus: Since organisms are to be evaluated as members of their species, how does a proper understanding of species affect the feasibility of natural goodness evaluations? Philippa Foot has argued for a form of natural goodness evaluation in which living things are evaluated by how well fitted they (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  32.  60
    (2 other versions)How do Scientists Reach Agreement about Novel Observations?David Gooding - 1986 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 17 (2):205.
    I outline a pragmatic view of scientists' use of observation which draws attention to non-discursive, instrumental and social contexts of observation, in order to explain scientists' agreement about the appearance and significance of new phenomena. I argue that: observation is embedded in a network of activities, techniques, and interests; that experimentalists make construals of new phenomena which enable them communicate exploratory techniques and their outcomes, and that empirical enquiry consists of communicative, exploratory and predictive strategies whose interdependence ensures that, notwithstanding (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  33. "All in Their Nature Good": Descartes on the Passions of the Soul.Marie Jayasekera - 2020 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 58 (1):71-92.
    Descartes claims that the passions of the soul are “all in their nature good” even though they exaggerate the value of their objects, have the potential to deceive us, and often mislead us. What, then, can he mean by this? In this paper, I argue that these effects of the passions are only problematic when we incorrectly take their goodness to consist in their informing us of harms and benefits to the mind-body composite. Instead, the passions are good in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  34.  37
    St. Thomas Aquinas on Impairment, Natural Goods, and Human Flourishing.John Berkman & Robyn Boeré - 2020 - The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 20 (2):311-328.
    This essay examines St. Thomas Aquinas’s views on different types of impairment. Aquinas situates physical and moral impairments in a teleological account of the human species, and these impairments are made relative in light of our ultimate flourishing in God. For Aquinas, moral and spiritual impairments are of primary significance. Drawing on Philippa Foot’s account of natural goods, we describe what constitutes an impairment for Aquinas. In the Thomistic sense, an impairment is a lack or privation in relation to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  38
    Images of Anarchy: The Rhetoric and Science in Hobbes’s State of Nature, written by Evrigenis, Ioannis.Nicholas Gooding - 2015 - Hobbes Studies 28 (2):175-183.
  36.  48
    Review: Nature in american philosophy. [REVIEW]James Good - 2008 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 44 (3):pp. 541-547.
    Although he had intermittently toiled over his translation of Hegel's Science of Logic for nearly half a century without finding a publisher, Henry Conrad Brokmeyer, the petulant visionary of St. Louis Hegelian fame, concluded it was naive to expect an infant nation to devote itself to philosophical reflection while it was "carving civilization out of wilderness." Brokmeyer's difficulties may have had more to do with his disdain for the grammatical and spelling conventions of the English language than he cared to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  54
    Theory and observation: The experimental nexus.David Gooding - 1990 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 4 (2):131 – 148.
    Abstract Philosophical discussions of experiment usually focus exclusively on testing predictions. In this paper I compare G. Morpurgo's experimental test of the Gell?Mann/ Zweig quark hypothesis with two neglected uses of experiment: constructing representations of new phenomena and inventing the instruments that produce such phenomena. These roles are illustrated by J. B. Biot's 1821 observations of electromagnetism and by Michael Faraday's invention of the first electromagnetic motor, also in 1821. The comparison identifies similarities between observation and experiment, showing how both (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  20
    Xie, Xiaodong 謝曉東, Human Nature, Good Government, and Justice: On Pre-Qin Confucianism and Classical Liberalism 人性、優良政府與正義——政治哲學視角下的先秦儒學與古典自由主義研究: Beijing 北京: Zhongguo Shehui Kexue Chubanshe 中國社會科學出版社, 2019, 256 pages.Huilan Zhu - 2020 - Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 19 (2):327-330.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  92
    Philippa foot, natural goodness (book review).Neal Weiner - 2002 - Journal of Value Inquiry 36 (4):567-572.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  2
    Fine and the Pragmatist Tradition.Philip Good - 2024 - European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 16 (1).
