Results for 'observability of Turing machines'

969 found
Order:
  1.  27
    The computational strengths of α-tape infinite time Turing machines.Benjamin Rin - 2014 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 165 (9):1501-1511.
    In [7], open questions are raised regarding the computational strengths of so-called ∞-α -Turing machines, a family of models of computation resembling the infinite-time Turing machine model of [2], except with α -length tape . Let TαTα denote the machine model of tape length α . Define that TαTα is computationally stronger than TβTβ precisely when TαTα can compute all TβTβ-computable functions ƒ: min2→min2 plus more. The following results are found: Tω1≻TωTω1≻Tω. There are countable ordinals α such (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  2. Philosophy and Science, the Darwinian-Evolved Computational Brain, a Non-Recursive Super-Turing Machine & Our Inner-World-Producing Organ.Hermann G. W. Burchard - 2016 - Open Journal of Philosophy 6 (1):13-28.
    Recent advances in neuroscience lead to a wider realm for philosophy to include the science of the Darwinian-evolved computational brain, our inner world producing organ, a non-recursive super- Turing machine combining 100B synapsing-neuron DNA-computers based on the genetic code. The whole system is a logos machine offering a world map for global context, essential for our intentional grasp of opportunities. We start from the observable contrast between the chaotic universe vs. our orderly inner world, the noumenal cosmos. So far, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  3. Can machines think? The controversy that led to the Turing test.Bernardo Gonçalves - 2023 - AI and Society 38 (6):2499-2509.
    Turing’s much debated test has turned 70 and is still fairly controversial. His 1950 paper is seen as a complex and multilayered text, and key questions about it remain largely unanswered. Why did Turing select learning from experience as the best approach to achieve machine intelligence? Why did he spend several years working with chess playing as a task to illustrate and test for machine intelligence only to trade it out for conversational question-answering in 1950? Why did (...) refer to gender imitation in a test for machine intelligence? In this article, I shall address these questions by unveiling social, historical and epistemological roots of the so-called Turing test. I will draw attention to a historical fact that has been only scarcely observed in the secondary literature thus far, namely that Turing’s 1950 test emerged out of a controversy over the cognitive capabilities of digital computers, most notably out of debates with physicist and computer pioneer Douglas Hartree, chemist and philosopher Michael Polanyi, and neurosurgeon Geoffrey Jefferson. Seen in its historical context, Turing’s 1950 paper can be understood as essentially a reply to a series of challenges posed to him by these thinkers arguing against his view that machines can think. Turing did propose gender learning and imitation as one of his various imitation tests for machine intelligence, and I argue here that this was done in response to Jefferson's suggestion that gendered behavior is causally related to the physiology of sex hormones. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  4.  21
    Galilean resonances: the role of experiment in Turing’s construction of machine intelligence.Bernardo Gonçalves - 2024 - Annals of Science 81 (3):359-389.
    In 1950, Alan Turing proposed his iconic imitation game, calling it a ‘test’, an ‘experiment’, and the ‘the only really satisfactory support’ for his view that machines can think. Following Turing’s rhetoric, the ‘Turing test’ has been widely received as a kind of crucial experiment to determine machine intelligence. In later sources, however, Turing showed a milder attitude towards what he called his ‘imitation tests’. In 1948, Turing referred to the persuasive power of ‘the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  45
    Indicators and Criteria of Consciousness in Animals and Intelligent Machines : An Inside-Out Approach.Cyriel Pennartz, Michele Farisco & Kathinka Evers - 2019 - Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience 13.
    In today’s society, it becomes increasingly important to assess which non-human and non-verbal beings possess consciousness. This review article aims to delineate criteria for consciousness especially in animals, while also taking into account intelligent artifacts. First, we circumscribe what we mean with “consciousness” and describe key features of subjective experience: qualitative richness, situatedness, intentionality and interpretation, integration and the combination of dynamic and stabilizing properties. We argue that consciousness has a biological function, which is to present the subject with a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6. Laws of Form and the Force of Function: Variations on the Turing Test.Hajo Greif - 2012 - In Vincent C. Müller & Aladdin Ayesh (eds.), Revisiting Turing and His Test: Comprehensiveness, Qualia, and the Real World. AISB. pp. 60-64.
