Results for 'proportional liability'

966 found
Order:
  1.  53
    An appraisal of shareholder proportional liability.Gordon G. Sollars - 2001 - Journal of Business Ethics 32 (4):329-345.
    Shareholders of corporations have their liability for actions of the corporation limited by law. Unlike the equity holder in a partnership or proprietorship, the assets that a shareholder has distinct from her holdings in the enterprise can not be taken to satisfy liabilities arising from actions of the enterprise itself. This paper argues that a reasonable principle of fairness argues for an alternative to limited liability, proportional liability. Proportional liability makes a shareholder liable for (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  2.  30
    The Multiple Debtors Case: the Extent of the Tortious Duty to Compensate Damage—Solidary or Proportional Liability? (text only in Lithuanian).Simona Selelionytė-Drukteinienė - 2010 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 121 (3):233-250.
    Among the most complicated issues in the law of delict, in the case of multiple debtors, is to determine the scope of each co-debtor’s liability. The rule of proportional liability clearly favours debtors more than the aggrieved party. And, on the contrary, the solidary liability best suits the interests of the aggrieved party as the risk of co-debtor’s insolvency is transferred to the debtors. Furthermore, in the latter case, the debtors who attempt to allocate the scope (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  33
    All-or-Nothing, or Something – Proportional Liability in Private Law.Omer Y. Pelled - 2021 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 22 (1):159-199.
    Judges and juries often make factual decisions even if the facts are disputed and there is no clear-cut evidence available. Despite this common state of uncertainty, verdicts are thought of as having clear winners and losers––either the plaintiff wins and receives a full remedy, or the defendant wins and the plaintiff gets nothing. In private disputes, factfinders base their binary factual determinations on the preponderance of the evidence. There are, however, several doctrines that allow for partial remedy, discounted by the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  41
    Strict Liability and the Paradoxes of Proportionality.Leo Katz & Alvaro Sandroni - 2018 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 12 (3):365-373.
    This essay explores the case against strict liability offenses as part of the more general debate about proportional punishment. This debate takes on a very different look in light of a formal result derived by the authors elsewhere, that is briefly summarized and whose implications are pursued here. Traditional objections that consequentialists have mounted against the deontologists’/retributivists’ defense of proportionality fall by the wayside, but a new threat to the proportionality requirement replaces it: the ease with which any (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  19
    Evidentiary Graded Punishment: A New Look at Criminal Liability for Failing to Report Criminal Activity.Doron Teichman - 2024 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 18 (2):579-598.
    This Article presents a theory whereby criminal punishments are routinely distributed in proportion to the weight of the evidence mounted against the defendant. According to this theory, the law relaxes the stringent decision threshold in criminal trials—beyond a reasonable doubt—by creating easy-to-prove evidentiary offenses. These offenses, in turn, are associated with less severe sanctions, thus creating a de-facto proportional liability regime. Against that backdrop, the Article examines the legal duty to report criminal activity to the authorities. As the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  13
    The Uneasy Case of Multiple Injurers’ Liability.Shmuel Leshem & Ehud Guttel - 2014 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 15 (2):261-292.
    When harm is caused by multiple injurers, damages are allocated among the responsible injurers in proportion to their relative responsibility for harm. This Article shows that a proportional allocation of liability between strictly-liable injurers distorts incentives to take precautions. The effects of this distortion depend on the nature of the injurers’ precautions. If precautions are complements, injurers compete for lower liability shares, which results in excessive care-taking. If precautions are substitutes, injurers are afflicted by moral hazard, which (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  74
    (1 other version)Egalitarianism and the Problem of Tort Liability.Michael Corrado - 2001 - Noûs 35 (s1):388-419.
    Is the negligence standard in accident law acceptable to the egalitarian? The egalitarian - the egalitarian who would compensate only losses for which the actor was not responsible - cannot accept either a system of strict liability for all accidents or a system of social insurance for all accidents. A system of tort law acceptable to the responsibility - egalitarian must be a system based on negligence. But what will negligence mean? A negligence system in which the notion of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8. Complicity and the responsibility dilemma.Morten Højer Jensen - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 177 (1):109-127.
