Results for 'passion control'

982 found
Order:
  1. Controlling the passions: passion, memory, and the moral physiology of self in seventeenth-century neurophilosophy.John Sutton - 1998 - In Stephen Gaukroger (ed.), The Soft Underbelly of Reason: The Passions in the Seventeenth Century. New York: Routledge. pp. 115-146.
    Some natural philosophers in the 17th century believed that they could control their own innards, specifically the animal spirits coursing incessantly through brain and nerves, in order to discipline or harness passion, cognition and action under rational guidance. This chapter addresses the mechanisms thought necessary after Eden for controlling the physiology of passion. The tragedy of human embedding in the body, with its cognitive and moral limitations, was paired with a sense of our confinement in sequential time. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  2.  19
    Passion, Trait Self-Control, and Wellbeing: Comparing Two Mediation Models Predicting Wellbeing.Walid Briki - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. The rational control of passions in Descartes: The ambivalence of compassion.Alicia Villar Ezcurra - 2008 - Pensamiento 64 (239):143-150.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  99
    On Reason’s Control of the Passions in Aquinas’s Theory of Temperance.Giuseppe Butera - 2006 - Mediaeval Studies 68 (1):133-160.
    Contrary to the fairly standard view of Aquinas on temperance according to which this virtue habituates the concupiscible appetite to move in ways that accord with reason spontaneously, that is, independently of any immediate command from reason, the author of this paper argues that temperance is a virtue which "(1) disposes the concupiscible appetite to remain more or less still in the absence of any command from reason to move, thus preventing vehement, spontaneous passions of any sort, ordinate or inordinate, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  34
    Reining In The Passions: The Role Of Emotions In Understanding Self-Control.Mara McGuire - unknown
    In this paper, I consider a philosophical model of self-control recently developed by Chandra Sripada and inspired by current dual-process models in both the sciences of the mind and philosophy. Sripada argues that the mind is bifurcated into two motivational systems that correspond to Emotion and Reason and that to exercise self-control is to act in accordance with reason when it comes into conflict with emotion. I argue that Sripada’s model rests on two false assumptions, that emotions are (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Spinoza on Destroying Passions with Reason.Colin Marshall - 2012 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85 (1):139-160.
    Spinoza claims we can control any passion by forming a more clear and distinct idea of it. The interpretive consensus is that Spinoza is either wrong or over-stating his view. I argue that Spinoza’s view is plausible and insightful. After breaking down Spinoza’s characterization of the relevant act, I consider four existing interpretations and conclude that each is unsatisfactory. I then consider a further problem for Spinoza: how his definitions of ‘action’ and ‘passion’ make room for passions (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  7. Thomas Aquinas on Reason's Control of the Passions in the Virtue of Temperance.Giuseppe Butera - 2001 - Dissertation, The Catholic University of America
    This dissertation examines Aquinas's teaching on the acts specific to temperance. According to a widespread interpretation of this teaching , the proper act of temperance is spontaneous, ordinate passion. Temperance thus not only causes someone to experience the right passions towards the right objects but does so antecedent to reason's command. Indeed, temperance is thought to have little if anything to do with reason's control of the passions. In an introductory chapter, I show that this understanding of temperance (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  33
    Going Through the Emotions: Passion, Violence, and “Other‐Control” among the Dou Donggo.Peter Just - 1991 - Ethos: Journal of the Society for Psychological Anthropology 19 (3):288-312.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning.Simon Blackburn - 1998 - New York: Oxford University Press UK.
    Simon Blackburn puts forward a compelling original philosophy of human motivation and morality. He maintains that we cannot get clear about ethics until we get clear about human nature. So these are the sorts of questions he addresses: Why do we behave as we do? Can we improve? Is our ethics at war with our passions, or is it an upshot of those passions? Blackburn seeks the answers in an exploration of guilt, shame, disgust, and other moral emotions; he draws (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   345 citations  
  10.  11
    When Passion Does Not Change, but Emotions Do: Testing a Social Media Intervention Related to Exercise Activity Engagement.Silje Berg, Jacques Forest & Frode Stenseng - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11:504731.
    Grounded in self-determination theory and the dualistic model of passion, the present study tested whether a social media intervention could promote harmonious passion and positive emotions related to exercise activities. A four-week intervention managed through an Instagram account was designed to promote more harmonious passion and less obsessive passion, as well as more positive emotions and less negative emotions related to participants’ favourite exercise activities. A web-based questionnaire was distributed to 518 young adults (mean age 26.5) (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11. Passionate Regulation and the Practicality of Reason.Elizabeth S. Radcliffe - 2018 - In Philip A. Reed & Rico Vitz (eds.), Hume’s Moral Philosophy and Contemporary Psychology. London, UK: Routledge.