    This paper commences from the critical observation that the Turing Test (TT) might not be best read as providing a definition or a genuine test of intelligence by proxy of a simulation of conversational behaviour. Firstly, the idea of a machine producing likenesses of this kind served a different purpose in Turing, namely providing a demonstrative simulation to elucidate the force and scope of his computational method, whose primary theoretical import lies within the realm of mathematics rather than (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  9
    Refining Mark Burgin’s Case against the Church–Turing Thesis.Edgar Graham Daylight - 2024 - Philosophies 9 (4):122.
    The outputs of a Turing machine are not revealed for inputs on which the machine fails to halt. Why is an observer not allowed to see the generated output symbols as the machine operates? Building on the pioneering work of Mark Burgin, we introduce an extension of the Turing machine model with a visible output tape. As a subtle refinement to Burgin’s theory, we stipulate that the outputted symbols cannot be overwritten: at step i, the content of the (...) (RBMs) compute more functions than Turing machines, but fewer than Burgin’s simple inductive Turing machines. We argue that RBMs more closely align with both human and electronic computers than Turing machines do. Consequently, RBMs challenge the dominance of Turing machines in computer science and beyond. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. The Turing Test is a Thought Experiment.Bernardo Gonçalves - 2023 - Minds and Machines 33 (1):1-31.
    The Turing test has been studied and run as a controlled experiment and found to be underspecified and poorly designed. On the other hand, it has been defended and still attracts interest as a test for true artificial intelligence (AI). Scientists and philosophers regret the test’s current status, acknowledging that the situation is at odds with the intellectual standards of Turing’s works. This article refers to this as the Turing Test Dilemma, following the observation that the test (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  9. The Physical Church–Turing Thesis: Modest or Bold?Gualtiero Piccinini - 2011 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 62 (4):733-769.
    This article defends a modest version of the Physical Church-Turing thesis (CT). Following an established recent trend, I distinguish between what I call Mathematical CT—the thesis supported by the original arguments for CT—and Physical CT. I then distinguish between bold formulations of Physical CT, according to which any physical process—anything doable by a physical system—is computable by a Turing machine, and modest formulations, according to which any function that is computable by a physical system is computable by a (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  10.  86
    Representing the knowledge of turing machines.Hyun Song Shin & Timothy Williamson - 1994 - Theory and Decision 37 (1):125-146.
  11. The Present Theory of Turing Machine Computability.C. E. M. Yates - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (3):513.
  12.  75
    Intension in terms of Turing machines.Pavel Tichý - 1969 - Studia Logica 24 (1):7 - 25.
  13. The irrelevance of Turing machines to AI.Aaron Sloman - 2002 - In Matthias Scheutz (ed.), Computationalism: New Directions. MIT Press.
  14.  28
    Computer Studies of Turing Machine Problems.Shen Lin, Tibor Rado, Allen H. Brady & Milton W. Green - 1975 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (4):617-617.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  9
    On the inference of Turing machines from sample computations.A. W. Biermann - 1972 - Artificial Intelligence 3 (C):181-198.
  16.  16
    Turing's Dream and Searle's Nightmare in Westworld.Lucía Carrillo González - 2018 - In James B. South & Kimberly S. Engels (eds.), Westworld and Philosophy. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 71–78.
    Westworld tells the story of a technologically advanced theme park populated by robots referred to as hosts, who follow a script and rules that the park's operators set up for them. Alan Turing argued that machines think not because they have special powers or because they are like us. Turing's perspective is illustrated perfectly in the show's focus on the hosts. Objecting to Turing's theory, John Searle proposes a situation called the “Chinese room argument”, concluding that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  32
    Three forms of physical measurement and their computability.Edwin Beggs, José Félix Costa & John V. Tucker - 2014 - Review of Symbolic Logic 7 (4):618-646.