    Jeff McMahan famously defends a moral inequality of combatants, where liability to be attacked and potentially killed in war, should be grounded in the individual combatant’s moral responsibility for posing an unjust threat. In a response, Seth Lazar shows that McMahan’s criterion for liability leads to an unacceptable dilemma between “contingent pacifism” and “total war”, i.e. between war being practically infeasible, or implausibly many civilians being legitimate targets. The problem is that McMahan grounds liability mainly in the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9. Sailing Alone: Teenage Autonomy and Regimes of Childhood.Joel Anderson & Rutger Claassen - 2012 - Law and Philosophy 31 (5):495-522.
    Should society intervene to prevent the risky behavior of precocious teenagers even if it would be impermissible to intervene with adults who engage in the same risky behavior? The problem is well illustrated by the legal case of the 13-year-old Dutch girl Laura Dekker, who set out in 2009 to become the youngest person ever to sail around the world alone, succeeding in January 2012. In this paper we use her case as a point of entry for discussing the fundamental (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  10. Decentralized Governance of AI Agents.Tomer Jordi Chaffer, Charles von Goins Ii, Bayo Okusanya, Dontrail Cotlage & Justin Goldston - manuscript
    Autonomous AI agents present transformative opportunities and significant governance challenges. Existing frameworks, such as the EU AI Act and the NIST AI Risk Management Framework, fall short of addressing the complexities of these agents, which are capable of independent decision-making, learning, and adaptation. To bridge these gaps, we propose the ETHOS (Ethical Technology and Holistic Oversight System) framework—a decentralized governance (DeGov) model leveraging Web3 technologies, including blockchain, smart contracts, and decentralized autonomous organizations (DAOs). ETHOS establishes a global registry for AI (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Offences and defences: selected essays in the philosophy of criminal law.John Gardner - 2007 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The wrongness of rape -- Rationality and the rule of law in offences against the person -- Complicity and causality -- In defence of defences -- Justifications and reasons -- The gist of excuses -- Fletcher on offences and defences -- Provocation and pluralism -- The mark of responsibility -- The functions and justifications of criminal law and punishment -- Crime : in proportion and in perspective -- Reply to critics.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  12.  18
    Antiretroviral Therapy Coverage, Entrepreneurship, and Development in Low- and Middle-Income Countries.Cornelius A. Rietveld & Pankaj C. Patel - 2025 - Business and Society 64 (3):441-471.
    Improvements in the health capital of citizens are central to the development of countries. By exploiting steep decreases in antiretroviral drug prices and the subsequent increases in antiretroviral therapy (ART) coverage, we test whether the resulting improvements in the health of the population are associated with the prevalence of entrepreneurial activity and whether entrepreneurial activity strengthens the relationship between ART coverage and a country’s development. Drawing on a sample of 87 low- and middle-income countries (2006–2019), we find that a 1% (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  70
    Marketing strategy, product safety, and ethical factors in consumer choice.Eleonora Curlo - 1999 - Journal of Business Ethics 21 (1):37 - 48.
    Firms that wish to be morally responsible in providing products that meet a high standard of safety may face problems competing against firms that make unsafe products and sell these products at cheap prices; these problems may be compounded when consumers do not accurately process information about safety and risk. This paper presents a conceptual argument that the tort system may serve to promulgate information which makes it feasible for firms to market safe products even in the face of these (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  14.  47
    The responsible shareholder: a case study.Richard C. Warren - 2002 - Business Ethics, the Environment and Responsibility 11 (1):14-24.
    Shareholders are sometimes considered to be, in moral terms, the owners of a company, they are after all the carriers of the residual liabilities and bear a higher proportion of the financial risk. However, in company law, the shareholders’ responsibility is limited, and in financial terms shareholders are only liable up to the fully paid value of the share certificate. Moreover, when the shares are sold, the responsibility and risk are transferred completely to the new bearer of the shares. Whether (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15. Mary Jane sheffet.Market Share Liability - 1989 - In A. Pablo Iannone (ed.), Contemporary moral controversies in business. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Robert H. malott.Liability Law - 1989 - In A. Pablo Iannone (ed.), Contemporary moral controversies in business. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 376.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Liability and risk.David McCarthy - 1996 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 25 (3):238-262.