    The author presents a reading of Hume’s theory of passionate self-moderation and explore its application to the question of whether Hume accords any practicality to reason. One of Hume’s well-known arguments concludes that reason cannot exercise control over the passions, many of which cause or motivate action. So, it looks as though actions are inevitable results of unruly passions. Hume’s theory of action, however, embodies principles by which certain passions can moderate the effects of other passions. The goal in (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  73
    A politics of passion in education: The foucauldian legacy.Michalinos Zembylas - 2007 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 39 (2):135–149.
    Prompted by what is seen as a missing analysis in the discussions about passion and affect in education, this essay attempts to clarify and provide a context for understanding the contribution of Foucault in the discourse of passion. In particular, the author traces the politics of passion in Foucault's work. A ‘politics of passion’ is the analysis that challenges the cultural and historical emotional rules with respect to what passion is, how it is expressed, who (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  13. Courage, Passion and Virtue.Xinyan Jiang - 1994 - Dissertation, University of Cincinnati
    An important question about the nature of virtue is whether an agent's being virtuous requires the harmony in the agent between right action and right passion. This dissertation tries to answer this question by examining a particular virtue-- courage. ;The dissertation discusses different positions in both the West and the East on the relation of action and passion in the virtue of courage. These positions form a spectrum as follows: Mencius's view : courage does not involve battling with (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  22
    Passions and Individual Responsibility in Seneca.Panos Eliopoulos - 2018 - Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy 2 (3):11-17.
    For Seneca passions are not just bad judgments that need to be defeated. Even though he generally agrees with Chrysippus on the matter of the ontology of passions, Seneca differentiates mainly in his emphasis that passions are the reason why man leads an inauthentic, unhappy and undignified life. The Roman philosopher employs practical techniques that refer to the ordinary man, the man who rationally desires to change his merely-being into well-being. But that action requires the energetic engagement of the individual (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. The passionate scientist: Emotion in scientific cognition.Paul R. Thagard - 2002 - In The Cognitive Basis of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 235.
    Since Plato, most philosophers have drawn a sharp line between reason and emotion, assuming that emotions interfere with rationality and have nothing to contribute to good reasoning. In his dialogue the Phaedrus, Plato compared the rational part of the soul to a charioteer who must control his steeds, which correspond to the emotional parts of the soul (Plato 1961, p. 499). Today, scientists are often taken as the paragons of rationality, and scientific thought is generally assumed to be independent (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  16. "Passions" in the Discourses on Witchcraft in Kerala.G. Tarabout - 2000 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 28 (5/6):651-664.
    This paper is about misfortune as elaborated in the narratives of (counter-) witchcraft practitioners and consultants. Their statements can be read from different perspectives, and I choose here to look at them specifically in terms of 'passions' and their control.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  14
    Reason, Passion, and Metaphysics in Bonaventure: Against Hylomorphic Enthusiasm.Matthew J. Dugandzic - 2024 - Nova et Vetera 22 (1):123-134.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reason, Passion, and Metaphysics in Bonaventure:Against Hylomorphic EnthusiasmMatthew J. DugandzicIntroductionContemporary commentators on Aquinas's understanding of the passions all agree that reason is supposed to be the ruler of the passions, but they disagree on the character of this rule. Some would ascribe a high degree of freedom to the passions, such that, even though reason is overall the ruler of the passions, sometimes the passions are right to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  40
    The Passion for Happiness: Samuel Johnson and David Hume (review).Walter E. Broman - 2001 - Philosophy and Literature 25 (1):169-171.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy and Literature 25.1 (2001) 169-171 [Access article in PDF] Book Review The Passion for Happiness: Samuel Johnson and David Hume The Passion for Happiness: Samuel Johnson and David Hume, by Adam Potkay; 241 pp. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2000, $42.50. This book is a sustained attack on the widespread impression that Samuel Johnson and David Hume were antithetical characters, a notion largely nourished by that memorable (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  30
    Passion and Action: The Emotions in Seventeenth-Century Philosophy (review).Richard A. Watson - 1999 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 37 (1):168-169.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Passion and Action: The Emotions in Seventeenth-Century Philosophy by Susan JamesRichard A. WatsonSusan James. Passion and Action: The Emotions in Seventeenth-Century Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press, 1997. Pp. vii + 318. Cloth, $35.00.Susan James shows how during the seventeenth century philosophers moved from the three souls of Aristotle and the tripartite soul of Thomas Aquinas in which passions and reasons compete for the attention of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  97
    Descartes, Passion, and the Ability to Do Otherwise.Christopher Gilbert - 2013 - Journal of Philosophical Research 38:275-298.
