Results for 'Keith Nainby'

959 found
Order:
  1.  28
    Engagement Beyond Interruption: A Performative Perspective on Listening and Ethics.Chris McRae & Keith Nainby - 2015 - Educational Studies: A Jrnl of the American Educ. Studies Assoc 51 (2):168-184.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Proper names and identifying descriptions.Keith S. Donnellan - 1970 - Synthese 21 (3-4):335 - 358.
  3. Is classical mechanics really time-reversible and deterministic?Keith Hutchison - 1993 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44 (2):307-323.
  4.  40
    Perceptions and representations: the theoretical bases of brain research and psychology.Keith Oatley - 1978 - London: Methuen.
    problems in psychology The three themes of this book are the relation of the brain's structure to psychological function, the problem of how people perceive ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  5.  40
    The IRB paradox: Could the protectors also encourage deceit?Patricia Keith-Spiegel & Gerald P. Koocher - 2005 - Ethics and Behavior 15 (4):339 – 349.
    The efforts of some institutional review boards (IRBs) to exercise what is viewed as appropriate oversight may contribute to deceit on the part of investigators who feel unjustly treated. An organizational justice paradigm provides a useful context for exploring why certain IRB behaviors may lead investigators to believe that they have not received fair treatment. These feelings may, in turn, lead to intentional deception by investigators that IRBs will rarely detect. Paradoxically, excessive protective zeal by IRBs may actually encourage misconduct (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  6. Why Not Scepticism?Keith Lehrer - 1971 - Philosophical Forum 2 (3):283.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  7.  58
    Thomas Reid.Keith Lehrer - 1989 - New York: Routledge.
    This book is available either individually, or as part of the specially-priced Arguments of the Philosphers Collection.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  8. 'Can' in theory and practice: A possible worlds analysis.Keith Lehrer - 1976 - In M. Brand & Douglas Walton (eds.), Action Theory. Reidel. pp. 241-270.
  9.  8
    (1 other version)Body and mind.Keith Campbell - 1970 - Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press.
    Concerned with the nature of the human body, the nature of the human mind, and how the body and mind interact. This investigation into what is, then, the nature of man himself is one of the most crucial philosophical questions and is preliminary to the broader investigations of logic, metaphysics and epistemology.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  10. Induction, reason and consistency.Keith Lehrer - 1970 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 21 (1):103-114.
  11. Is Kuhn a sociologist?Keith Jones - 1986 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37 (4):443-452.
  12. Perceptual constancy and apparent properties.Keith Allen - 2018 - In Fiona Macpherson & Fabian Dorsch (eds.), Phenomenal Presence. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
  13.  36
    Rational theology and the creativity of God.Keith Ward - 1982 - Oxford: Blackwell.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  14. The Impact of Perceived Control on the Imagination of Better and Worse Possible Worlds.Keith Markman, Igor Gavanski, Steven Sherman & Matthew McMullen - 1995 - Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 21 (6):588-595.
    Effects of perceived control and close alternative outcomes were examined. Subjects played a computer-simulated "wheel-of-fortune" game with another player in which two wheels spun simultaneously. Subjects had either control over spinning the wheel or control over which wheel would determine their outcome and which would determine the other player's outcome. Results showed that (a) subjects generated counterfactuals about the aspect of the game that they controlled, (b) the direction of these counterfactuals corresponded to the close outcome associated with the aspect (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  15.  19
    Sosa, Safety, Sensitivity, and Skeptical Hypotheses.Keith DeRose - 2004 - In John Greco (ed.), Ernest Sosa: And His Critics. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 22–41.
    This chapter contains section titled: Sensitivity Accounts — Direct and Indirect The Attack by Counterexample on Sensitivity Accounts — And Why SCA Seems on the Right Track Nonetheless Sosa's Safety Account Sosa's Account as a Sensitivity Account — and His Counterexamples Safety and the Problem of True/True Subjunctives Other Formulations of Safety Safety and Strength of Epistemic Position Contextualist Solutions to Skepticism Intuitive Complexity: Do We Know that We're Not Brains in Vats?
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  16.  66
    Causal effects and counterfactual conditionals: contrasting Rubin, Lewis and Pearl.Keith A. Markus - 2021 - Economics and Philosophy 37 (3):441-461.