    Standard theories of liability say that X is liable to Y only if Y was harmed, only if X caused Y harm, and (usually) only if X was at fault. This article offers a series of criticisms of each of these claims, and use them to construct an alternative theory of liability in which the nature of X's having imposed a risk of harm on Y is central to the question of when X is liable to Y, and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  18.  33
    Contractual Liability: for Fault or Strict?Simona Selelionytė-Drukteinienė - 2011 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 18 (4):1417-1441.
    The author investigates the necessity of fault as the prerequisite of contractual civil liability. The author makes the conclusion that Lithuanian law, following most of the countries belonging to the civil law tradition and contrary to the common law systems, as well as Vienna convention, UNIDROIT principles, PECL and DCFR, begins with the theory that fault is a requirement for contractual liability. Strict liability in Lithuanian law is the exception of this general rule. Nevertheless, the author argues (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  88
    Proportional Hazards Modeling of Saccadic Response Times During Reading.Mattias Nilsson & Joakim Nivre - 2013 - Topics in Cognitive Science 5 (3):541-563.
    In this article we use proportional hazards models to examine how low-level processes affect the probability of making a saccade over time, through the period of fixation, during reading. We apply the Cox proportional hazards model to investigate how launch distance (relative to word beginning), fixation location (relative to word center), and word frequency affect the hazard of a saccadic response. This model requires that covariates have a constant impact on the hazard over time, the assumption of (...) hazards. We show that this assumption is not supported. The impact of the covariates changes with the time passed since fixation onset. To account for the non-proportional hazards we fit step functions of time, resulting in a model with time-varying effects on the hazard. We evaluate the ability to predict the timing of saccades on held-out fixation data. The model with time-varying effects performs better in predicting the timing of saccades for fixations as short as 100 ms and as long as 500 ms, when compared both to a baseline model without covariates and a model which assumes constant covariate effects. This result suggests that the time-varying effects model better recovers the time course of low-level processes that influence the decision to move the eyes. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  10
    Defensive Liability Without Culpability.Saba Bazargan - 2016 - In Christian Coons & Michael Weber (eds.), The Ethics of Self-Defense. New York, NY: Oxford University Press USA.
    A minimally responsible threatener is someone who bears some responsibility for imposing an objectively wrongful threat, but whose responsibility does not rise to the level of culpability. Minimally responsible threateners include those who knowingly commit a wrongful harm under duress, those who are epistemically justified but mistaken in their belief that a morally risky activity will not cause a wrongful harm, and those who commit a harm while suffering from a cognitive impairment which makes it prohibitively difficult to recognize and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  98
    Vicarious liability: a solution to a problem of AI responsibility?Matteo Pascucci & Daniela Glavaničová - 2022 - Ethics and Information Technology 24 (3):1-11.
    Who is responsible when an AI machine causes something to go wrong? Or is there a gap in the ascription of responsibility? Answers range from claiming there is a unique responsibility gap, several different responsibility gaps, or no gap at all. In a nutshell, the problem is as follows: on the one hand, it seems fitting to hold someone responsible for a wrong caused by an AI machine; on the other hand, there seems to be no fitting bearer of responsibility (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22. Liability and Just Cause.Thomas Hurka - 2007 - Ethics and International Affairs 21 (2):199-218.
    This paper is a response to Jeff McMahan's "Just Cause for War". It defends a more permissive, and more traditional view of just war liability against McMahan's claims.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  23.  74
    Civilian Liability.Helen Frowe - 2019 - Ethics 129 (4):625-650.
    Adil Ahmad Haque argues that civilians who contribute to unjust lethal threats in war, but who do not directly participate in the war, are not liable to defensive killing. His argument rests on two central claims: first, that the extent of a person’s liability to defensive harm in virtue of contributing to an unjust threat is limited to the cost that she is initially required to bear in order to avoid contributing, and, second, that civilians need not bear lethal (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24.  27
    Proportions du ciel d’Anaximandre.Jean-François Corre - 2013 - Phronesis 58 (1):1-16.
    The doxography for Anaximander’s account of the rings of the sky gives proportions for them that are discrepant. So a widely accepted hypothesis proposes that, since the circles of the celestial bodies are compared to wheels, we should add the thickness of their ‘rims’ to the measurements for the celestial rings. This paper proposes an entirely different hypothesis which avoids this awkward expedient by suggesting that there is a ‘geometrical’ reading of the numerical data. The discrepancies can then be explained (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Rights, Liability, and the Moral Equality of Combatants.Uwe Steinhoff - 2012 - The Journal of Ethics 16 (4):339-366.