    What does Descartes regard as necessary for human freedom? I approach this topic from a distinctive angle by focusing on the role of the passions in Descartes’s account of free will. My goal is to show that (1) Descartes takes us to have the ability to do otherwise when we judge or choose under the influence of the passions, and that (2) while such ability does not constitute freedom in the fullest Cartesian sense, it does ensure that the judgments and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  4
    The passions of the soul in René Descartes: physiologies, utility and remedies.Felini de Souza - 2024 - Griot 24 (3):28-45.
    Descartes dedicates his last work to the study of passions. This theme would come to close his contributions to the discussion of substantial union. How do two substances complete and distinct are united? This interaction between body and soul may not be explained in theoretical terms, but when Descartes draws practical conclusions, seeking in passions the key to this relationship. In “The Passions of Soul” Descartes creates a kind of taxonomy of passions, classifying them into six primary passions passions and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  28
    Master Passions: Emotion, Narrative, and the Development of Culture.Mihnea C. Moldoveanu & Nitin Nohria - 2002 - MIT Press.
    At the heart of the human experience lies anxiety caused by the realization that the world is unknown, forever eluding our control. And out of this anxiety arise the master passions of ambition and envy, which we repress to mask their power over our lives. Discussion of the role of the emotions in our lives is not new, but Mihnea Moldoveanu and Nitin Nohria go much further, showing how these passions shape not only our individual lives but our social (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23.  73
    Self-Control in Action.Alfred Mele - 2011 - In Shaun Gallagher (ed.), The Oxford handbook of the self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    This article describes a neo-Aristotelian conception of self-control, a concept that seems essential to what it means to be a mature human person. It discusses the moral condition known as akrasia and the conception of self that underpins it. While Aristotle regarded the human self to be primarily rational where reason is taken in a strong sense, this article suggests a more holistic conception of the self, where to act out of passion may not mean that one is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24. Self-control, Attention, and How to live without Special Motivational Powers.Sebastian Watzl - 2019 - In Michael Brent & Lisa Miracchi Titus (eds.), Mental Action and the Conscious Mind. New York, NY: Routledge. pp. 272-300.
    It has been argued that the explanation of self-control requires positing special motivational powers. Some think that we need will-power as an irreducible mental faculty; others that we need to think of the active self as a dedicated and depletable pool of psychic energy or – in today more respectable terminology – mental resources; finally, there is the idea that self-control requires postulating a deep division between reason and passion – a deliberative and an emotional motivational system. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25.  18
    Fire spreading across boundaries: The positive spillover of entrepreneurial passion to family and community domains.Xiong-Hui Xiao & Hui Fu - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    Passion plays a crucial role in entrepreneurial activity, while its positive spillover to the family and community domains is scant. We proposed an integrated enrichment framework of “work-family-community” based on the literature in the field. Drawing upon the matching samples of entrepreneurs' individuals, families, and communities in the China Labor-force Dynamics Survey database, we identified a significant positive spillover effect into the family and community domains and explored the moderating role of the entrepreneur's perceived personal control. The empirical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  10
    A passion to oppose: John Anderson, philosopher.Brian Kennedy - 1995 - Carlton South, Vic., Australia: Melbourne University Press.
    John Anderson was Australia's most important philosopher in the first half of this century. Coming from Scotland as a young man, he held the chair of philosophy at the University of Sydney for thirty years until his retirement in 1958. The doctrinaire Scots empiricist would become as Australian as a magpie. He developed his own distinctive system of realism and fathered a vigorous local school characterised by inquiry, independence and a deep commitment to philosophy as a way of life. Far (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27. Augustine and the Cognitive Cause of Stoic Preliminary Passions ( Propatheiai ).Sarah C. Byers - 2003 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 41 (4):433-448.
    Augustine made a significant contribution to the history of philosophical accounts of affectivity which scholars have not yet noticed. He resolved a problem with the Stoic theory as it was known to him: the question of the cognitive cause of "preliminary passions" ( propatheiai ), reflex-like affective reactions which must be immediately controlled if a morally bad emotion is to be avoided. He identified this cognitive cause as momentary doubt, as I demonstrate by citing passages from sermons spanning twenty-seven years (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  28.  28
    How contempt became a passion.Ross Carroll - 2019 - History of European Ideas 45 (3):346-362.