    Rubin and Pearl offered approaches to causal effect estimation and Lewis and Pearl offered theories of counterfactual conditionals. Arguments offered by Pearl and his collaborators support a weak form of equivalence such that notation from the rival theory can be re-purposed to express Pearl’s theory in a way that is equivalent to Pearl’s theory expressed in its native notation. Nonetheless, the many fundamental differences between the theories rule out any stronger form of equivalence. A renewed emphasis on comparative research can (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17.  44
    Beta-testing the ethics plugin.Keith Begley - 2023 - AI and Society 38:1503–1505.
    The three main kinds of theory in normative ethics, namely, consequentialism, deontology, and virtue ethics, are often presented as the ‘palette’ from which we may choose, or use as a starting point for an investigation. However, this way of doing ethics and philosophy, by the palette, may be leading some of us astray. It has led some to believe that all that there is to ethics, and to ethics of AI, is given in terms of these already devised petrified categories (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18. Integrating text and pictorial information: eye movements when looking at print advertisements.Keith Rayner, Caren M. Rotello, Andrew J. Stewart, Jessica Keir & Susan A. Duffy - 2001 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied 7 (3):219.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  19.  44
    (1 other version)RepliesSelf-Trust: A Study of Reason, Knowledge and Autonomy.Keith Lehrer - 1999 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (4):1065.
  20. Does Property-Perception Entail the Content View?Keith A. Wilson - 2024 - Erkenntnis 89:841–860.
    Visual perception is widely taken to present properties such as redness, roundness, and so on. This in turn might be thought to give rise to accuracy conditions for experience, and so content, regardless of which metaphysical view of perception one endorses. An influential version of this argument—Susanna Siegel’s ’Argument from Appearing’—aims to establish the existence of content as common ground between representational and relational views of perception. This goes against proponents of ‘austere’ relationalism who deny that content plays a substantive (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  26
    Conceptual confusion in the chemistry curriculum: exemplifying the problematic nature of representing chemical concepts as target knowledge.Keith S. Taber - 2019 - Foundations of Chemistry 22 (2):309-334.
    This paper considers the nature of a curriculum as presented in formal curriculum documents, and the inherent difficulties of representing formal disciplinary knowledge in a prescription for teaching and learning. The general points are illustrated by examining aspects of a specific example, taken from the chemistry subject content included in the science programmes of study that are part of the National Curriculum in England. In particular, it is suggested that some statements in the official curriculum document are problematic if we (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  34
    Coherence, justification, and Chisholm.Keith Lehrer - 1988 - Philosophical Perspectives 2:125-138.
  23. Affective Impact of Close Counterfactuals: Implications of Possible Futures for Possible Pasts.Keith Markman & Matthew McMullen - 2002 - Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 38:64-70.
    Three studies examined the motivational implications of thinking about how things could have been worse. It was hypothesized that when these downward counterfactuals yield negative affect, through consideration of the possibility of a negative outcome, motivation to change and improve would be increased (the wake-up call). When downward counterfactuals yield positive affect, through diminishing the impact of a potentially negative outcome, motivation to change and improve should be reduced (the Pangloss effect). Results from three studies supported these hypotheses. Studies 1 (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24.  16
    Naturalism in the Continental Tradition.Keith Ansell Pearson & John Protevi - 2015 - In Kelly James Clark (ed.), The Blackwell Companion to Naturalism. Hoboken: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 34–48.
    We begin by treating the antinaturalism of Edmund Husserl's phenomenology, and follow that by considering the recent project of “naturalizing phenomenology.” As a transitional figure, we treat Hans Jonas and the weakly emergent status he allows organismic life. In a section on “affirmative naturalism,” we treat Friedrich Nietzsche, Henri Bergson, and Gilles Deleuze, emphasizing their relation to Spinoza's ethics of joy. We conclude by considering the antinaturalism of continental philosophy positions in critical race theory (Linda Alcoff), gender theory (Judith Butler), (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25.  10
    The development of Kant's view of ethics.Keith Ward (ed.) - 1972 - New York,: Humanities Press.
  26.  64
    Reid on Primary and Secondary Qualities.Keith Lehrer - 1978 - The Monist 61 (2):184-191.
    Reid defends the distinction between primary and secondary qualities. He does so in spite of accepting Berkeley’s critique of Locke on this issue and rejecting the Cartesian thesis that the distinction is based on reason. Reid contends that we have a clear, direct, and distinct conception of primary qualities but not of secondary qualities. We shall attempt to explain how Reid could defend the distinction while rejecting the resemblance theory of Locke and the rationalistic theory of Descartes.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  27.  23
    Role of Imagination and Anticipation in the Acceptance of Computability Proofs: A Challenge to the Standard Account of Rigor.Keith Weber - 2022 - Philosophia Mathematica 30 (3):343-368.