    According to the dominant position in the just war tradition from Augustine to Anscombe and beyond, there is no "moral equality of combatants." That is, on the traditional view the combatants participating in a justified war may kill their enemy combatants participating in an unjustified war - but not vice versa (barring certain qualifications). I shall argue here, however, that in the large number of wars (and in practically all modern wars) where the combatants on the justified side violate the (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  26. Complicitous liability in war.Saba Bazargan - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 165 (1):177-195.
    Jeff McMahan has argued against the moral equivalence of combatants (MEC) by developing a liability-based account of killing in warfare. On this account, a combatant is morally liable to be killed only if doing so is an effective means of reducing or eliminating an unjust threat to which that combatant is contributing. Since combatants fighting for a just cause generally do not contribute to unjust threats, they are not morally liable to be killed; thus MEC is mistaken. The problem, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  27.  12
    Collective Liability in Islam: The ʿĀqila and Blood-Money Payments. By Nurit Tsafrir.Marion H. Katz - 2022 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 142 (1).
    Collective Liability in Islam: The ʿĀqila and Blood-Money Payments. By Nurit Tsafrir. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2020. Pp. xviii + 167. $99.99.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  56
    Material Liability of Public Servants in Lithuania: Theory and Practice.Violeta Kosmačaitė & Vidmantas Jurgaitis - 2013 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 20 (2):611-625.
    Legal acts of the Republic of Lithuania establish several types of material liability of workers engaged in labour (professional) relations: material liability applied pursuant to the Labour Code of the Republic of Lithuania (hereinafter referred to as the LC) and material liability applied pursuant to the Law on Public Service of the Republic of Lithuania (hereinafter referred to as the LPC). In the present article, theoretical and practical aspects of material liability of Lithuanian public servants for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  49
    Justifying liability to third parties for negligent misstatements.Witting Christian - 2000 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 20 (4):615-643.
    The courts have experienced difficulty in justifying the imposition of liability to third parties for negligent misstatements. The justifications ordinarily invoked relate to notions of assumption of responsibility and detrimental reliance. These can be seen, in turn, to rest upon a normative framework of give and take (or «mutuality») between statement makers and third party recipients. This article challenges the cogency of that normative framework and offers an alternative based upon the remedial nature of tort, which has traditionally focused (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  21
    Liability for Emissions without Laws or Political Institutions.Göran Duus-Otterström - 2023 - Law and Philosophy 42 (5):461-486.
    Many climate ethicists maintain that climate policy costs should be borne by those who historically emitted the most greenhouse gases. Some theorists have recently argued, however, that actors only became liable for emitting once the emissions breached legitimate legal regulation governing emissions. This paper challenges this view. Focusing on the climate responsibility of states, it argues that even if we assume that legitimate legal regulation is needed to remove excusable ignorance of entitlements to emit or is constitutive of such entitlements, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  66
    Defensive Liability: A Matter of Rights Enforcement, not Distributive Justice.Susanne Burri - 2022 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 16 (3):539-553.
    The Moral Responsibility Account of Liability to Defensive Harm (MRA) states that an agent becomes liable to defensive harm if, and only if, she engages in a foreseeably risk-imposing activity that subsequently threatens objectively unjustified harm. Advocates of the account contend that liability to defensive harm is best understood as an aspect of distributive justice. Individuals who are liable to some harm are not wronged if the harm is imposed on them, and liability to defensive harm thus (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  25
    Origin of the Criminal Liability of Legal Entities (text only in Lithuanian).Romualdas Drakšas - 2010 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 122 (4):189-201.
    Criminal liability of legal entities was legitimized in the Republic of Lithuania eight years ago, and in the ruling of the Constitutional Court of 8 June 2009, a conclusive confirmation on its accordance with the Constitution was made. It should be noted that the extension of the concept of criminal offense subject has received considerable attention of Lithuanian scientists. It was obvious that this penal law novel would cause many problems and, surely, it has become a reason of many (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  53
    Risk Imposition and Liability to Defensive Harm.Helen Frowe - 2022 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 16 (3):511-524.