    ABSTRACTPhilosophers and psychologists have come to recognize contempt as a crucial concept for understanding moral and social life. Yet its conceptual history remains understudied. I argue that contempt underwent an important conceptual shift at the end of the 1640s with the publication of René Descartes’ Passions de l’âme. Prior to Descartes, early modern philosophers excluded contempt from their taxonomies of the passions, treating it instead as a form of indifference. To have contempt for something was to be free of (...) in the face of it. Following Descartes’ intervention, however, philosophers increasingly included contempt among the passions, those unruly perturbations of the mind that could have benign or dangerous effects depending on how they were moderated. This was a change that harboured practical as well as philosophical implications. For what had once been an emblem of self-mastery was now itself a passion in need of regulation. The contempt displayed by aristocrats, in particular, now signified a dangerous lack of self-control rather than a cool display of superiority. I conclude by drawing out the affinities between this mid-seventeenth-century reconceptualization of contempt as a passion and the current attempt by philosophers to redeem contempt as a morally justifiable attitude. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29. Hume on the Passions.Stephen Buckle - 2012 - Philosophy 87 (2):189-213.
    Hume's account of the passions is largely neglected because the author's purposes tend to be missed. The passions were accepted by early modern philosophers, of whatever persuasion, as the mental effects of bodily processes. The dualist and the materialist differed over whether reason is a higher power able to judge and control them: thus Descartes affirms, whereas Hobbes denies, this possibility.Hume's account lines up firmly behind Hobbes. Although he shies away from Hobbes's dogmatic physiological claims, he affirms all the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  30.  3
    Crimes of passion (An Irresistible Impulse) in Kazakhstan.Kudaibergenova A. Zh, F. S. Safuanov, E. K. Kalymbetova, A. A. Urisbayeva & T. E. Konysbai - forthcoming - Evolutionary Studies in Imaginative Culture:1530-1537.
    The article presents the main results of theoretical review on the study of the phenomenon of affect and definition, classification, legal aspects of affective states, as well as the results of statistical processing of data on crimes in the state of affect are provided in Kazakhstan for the last 5 years according to the provided statistical data from the database of the General Prosecutor's Office of the CLSaSA (Committee on Legal Statistics and Special Accounts) of the RK. The relevance of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  22
    The "Wider view": André Hellegers's passionate, integrating intellect and the creation of bioethics.Warren T. Reich - 1999 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 9 (1):25-51.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The “Wider View”: André Hellegers’s Passionate, Integrating Intellect and the Creation of BioethicsWarren Thomas Reich* (bio)AbstractThis article provides an account of how André Hellegers, founder and first Director of the Kennedy Institute of Ethics at Georgetown University, laid medicine open to bioethics. Hellegers’s approach to bioethics, as to morality generally and also to medicine and biomedical science, involved taking the “wider view”—a value-filled vision that integrated and gave meaning (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32. The neural bases of cognitive conflict and control in moral judgment.Joshua D. Greene - 2004 - Neuron 44 (2):389–400.
    In philosophy, a debate can live forever. Nowhere is this more evident than in ethics, a field that is fueled by apparently intractable dilemmas. To promote the wellbeing of many, may we sacrifice the rights of a few? If our actions are predetermined, can we be held responsible for them? Should people be judged on their intentions alone, or also by the consequences of their behavior? Is failing to prevent someone’s death as blameworthy as actively causing it? For generations, questions (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   185 citations  
  33.  39
    Education, Creativity and the Economy of Passions: New Forms of Educational Capitalism.Michael A. Peters - 2009 - Thesis Eleven 96 (1):40-63.
    This article reviews claims for creativity in the economy and in education distinguishing two accounts: 'personal anarcho-aesthetics' and 'the design principle'. The first emerges in the psychological literature from sources in the Romantic Movement emphasizing the creative genius and the way in which creativity emerges from deep subconscious processes, involves the imagination, is anchored in the passions, cannot be directed and is beyond the rational control of the individual. This account has a close fit to business as a form (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  34.  52
    Sovereign Sentiments: Conceptions of Self-Control in David Hume, Adam Smith, and Jane Austen.Lauren Kopajtic - 2017 - Dissertation, Harvard University
    The mention of “self-control” calls up certain stock images: Saint Augustine struggling to renounce carnal pleasures; dispassionate Mr. Spock of Star Trek; the dieter faced with tempting desserts. In these stock images reason is almost always assigned the power and authority to govern passions, desires, and appetites. But what if the passions were given the power to rule—what if, instead of sovereign reason, there were sovereign sentiments? My dissertation examines three sentimentalist conceptions of self-control: David Hume’s conception of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  49
    Sorting Out Reason’s Relation to the Passions in the Moral Theory of Aquinas.Leonard Ferry - 2014 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 88:227-244.