    In a 2022 paper, Hamami claimed that the orthodox view in mathematics is that a proof is rigorous if it can be translated into a derivation. Hamami then developed a descriptive account that explains how mathematicians check proofs for rigor in this sense and how they develop the capacity to do so. By exploring introductory texts in computability theory, we demonstrate that Hamami’s descriptive account does not accord with actual mathematical practice with respect to computability theory. We argue instead for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  22
    Truth is what the context makes of it.Keith Allan - 2022 - Claridades. Revista de Filosofía 14 (2):15-33.
    This essay shows that truth cannot be divorced from human experience and an individual’s world view, his or her weltanschauung. There exist different weltanschauungen that favour alternative truths. Thus, loosely speaking, truth is determined by context. It may be socially acceptable to prefer one among the alternative truths as truly true, but this goal necessarily involves taking an ideological perspective on what is perceived and accepted as the sole truth. In other words, it is prejudiced. The truth value assigned to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29. Depression, Control, and Counterfactual Thinking: Functional for Whom?Keith Markman & Audrey Miller - 2006 - Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology 25 (2):210-227.
    The present study examined relationships among counterfactual thinking, perceived control, and depressive symptoms. Undergraduate participants, grouped according to nondepressed, mild–to–moderately depressed, and severely depressed symptom categories, described potentially repeatable negative academic events and then made upward counterfactuals about those events. Whereas participants endorsing mild–to–moderate depressive symptom levels generated more counterfactuals about controllable than uncontrollable aspects of the events they described, participants endorsing severe levels of depressive symptoms generated counterfactuals that were less controllable, less reasonable, and more characterological in nature. Furthermore, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30. Knowledge reconsidered.Keith Lehrer - 1989 - In Marjorie Clay & Keith Lehrer (eds.), Knowledge and skepticism. Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  31.  46
    The evident object of inquiry.Keith K. Niall - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):578-578.
  32.  57
    The experience of emotions in everyday life.Keith Oatley & Elaine Duncan - 1994 - Cognition and Emotion 8 (4):369-381.
  33.  95
    Social Information.Keith Lehrer - 1977 - The Monist 60 (4):473-487.
    There are those philosophers and historians of science who claim that the acceptance and rejection of scientific theories is underdetermined by experimental results. They conclude that there is no rational method for deciding such matters solely on the basis of empirical information. The acceptance and rejection of scientific theories depends on social influence and is settled by social dominance. This I call the dominance thesis. There are also those who hold, on the contrary, that the acceptance and rejection of theories (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  34.  16
    Motivated Reasoning and Partisan Epistemology: A Reply to van Doorn.Keith Harris - forthcoming - Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  39
    Two Movements in Emotions: Communication and Reflection.Keith Oatley - 2010 - Emotion Review 2 (1):29-35.
    In understanding the degree of choice we have in our emotions, we benefit from the Stoics’ analysis into first and second movements: appraisals and reappraisals. The Stoics were concerned to avoid the harm that emotions can cause, but their idea of working on goals, rather than on emotions as such, generalizes beyond their concerns. For modern people, the problem of taking responsibility for our emotional life becomes less paradoxical when we consider interpersonal issues.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  36.  16
    Consensus and comparison: a theory of social rationality.Keith Lehrer - 1978 - In A. Hooker, J. J. Leach & E. F. McClennen (eds.), Foundations and Applications of Decision Theory: Vol.II: Epistemic and Social Applications. D. Reidel. pp. 283--309.
  37.  60
    Intransitive indifference: The semi-order problem.Keith Lehrer & Carl Wagner - 1985 - Synthese 65 (2):249 - 256.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  38.  31
    Neuropsychological vulnerability or episode factors in schizophrenia?Keith H. Nuechterlein & Michael Foster Green - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):37-38.
  39. Nietzsche on the passions and self-cultivation: contra the Stoics and Spinoza.Keith Ansell-Pearson - 2021 - Continental Philosophy Review 55 (3):245-265.