    According to Jonathan Quong’s _moral status account_ of liability to defensive harm, an agent is liable to defensive harm only when she mistakenly treats others as if their moral status is diminished (for example, as if they lack a right that they in fact possess). Quong argues that, by the lights of the moral status account, a conscientious driver (Driver) who faultlessly threatens to kill Pedestrian is not liable to defensive harm. Quong argues that Driver’s action is evidence-relative permissible, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34.  10
    Citizen liabilities for state-perpetrated injustices in non-democracies: toward a new authorisation account.Brian Wong Yue Shun - forthcoming - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy.
    When states perpetrate injustices, do their individual citizens develop liabilities to repair such wrongdoings? Most existing accounts of citizens’ liabilities for state-perpetrated injustices, whilst applicable across certain democratic contexts, struggle to provide robust accounts of the grounds and nature of liabilities for citizens in non-democratic contexts. This problematically leaves a lacuna when it comes to the responsibilities and appropriate responses of citizens in these states. This article advances a distinctive two-pronged authorisation-based account applicable to non-democracies. Objective authorisers are individuals who (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  77
    Proportionality, Liability, and Defensive Harm.Jonathan Quong - 2015 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 43 (2):144-173.
  36. Epistemological liabilities of the clinical appraisal of psychoanalytic theory.Adolf Grunbaum - 1980 - Noûs 14 (3):307-385.
  37.  55
    Proportional readings of many and few: the case for an underspecified measure function.Alan Bale & Bernhard Schwarz - 2020 - Linguistics and Philosophy 43 (6):673-699.
    In the so-called reverse proportional reading :53, 1997), the truth conditions of statements of the form many/few \\ appear to make reference to the ratio of the individuals that are in the extensions of both \ and \ to the individuals that are in the extension of \. The analysis of such readings is controversial. One prominent approach assumes they are a symptom of many and few making reference to a context dependent standard of comparison. We observe that this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  16
    Liability of Experts and the Boundary between Tort and Contract.Hans Bernd-Schäfer - 2002 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 3 (2).
    This paper offers an economic analysis of one aspect of the possible liability for incorrect information traded on information markets: expert liability for incorrect asset valuation. The article does not address the questions of whether and under what circumstances an expert should bear contractual liability for an incorrect valuation. Rather, it assumes such contractual liability towards the person who has solicited the opinion and focuses instead on analyzing the circumstances under which the expert’s liability should (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  26
    Criminal Liability for Unlawful Engagement in Economic, Commercial, Financial or Professional Activities: In Search of Optimal Criteria.Oleg Fedosiuk - 2013 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 20 (1):301-317.
    This article focuses on the problem of criminal liability for unlawful engagement in economic activities, analyses the emergence and development of this norm in criminal law and the ways of its optimal explanation. Special attention is paid to the problem of identification of illegality of activities, based on specific tax and economic regulation. The study concludes that criminal liability must be limited to a violation of fundamental requirements for the legality of business, and does not include particular abuses (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  13
    Criminal liability for crimes related to the illegal conduct of a medical experiment.Rafał Kubiak - 2023 - Diametros 20 (78):37-71.
    In 2021, there was a significant amendment to the legislation on medical experimentation. In particular, Chapter 4 of the Law of December 5, 1996 on the Profession of Physician and Dentist (Journal of Laws 2023, item 1516) was amended, in which the prerequisites of legally relevant consent given by the participant in the experiment or by other entities that express a position on their behalf were specified. In addition, procedures related to the opinion of the research project by the so-called (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Defensive Liability Without Culpability.Saba Bazargan-Forward - 2016 - In Christian Coons & Michael Weber (eds.), The Ethics of Self-Defense. New York, NY: Oxford University Press USA.
    A minimally responsible threatener is someone who bears some responsibility for imposing an objectively wrongful threat, but whose responsibility does not rise to the level of culpability. Minimally responsible threateners include those who knowingly commit a wrongful harm under duress, those who are epistemically justified but mistaken in their belief that a morally risky activity will not cause a wrongful harm, and those who commit a harm while suffering from a cognitive impairment which makes it prohibitively difficult to recognize and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Liability for failing to rescue.TheodoreM Benditt - 1982 - Law and Philosophy 1 (3):391 - 418.