    This paper examines the relationship between Arthur Fine’s “Natural Ontological Attitude” and the work of neo-pragmatists, particularly Hilary Putnam and Richard Rorty. I argue that many of the problems that face Fine’s account can be seen as a direct result of his failure to employ certain key pragmatist insights concerning the nature and status of the realism-antirealism issue. Consequently, I suggest that we should cease to think of Fine as representative of mainstream attempts to dispense with the realism-antirealism issue (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  15
    Experiment.David C. Gooding - 2000 - In W. Newton-Smith (ed.), A companion to the philosophy of science. Malden, Mass.: Blackwell. pp. 117–126.
    There have been many images of experiment. The contemplative narratives of Aristotle served to illustrate hypotheses and arguments. There was no expectation that they be performed. Even in Galileo's dialogues, the distinction between real experiments and imaginary ones is not sharp (see galileo). During the seventeenth century, performance and public description became essential to the probative power of experiment. These made its methods and procedures transparent, allowing any reader of the narrative to be a virtual witness of an active demonstration (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42. Natural goodness and abandoning the economy of value: Ron Sandler's character and environment.Allen Thompson - 2008 - Ethics, Place and Environment 11 (2):218-226.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  29
    Human Nature as a Source of Moral Normativity: Reflections on the Naturalist Approach in P. Foot’s Work Natural Goodness.Michal Chabada - 2023 - Philosophisches Jahrbuch 130 (1):46-60.
    This article considers aspects of Philippa Foot’s theory of naturalist realist metaethics. It addresses the question of whether human nature can function as a direct source of normativity or whether it is more of a metanormative framework that is open to norm-creation based on the agent’s rational volitional activity. This gives rise to the question of whether the source of moral normativity is not in fact the agent’s practical rationality since natural facts may conflict and therefore cannot constitute a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  63
    Nothing in Ethics Makes Sense Except in the Light of Evolution? Natural Goodness and Evolutionary Biology.Jay Odenbaugh - unknown
    Philippa Foot and Rosalind Hursthouse, along with other philosophers, have argued for a metaethical position, the natural goodness approach, that claims moral evaluations are, or are on a par with, teleological claims made in the biological sciences. Specifically, an organism’s flourishing is characterized by how well they function as specified by the species to which they belong. In this essay, I first sketch the Neo-Aristotelian natural goodness approach. Second, I argue that critics who claim that this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  41
    The Moral Good and the Natural Good in Kant's Ethics.John R. Silber - 1982 - Review of Metaphysics 36 (2):397 - 437.
    THE heterogeneity of the good--its division into the moral good, as virtue, and the natural good, as happiness--is central to Kant's philosophy. In order to clarify and sustain this division, Kant was compelled to specify the valuational characteristics of each kind of good and their relation to one another. But in trying to analyze the good in its heterogeneity Kant faced a terminological difficulty. He could no longer speak simply of "the good" without speaking ambiguously. To avoid this ambiguity (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Natural Goods and Moral Beauty.Stephen Clark - 1993 - Philosophical Quarterly.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  21
    Rousseau's God: theology, religion, and the natural goodness of man.John T. Scott - 2023 - London: University of Chicago Press.
    Rousseau's God offers a comprehensive interpretation of Rousseau's theological and religious writings, both in themselves and in relation to his philosophy of the natural goodness of man. John T. Scott argues that there is a complicated relationship between Rousseau's philosophy, on the one hand, and his theological and religious thought. This relationship revolves around two oppositions: first, between the attributes and psychological needs of natural man and social or moral man; second, between the criteria of truth and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. FOOT, P.-Natural Goodness.S. Kirchin - 2003 - Philosophical Books 44 (2):179-180.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Arthur M. Melzer, The Natural Goodness of Man: On the System of Rousseau's Thought Reviewed by.Howard R. Cell - 1991 - Philosophy in Review 11 (3):212-214.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  34
    Metaphysics versus measurement: The conversion and conservation of force in Faraday's physics.David Gooding - 1980 - Annals of Science 37 (1):1-29.
    SummaryFaraday's concept of force is described by six assumptions. These specify a concept that is quite distinct from ‘mechanical’ conceptions of his contemporaries and interpreters. Analysis of the role of these assumptions clarifies Faraday's weighting of experimental evidence and shows how closely-linked Faraday's chemistry and physics were to his theology. It is argued that Faraday was unable to secularize his concept of force by breaking the ties between his physics and his theology of nature. Examination of his basic assumptions also (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
1 — 50 / 974