    We have begun a theory of measurement in which an experimenter and his or her experimental procedure are modeled by algorithms that interact with physical equipment through a simple abstract interface. The theory is based upon using models of physical equipment as oracles to Turing machines. This allows us to investigate the computability and computational complexity of measurement processes. We examine eight different experiments that make measurements and, by introducing the idea of an observable indicator, we identify three (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. The irrelevance of Turing machines to artificial intelligence.Aaron Sloman - 2002 - In Matthias Scheutz (ed.), Computationalism: New Directions. MIT Press.
    The common view that the notion of a Turing machine is directly relevant to AI is criticised. It is argued that computers are the result of a convergence of two strands of development with a long history: development of machines for automating various physical processes and machines for performing abstract operations on abstract entities, e.g. doing numerical calculations. Various aspects of these developments are analysed, along with their relevance to AI, and the similarities between computers viewed in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  19.  23
    (1 other version)A variant of turing machines requiring print instructions only.J. W. Swanson - 1967 - Logique Et Analyse 10 (1):200-206.
  20. (1 other version)The constructability of artificial intelligence.Bruce Edmonds - 2000 - Journal of Logic Language and Information 9 (4):419-424.
    The Turing Test, as originally specified, centres on theability to perform a social role. The TT can be seen as a test of anability to enter into normal human social dynamics. In this light itseems unlikely that such an entity can be wholly designed in anoff-line mode; rather a considerable period of training insitu would be required. The argument that since we can pass the TT,and our cognitive processes might be implemented as a Turing Machine, that consequently a (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21. What does the Turing test really mean? And how many human beings (including Turing) could pass?Tyler Cowen & Michelle Dawson - unknown
    The so-called Turing test, as it is usually interpreted, sets a benchmark standard for determining when we might call a machine intelligent. We can call a machine intelligent if the following is satisfied: if a group of wise observers were conversing with a machine through an exchange of typed messages, those observers could not tell whether they were talking to a human being or to a machine. To pass the test, the machine has to be intelligent but it also (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22. Even Turing machines can compute uncomputable functions.Jack Copeland - unknown
    Accelerated Turing machines are Turing machines that perform tasks commonly regarded as impossible, such as computing the halting function. The existence of these notional machines has obvious implications concerning the theoretical limits of computability.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  23. The myth of the Turing machine: The failings of functionalism and related theses.Chris Eliasmith - 2002 - Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence 14 (1):1-8.
    The properties of Turing’s famous ‘universal machine’ has long sustained functionalist intuitions about the nature of cognition. Here, I show that there is a logical problem with standard functionalist arguments for multiple realizability. These arguments rely essentially on Turing’s powerful insights regarding computation. In addressing a possible reply to this criticism, I further argue that functionalism is not a useful approach for understanding what it is to have a mind. In particular, I show that the difficulties involved in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  24.  78
    Turing machines and the spectra of first-order formulas.Neil D. Jones & Alan L. Selman - 1974 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 39 (1):139-150.
  25. Accelerating Turing machines.B. Jack Copeland - 2002 - Minds and Machines 12 (2):281-300.
    Accelerating Turing machines are Turing machines of a sort able to perform tasks that are commonly regarded as impossible for Turing machines. For example, they can determine whether or not the decimal representation of contains n consecutive 7s, for any n; solve the Turing-machine halting problem; and decide the predicate calculus. Are accelerating Turing machines, then, logically impossible devices? I argue that they are not. There are implications concerning the nature of (...)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  26. Do Accelerating Turing Machines Compute the Uncomputable?B. Jack Copeland & Oron Shagrir - 2011 - Minds and Machines 21 (2):221-239.
    Accelerating Turing machines have attracted much attention in the last decade or so. They have been described as “the work-horse of hypercomputation” (Potgieter and Rosinger 2010: 853). But do they really compute beyond the “Turing limit”—e.g., compute the halting function? We argue that the answer depends on what you mean by an accelerating Turing machine, on what you mean by computation, and even on what you mean by a Turing machine. We show first that in (...)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  27. (1 other version)Infinite time Turing machines.Joel David Hamkins & Andy Lewis - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (2):567-604.
    Infinite time Turing machines extend the operation of ordinary Turing machines into transfinite ordinal time. By doing so, they provide a natural model of infinitary computability, a theoretical setting for the analysis of the power and limitations of supertask algorithms.