    Should there be civil liability when a person who could easily and without risk rescue another fails to do so? It is argued that the failure to act does not cause the harm that follows, and that the misfeasance/nonfeasance distinction provides no basis for liability. In spite of this, it is maintained that there can sometimes be a duty to rescue, and even a right to be rescued, even in the absence of a voluntary undertaking or an explicit (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  18
    Contractual liability and voluntary undertakings.Sheinman Hanoch - 2000 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 20 (2):205-220.
    Developments in contract law over the past century have led to the proliferation of interpretive theories according to which contract law is no longer a sui generisi legal branch. It is widely accepted that if there is a sui generis contractual obligation, it must somehow be based on the wills of the parties. But a new orthodoxy in contract theory claims that the role of the will of the parties in contract law has been progressively shrinking due to judicial doctrines (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  17
    The Liability of Tribe in Corporate Political Activity: Ethical Implications for Political Contestability.Tahiru Azaaviele Liedong - 2022 - Journal of Business Ethics 181 (3):623-644.
    Political contestability is an important issue in the ethical analysis of corporate political activity (hereafter CPA). Though previous studies have proposed analytical frameworks for creating contestable political systems, these studies conceive firm-level factors such as size and wealth as the main (and perhaps, only) determinants of contestability. This relegates the influences of informal managerial-level attributes such as tribalism, especially in ethnically diverse contexts where politics and tribe are inseparable. In this article, I explore the linkages between managers’ tribal identity and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  19
    Liability for Dispensing Errors in Hong Kong.Cedric Tang - 2021 - Asian Bioethics Review 13 (4):435-462.
    The United Kingdom case R v Lee EWCA Crim 1404 resulted in a pharmacist being convicted for an inadvertent dispensing error and paved way for the decriminalisation of such errors by way of a due diligence defence enacted in 2018. In relation to Hong Kong, what is its legal position for dispensing errors, and can it follow the decriminalising steps of UK? The primary objective of this paper is to explore whether and how HK can reach the normative position for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  45
    Can Strict Criminal Liability for Responsible Corporate Officers be Justified by the Duty to Use Extraordinary Care?Kenneth W. Simons - 2018 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 12 (3):439-454.
    The responsible corporate officer doctrine is, as a formal matter, an instance of strict criminal liability: the government need not prove the defendant’s mens rea in order to obtain a conviction, and the defendant may not escape conviction by proving lack of mens rea. Formal strict liability is sometimes consistent with retributive principles, especially when the strict liability pertains to the grading of an offense. But is strict liability consistent with retributive principles when it pertains, not (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  11
    Employer Liability for “Take-Home” COVID-19.Mark A. Rothstein & Julia Irzyk - 2021 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 49 (1):126-131.
    Workplace exposure to SARS-CoV-2 has sickened workers and, subsequently, their family members. Family members might be able to recover from the employer in a negligence action using “take-home” liability theory.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. The Liability of Justified Attackers.Uwe Steinhoff - 2016 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 19 (4):1016-1030.
    McMahan argues that justification defeats liability to defensive attack (which would undermine the thesis of the "moral equality of combatants"). In response, I argue, first, that McMahan’s attempt to burden the contrary claim with counter-intuitive implications fails; second, that McMahan’s own position implies that the innocent civilians do not have a right of self-defense against justified attackers, which neither coheres with his description of the case (the justified bombers infringe the rights of the civilians) nor with his views about (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49.  54
    Partial liability.Alex Kaiserman - 2017 - Legal Theory 23 (1):1-26.
    In most cases, liability in tort law is all-or-nothing—a defendant is either fully liable or not at all liable for a claimant's loss. By contrast, this paper defends a causal theory of partial liability. I argue that a defendant should be held liable for a claimant's loss only to the degree to which the defendant's wrongdoing contributed to the causing of the loss. I ground this principle in a conception of tort law as a system of corrective justice (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  50.  12
    Against Liability.Michelle Madden Dempsey - 2016 - In Christian Coons & Michael Weber (eds.), The Ethics of Self-Defense. New York, NY: Oxford University Press USA.
    According to Jeff McMahan, a person is liable to be killed in self-defense if the person has acted in such a way that to kill him would neither wrong him nor violate his rights. This account of self-defense has spawned something of a cottage industry in the philosophical literature of such “liability-based accounts.” Liability-based accounts of self-defense, however, are deficient for two reasons. First, they fail to account for the moral residue that remains in the wake of the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 966