    This essay challenges a growing consensus among Aquinas scholars who attribute to him a pro-passion attitude, linking his virtue theory to accounts of emotion that see the emotions in a primarily positive light. There are good reasons for thinking Aquinas far more skeptical of the role to be played by emotion in the virtuous life—indeed, one can safely argue, in agreement with Aquinas, that the emotions are often threats to and so in need of control by the virtues. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  20
    Debt and sad affects in the society of control.Iwona Młoźniak - 2018 - Conatus 2 (2):49.
    The article presents an analysis of the notion of debt in the context of Deleuzean philosophy of affect. The interpretation presented on the following pages is “indebted” to Lazzarato’s conception of the notion of debt as a figure of subjectivity typical for capitalism. Debt is understood as an assemblage of sad passions and considered in relation to social transformations, that have led to contemporary societies of control. The article shows the connection between the concept of debt and the process (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  35
    On the possibility of mind-reading or the external control of behavior: Contribution of Aquinas to the Neurorights discussion.Jose Ignacio Murillo - 2023 - Scientia et Fides 11 (2):87-105.
    Thomas Aquinas holds that the actual content of our thought is not accessible for any creature, and that free will cannot be superseded. These theses are founded on the spiritual condition of our intelligence and will, which makes them directly invulnerable to any intervention on our body. On the other hand, he enthrones the will as the keeper of interiority: it precludes a full transparency that would make our free decision to communicate superfluous, and it exert an inalienable control (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  20
    Charismatic Political Leadership and Tun Dr Mahathir Mohamad’s Malaysia: Power, Control, Stability and Defence.Suleyman Temiz & Arshad Islam - 2019 - Intellectual Discourse 27 (2):475-505.
    Prior to his renewed incumbency, as the fourth Prime Minister ofMalaysia, Mahathir Mohamad was able to remain in power for amore prolonged period compared to his predecessors. He was actively involvedin galvanizing political action immediately after the independence of Malaysiaand did not abandon active politics until his 2003 resignation. Under Mahathir’sleadership and guidance, Malaysia made remarkable economic and politicalprogress. He oversaw many innovations in the fledgling democracy and wasable to develop the country due to his exceptional leadership qualities. His styleand (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Kantian virtue as cure for affects and passions: Série 2.Maria Borges - 2009 - Kant E-Prints 4:267-283.
    : In the Critique of Practical Reason, Kant presents virtue not as an arduous task, but as an endeavor, that costs a lot for the agent. In order to explain in what consists moral content, Kant tells a story of an honest man, to whom it is offered great gifts if he joins the calumniators of an innocent person, but he denies it. Then he is threatened by his friends, who deny him friendship, by his relatives, who deny him inheritance, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Sor Juana Inés de la Cruz on self‐control.Sergio Armando Gallegos-Ordorica - 2020 - Philosophy Compass (10):1-10.
    The Novohispanic nun Sor Juana Inés de la Cruz has not been traditionally considered as a philosopher within the Anglophone philosophical sphere because her writings are primarily poems and plays. In the last three decades, only a few philosophers have engaged with Sor Juana's works. However, their scholarship has focused only on a narrow range of issues, such as Sor Juana's defense of the right of women to be educated, and has neglected other dimensions of her thought, such as her (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  61
    Cultivating Strength of Mind: Hume on the Government of the Passions and Artificial Virtue.Lauren Kopajtic - 2015 - Hume Studies 41 (2):201-229.