    Direct download (20 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  28. (1 other version)Forms of Luminosity: Epistemic Modality and Hyperintensionality in Mathematics.David Elohim - 2017 - Dissertation, Arché, University of St Andrews
    This book concerns the foundations of epistemic modality and hyperintensionality and their applications to the philosophy of mathematics. David Elohim examines the nature of epistemic modality, when the modal operator is interpreted as concerning both apriority and conceivability, as well as states of knowledge and belief. The book demonstrates how epistemic modality and hyperintensionality relate to the computational theory of mind; metaphysical modality and hyperintensionality; the types of mathematical modality and hyperintensionality; to the epistemic status of large cardinal axioms, undecidable (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  29.  84
    Corrado Böhm. On a family of Turing machines and the related programming language. ICC bulletin, vol. 3 , pp. 185–194.Martin Davis - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (1):140-140.
  30.  20
    Alan Turing's systems of logic: the Princeton thesis.Alan Turing - 2012 - Woodstock, England: Princeton University Press. Edited by Andrew W. Appel & Solomon Feferman.
    Though less well known than his other work, Turings 1938 Princeton Thesis, this title which includes his notion of an oracle machine, has had a lasting influence on computer science and mathematics. It presents a facsimile of the original typescript of the thesis along with essays by Appel and Feferman that explain its still-unfolding significance.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  19
    Turing-Machine Computable Functionals of Finite Types I.S. C. Kleene, Ernest Nagel, Patrick Suppes & Alfred Tarski - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (4):588-589.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32. Super Turing-machines.Jack Copeland - 1998 - Complexity 4 (1):30-32.
    The tape is divided into squares, each square bearing a single symbol—'0' or '1', for example. This tape is the machine's general-purpose storage medium: the machine is set in motion with its input inscribed on the tape, output is written onto the tape by the head, and the tape serves as a short-term working memory for the results of intermediate steps of the computation. The program governing the particular computation that the machine is to perform is also stored on the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  33. Beyond the universal Turing machine.Jack Copeland - 1999 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77 (1):46-67.
    We describe an emerging field, that of nonclassical computability and nonclassical computing machinery. According to the nonclassicist, the set of well-defined computations is not exhausted by the computations that can be carried out by a Turing machine. We provide an overview of the field and a philosophical defence of its foundations.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  34. On Turing machines knowing their own gödel-sentences.Neil Tennant - 2001 - Philosophia Mathematica 9 (1):72-79.
    Storrs McCall appeals to a particular true but improvable sentence of formal arithmetic to argue, by appeal to its irrefutability, that human minds transcend Turing machines. Metamathematical oversights in McCall's discussion of the Godel phenomena, however, render invalid his philosophical argument for this transcendentalist conclusion.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35. The Turing Machine on the Dissecting Table.Jana Horáková - 2013 - Teorie Vědy / Theory of Science 35 (2):269-288.
    Since the beginning of the twenty-first century there has been an increasing awareness that software rep- resents a blind spot in new media theory. The growing interest in software also influences the argument in this paper, which sets out from the assumption that Alan M. Turing's concept of the universal machine, the first theoretical description of a computer program, is a kind of bachelor machine. Previous writings based on a similar hypothesis have focused either on a comparison of the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Are Turing Machines Platonists? Inferentialism and the Computational Theory of Mind.Jon Cogburn & Jason Megil - 2010 - Minds and Machines 20 (3):423-439.
    We first discuss Michael Dummett’s philosophy of mathematics and Robert Brandom’s philosophy of language to demonstrate that inferentialism entails the falsity of Church’s Thesis and, as a consequence, the Computational Theory of Mind. This amounts to an entirely novel critique of mechanism in the philosophy of mind, one we show to have tremendous advantages over the traditional Lucas-Penrose argument.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37. The Demise of the Turing Machine in Complexity Theory.Iain A. Stewart - 1996 - In Peter Millican & Andy Clark (eds.), Machines and Thought: The Legacy of Alan Turing. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
  38.  45
    Infinite Time Turing Machines With Only One Tape.D. E. Seabold & J. D. Hamkins - 2001 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 47 (2):271-287.