    Although the literature on Nietzsche is now voluminous one area where there has surprisingly been very little research concerns Nietzsche on the passions. This essay aims to correct this neglect. My focus is on illuminating Nietzsche on the passions in relation to his primary teaching on self-cultivation. To illuminate his position, I focus attention on examining his relation to Stoic teaching on the passions. If for Nietzsche the Christian mind-set involves a disturbing pathological excess of feeling, the Stoic way of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  44
    Bergson's encounter with biology.Keith Ansell Pearson - 2005 - Angelaki 10 (2):59 – 72.
    The status of life in nature is the modern problem of philosophy and of science. A.N. Whitehead, Modes of Thought, 1938.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  41.  38
    Loving sinners to death.Keith Green - 2010 - Journal of Value Inquiry 44 (4):509-519.
  42. A teacher's guide to philosophy for children.Keith J. Topping - 2019 - New York, NY: Routledge. Edited by Steven Trickey & Paul Cleghorn.
    Philosophy for Children (P4C) provides educators with the process and structures to engage children in inquiring as a group into 'big' moral, ethical, and spiritual questions, while also considering curricular necessities and the demands of national and local standards. Based on the actual experiences of educators in diverse and global classroom contexts, this comprehensive guide gives you the tools you need to introduce philosophical thinking into your classroom, curriculum and beyond. Drawing on research-based educational and psychological models, this book highlights (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  42
    Why history?: ethics and postmodernity.Keith Jenkins - 1999 - New York: Routledge.
    Why History? is a compelling introduction to the issue of history and ethics. Designed to provoke discussion, the book asks whether and why a good knowledge and understanding of the past is desirable. In the context of current postmodern thinking, Keith Jenkins suggests that the goal of "learning lessons from the past" actually means learning lessons from stories written by historians and others. If the past as history has no foundation, can anything ethical be gained from history? Daring and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44. Stimulating Creativity in Groups through Mental Simulation.Keith Markman, Elaine Wong, Laura Kray & Adam Galinsky - 2009 - In E. A. Mannix (ed.), Creativity in Groups (Research on Managing Groups and Teams, Vol. 12). Emerald Group Publishing. pp. 111-134.
    A growing literature has recognized the importance of mental simulation (e.g., imagining alternatives to reality) in sparking creativity. In this chapter, we examine how counterfactual thinking, or imagining alternatives to past outcomes, affects group creativity. We explore these effects by articulating a model that considers the influence of counterfactual thinking on both the cognitive and social processes known to impact group creative performance. With this framework, we aim to stimulate research on group creativity from a counterfactual perspective.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  35
    No way to start a space program: Associationism as a launch pad for analogical reasoning.Keith J. Holyoak & John E. Hummel - 2008 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (4):388-389.
    Humans, including preschool children, exhibit role-based relational reasoning, of which analogical reasoning is a canonical example. The connectionist model proposed in the target article is only capable of conditional paired-associate learning.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  13
    Steve Edwards 1957–2020.Keith Cash & Janet Holt - 2020 - Nursing Philosophy 21 (3):e12316.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  38
    Coherence, consensus and language.Keith Lehrer - 1984 - Linguistics and Philosophy 7 (1):43 - 55.
  48. The Influence of Chronic Control Concerns on Counterfactual Thought.Keith Markman & Gifford Weary - 1996 - Social Cognition 14 (4):292-316.
    The present study investigated relationships between counterfactual thinking, control motivation, and depression. Mildly depressed and nondepressed participants described negative life events that might happen again (repeatable event condition) or probably will not happen again (nonrepeatable event condition) and then made upward counterfactuals about these events. Compared to nondepressed participants, depressed participants made more counterfactuals about controllable than uncontrollable aspects of the events they described, and this effect was mediated by general control loss perceptions in the repeatable event condition. Making more (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. A (Creative) Portrait of the Uncertain Individual: Self-Uncertainty and Individualism Enhance Creative Generation.Keith Markman, Kimberly Rios, Juliana Schroeder & Elizabeth Dyczewski - 2014 - Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 40 (8):1050-1062.
    Building on findings that self-uncertainty motivates attempts to restore certainty about the self, particularly in ways that highlight one’s distinctiveness from others, we show that self-uncertainty, relative to uncertainty in general, increases creative generation among individualists. In Studies 1 to 3, high (but not low) individualists performed better on a creative generation task after being primed with self-uncertainty as opposed to general uncertainty. In Study 4, this effect emerged only among those who were told that the task measured creative as (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Theoretical Terms and Inductive Inference.Keith Lehrer - forthcoming - American Philosophical Quarterly.
1 — 50 / 959