    Several authors have recently noted Hume’s relative silence on the virtue of strength of mind and how it is developed. In this paper I suggest that Hume had good reasons for this silence, and I argue that Hume’s discussion of artificial virtue, especially the virtue of allegiance, reveals a complex view of the limitations on human efforts at self-reform. Further, it reveals the need for government and externally-imposed regulative structures to enable the development of strength of mind. I argue that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  14
    Gender ambivalence and the expression of passions in the performances of early Roman cantatas by castrati and female singers.Christine Jeanneret - 2013 - In Tom Cochrane, Bernardino Fantini & Klaus R. Scherer (eds.), The Emotional Power of Music: Multidisciplinary perspectives on musical arousal, expression, and social control. Oxford University Press. pp. 85.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  6
    Appendix to" Gender ambivalence and the expression of passions.Christine Jeanneret - 2013 - In Tom Cochrane, Bernardino Fantini & Klaus R. Scherer (eds.), The Emotional Power of Music: Multidisciplinary perspectives on musical arousal, expression, and social control. Oxford University Press. pp. 359.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  27
    ¿Puede hacer Dios lo imposible? Sobre la concepción cartesiana de la omnipotencia divina.Rogelio Rovira Madrid - 1993 - Revista de Filosofía (Madrid) 10:329.
    This work intends to point out the role that the idea of God has in Cartesian morals. Both the conception of a God responsible of an universal rational order and the solution to evil question are the grounds for the idea of happiness related to the virtue understood as rational control of passions. Devotion, passion derived from love, is considered by Descartes as the most useful passion that man can experience, as it contributes to the strengthening of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  17
    Writing into the Cold War West. [REVIEW]Adam Piette - 2011 - Theory, Culture and Society 28 (7-8):390-395.
    John Beck's fine study of the representation of the postwar American West, analyzes the cultural impact of the secret state's establishment of its arsenals, proving grounds and waste disposal sites after the Manhattan Project. The giant Southwest Defense Complex is registered, with acute and telling political energy, in texts by Cormac MacCarthy, Leslie Marmon Silko, Bradford Morrow and Don DeLillo, as a brute invisible energy field at the edges of national experience. This is one of the best studies of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Spinoza's account of akrasia.Martin Lin - 2006 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 44 (3):395-414.
    : Perhaps the central problem which preoccupies Spinoza as a moral philosopher is the conflict between reason and passion. He belongs to a long tradition that sees the key to happiness and virtue as mastery and control by reason over the passions. This mastery, however, is hard won, as the passions often overwhelm its power and subvert its rule. When reason succumbs to passion, we act against our better judgment. Such action is often termed 'akratic'. Many commentators (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  47.  88
    Dios en la ética cartesiana. La devoción en la teoría de las pasiones.Félix González Romero - 2008 - 'Ilu. Revista de Ciencias de Las Religiones 13:71-90.
    This work intends to point out the role that the idea of God has in Cartesian morals. Both the conception of a God responsible of an universal rational order and the solution to evil question are the grounds for the idea of happiness related to the virtue understood as rational control of passions. Devotion, passion derived from love, is considered by Descartes as the most useful passion that man can experience, as it contributes to the strengthening of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  12
    Clear bright future: a radical defence of the human being.Paul Mason - 2019 - London: Allen Lane.
    A passionate defence of humanity and a work of radical optimism from the international bestselling author of Postcapitalism How do we preserve what makes us human in an age of uncertainty? Are we now just consumers shaped by market forces? A sequence of DNA? A collection of base instincts? Or will we soon be supplanted by algorithms and A.I. anyway? In Clear Bright Future, Paul Mason calls for a radical, impassioned defence of the human being, our universal rights and freedoms (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  16
    Montaigne et Descartes.Jil Muller - 2020 - Les Cahiers Philosophiques de Strasbourg 48:135-164.
    Cet article se propose d’analyser ce que la théorie cartésienne des passions doit à la conception montaignienne du phénomène passionnel. Les deux philosophes rejettent l’idée de l’âme tripartite et conçoivent une explication similaire pour les mouvements corporels indépendants de l’âme, qui se délie de la tradition aristotélicienne et scolastique. De même, chez les deux, l’imagination joue un rôle primordial dans le déclenchement et le contrôle des passions, dépassant ainsi tout effort de la volonté. Pourtant, l’aspect physiologique de l’explication mécaniste des (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. A Comprehensive Account of Blame: Self-Blame, Non-Moral Blame, and Blame for the Non-Voluntary.Douglas W. Portmore - 2022 - In Andreas Brekke Carlsson (ed.), Self-Blame and Moral Responsibility. New York, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    Blame is multifarious. It can be passionate or dispassionate. It can be expressed or kept private. We blame both the living and the dead. And we blame ourselves as well as others. What’s more, we blame ourselves, not only for our moral failings, but also for our non-moral failings: for our aesthetic bad taste, gustatory self-indulgence, or poor athletic performance. And we blame ourselves both for things over which we exerted agential control (e.g., our voluntary acts) and for things (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
1 — 50 / 982