    Infinite time Turing machines with only one tape are in many respects fully as powerful as their multi-tape cousins. In particular, the two models of machine give rise to the same class of decidable sets, the same degree structure and, at least for partial functions f : ℝ → ℕ, the same class of computable functions. Nevertheless, there are infinite time computable functions f : ℝ → ℝ that are not one-tape computable, and so the two models of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  39.  40
    Turing Machines, Finite Automata and Neural Nets.Michael A. Arbib - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (3):482-482.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  40. Turing machines and mental reports.Robert H. Kane - 1966 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 44 (3):344-52.
  41.  27
    Theories of Knowledge and Theories of Everything.David H. Wolpert - 2018 - In Wuppuluri Shyam & Francisco Antonio Dorio (eds.), The Map and the Territory: Exploring the Foundations of Science, Thought and Reality. Springer. pp. 165-184.
    There are four types of information an agent can have concerning the state of the universe: information acquired via observation, via control, via prediction, or via retrodiction, i.e., memory. Each of these four types of information appear to rely on a different kind of physical device. However it turns out that there is some mathematical structure that is common to those four types of devices. Any device that possesses that structure is known as an “inference device”. Here I review some (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  47
    Turing machines.David Barker-Plummer - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  43.  46
    (1 other version)Lin Shen and Rado Tibor. Computer studies of Turing machine problems. Journal of the Association for Computing Machinery, vol. 12 , pp. 196–212.Brady Allen H.. The conjectured highest scoring machines for Rado's Σ for the value k = 4. IEEE transactions on electronic computers, vol. EC-15 , pp. 802–803.Green Milton W.. A lower bound on Rado's sigma function for binary Turing machines. Switching circuit theory and logical design, Proceedings of the Fifth Annual Symposium, Princeton University, Princeton, N.J., November 11-13, 1964, The Institute of Electrical and Electronics Engineers, Inc., New York 1964, pp. 91–94. [REVIEW]H. B. Enderton - 1975 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (4):617-617.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  50
    Marvin L. Minsky. Recursive unsolvability of Post's problem of “Tag” and other topics in the theory of Turing machines. Annals of mathematics, second series, vol. 74 , pp. 437–455. [REVIEW]Martin Davis - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (4):654-655.
  45.  44
    Swanson J. W.. A variant of Turing machines requiring print instructions only. Logique et analyse, n.s. vol. 10 , pp. 200–206. [REVIEW]Martin Davis - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (1):134-135.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  63
    (1 other version)The undecidability of the Turing machine immortality problem.Philip K. Hooper - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (2):219-234.
  47. Turing machines and the mind-body problem.J. J. Clarke - 1972 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 23 (February):1-12.
  48.  78
    Weaker variants of infinite time Turing machines.Matteo Bianchetti - 2020 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 59 (3-4):335-365.
    Infinite time Turing machines represent a model of computability that extends the operations of Turing machines to transfinite ordinal time by defining the content of each cell at limit steps to be the lim sup of the sequences of previous contents of that cell. In this paper, we study a computational model obtained by replacing the lim sup rule with an ‘eventually constant’ rule: at each limit step, the value of each cell is defined if and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  49
    Some doubts about Turing machine arguments.James D. Heffernan - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 45 (December):638-647.
    In his article “On Mechanical Recognition” R. J. Nelson brings to bear a branch of mathematical logic called automata theory on problems of artificial intelligence. Specifically he attacks the anti-mechanist claim that “[i]nasmuch as human recognition to a very great extent relies on context and on the ability to grasp wholes with some independence of the quality of the parts, even to fill in the missing parts on the basis of expectations, it follows that computers cannot in principle be programmed (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  35
    Turing machine arguments.R. J. Nelson - 1980 - Philosophy of Science 47 (4):630-633.
    In I used Turing machine arguments to show that computers can recognize humanly recognizable patterns in principle. In 1978 James D. Heffernan has expressed some doubts about such arguments. He does not question the propositions that I defend in the paper, nor the specific arguments in their support. What he does criticize are certain background assumptions.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 969