Results for 'illegitimacy'

111 found
Order:
  1.  33
    Constructing Illegitimacy?: Cartels In Finnish Business Media.Marjo Siltaoja & Meri Vehkaperä - 2008 - Proceedings of the International Association for Business and Society 19:2-15.
    During the past decade, any questionable and illegal behavior of businesses has received significant attention in the media. Thus, taking a critical discursive approach, we investigate how the media constructs any questionable business as illegitimate. Our data draws upon articles dealing with cartels and cartel agreements in Finnish business media covering a five year period 2002-2007. Based on our findings, we suggest that regardless of the globalized business world, socio-cultural history plays an important role in constructing the illegitimacy of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  2.  76
    Constructing Illegitimacy? Cartels and Cartel Agreements in Finnish Business Media from Critical Discursive Perspective.Marjo E. Siltaoja & Meri J. Vehkaperä - 2010 - Journal of Business Ethics 92 (4):493-511.
    During the last decade, any questionable or illegal behaviour on the part of businesses has received considerable attention in the media. Using a critical discursive perspective, we here investigate how the media constructs one type of questionable business as illegitimate. Our data draw upon articles dealing with cartels and cartel agreements in Finnish business media covering the five year period 2002-2007. Our contributions are following: We add to the current literature on CSR and national businesses, suggesting that regardless of globalization (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  3. Imagining Illegitimacy in Classical Greek Literature.Lidia Gambón - 2004 - Circe de Clásicos y Modernos 9:207-209.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  38
    Revising illegitimacy: The use of epithets in the homeric hymn to Hermes.Elizabeth S. Greene - 2005 - Classical Quarterly 55 (02):343-349.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  24
    Governmental Illegitimacy in International Law.Brad R. Roth - 1999 - Oxford University Press UK.
    When is a de facto authority not entitled to be considered a `government' for the purposes of International Law? International reaction to the 1991-4 Haitian crisis is only the most prominent in a series of events that suggest a norm of governmental illegitimacy is emerging to challenge more traditional notions of state sovereignty. This challenge has dramatic implications for two fundamental legal strictures: that against the use or threat of force against a state's political independence, and that against interference (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  47
    Interacting factors affecting illegitimacy in preindustrial northern England.Susan Scott & C. J. Duncan - 1997 - Journal of Biosocial Science 29 (2):151-169.
    Illegitimacy in a historic, single community at Penrith, Cumbria (1557–1812), has been studied using aggregative analysis, family reconstitution and time series analysis. This population was living under extreme conditions of hardship. Long, medium and short wavelength cycles in the rate of illegitimacy have been identified by time series analysis; each represents a different response to social and economic pressures. In a complex interaction of events, the peaks of the cycles in wheat prices were associated with rises in adult (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  23
    Illegitimacy.J. Teichman - 1982 - Journal of Medical Ethics 8 (1):42-43.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. The Illegitimacy of Jesus.Jane Schaberg - 1987
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  32
    Illegitimacy: An Examination of Bastardy.Jenny Teichman - 1985 - Noûs 19 (3):453-456.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10. The Illegitimacy of Appeals to Natural Law in Constitutional Interpretation.Walter Berns - 1996 - In Robert P. George (ed.), Natural law, liberalism, and morality: contemporary essays. New York: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  53
    The illegitimacy of Gettier examples.D. S. G. Schreiber - 1987 - Metaphilosophy 18 (1):49–54.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  12.  64
    The Necessary Illegitimacy of the Whistleblower.Mark Holub - 2010 - Business and Professional Ethics Journal 29 (1-4):85-107.
    This article examines the plight of the whistleblower using elements of organizational legitimacy theory. In recognizing the negative correlation between the actions of the organization and the whistleblower it becomes clear that the continuing legitimacy of the organization necessitates the illegitimacy of the whistleblower. This helps explain the continual blacklisting of the whistleblower and their vilification, resulting in the destruction of both their professional career and their reputation. Only protective legislation will provide any guarantees for the whistleblower.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13. Institutionalising the Illegitimacy of the Comic Strip: the Role of the Act of 16 July 1949 in France.Jean-Matthieu Meon - 2009 - Hermès: La Revue Cognition, communication, politique 54 (2):45 - +.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  28
    The Meaning of Illegitimacy.Kathleen V. Wilkes & J. Teichman - 1981 - Philosophical Review 90 (2):310.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  17
    The Stigma of Illegitimacy Resolved, or Life Is an Alimentary Dream.David L. Anderson - 1993 - Diderot Studies 25:11 - 26.
  16.  25
    Divorce and illegitimacy.Leonard Darwin - 1918 - The Eugenics Review 9 (4):296.
  17.  19
    Governmental Illegitimacy in International Law, Brad Roth , 430 pp., $115 cloth. [REVIEW]Brian Orend - 2001 - Ethics and International Affairs 15 (1):225-228.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Anarchism, Historical Illegitimacy and Civil Disobedience: Reflections on A. John Simmons’ ‘Disobedience and its Objects’.Susanne Sreedhar - 2010 - The Boston University Law Review 90 (4):1833-1846.
  19.  50
    (1 other version)The Meaning of Illegitimacy.G. E. M. Anscombe & J. Teichman - 1979 - Philosophical Quarterly 29 (117):375.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. II. Toward a Concept of Political Illegitimacy.Melvin Richter - 1982 - Political Theory 10 (2):185-214.
  21.  41
    Ebbott (M.) Imagining Illegitimacy in Classical Greek Literature. Pp. xii + 121. Lanham, Boulder, New York and Oxford: Lexington Books, 2003. Paper, £17.99, US$24 (Cased, £44, US$58). ISBN: 978-0-7391-0538-2 (978-0-7391-0537-5 hbk). [REVIEW]E. M. Griffiths - 2007 - The Classical Review 57 (01):16-.
  22. Teichman, Jenny, "Illegitimacy: An Examination of Bastardy". [REVIEW]Vinit Haksar - 1982 - Ethics 93:821.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  44
    The Meaning of Illegitimacy By J. Teichman 3 Derby Street, Cambridge: Englehardt Books, 1978, 90 pp., £1.75. [REVIEW]H. J. Mccloskey - 1980 - Philosophy 55 (212):278-.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. TEICHMAN, J.: "Illegitimacy: A Philosophical Study". [REVIEW]I. Kesarcodi-Watson - 1983 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61:457.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  29
    Birth, marriage and death in illegitimacy: a study in northern Portugal.Augusto Abade & Jaume Bertranpetit - 1995 - Journal of Biosocial Science 27 (4):443-455.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  10
    French Revolutionary Legislation on Illegitimacy 1789-1804. [REVIEW]Ernst Schachtel - 1936 - Zeitschrift für Sozialforschung 5 (3):449-450.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  9
    Economies of Childcare, Debates Over Matter, and the Discursive Illegitimacy of an Educational Philosophy of the Nursery: Re-reading Irigaray after Butler.Zelia Gregoriou - 2013 - Philosophy of Education 69:416-424.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Does it really matter whether a judicial decision is morally legitimate? The practical implications of judicial illegitimacy in a[n] otherwise legitimate state.Kenneth E. Himma - 2007 - In José Rubio Carrecedo (ed.), Political philosophy: new proposals for new questions: proceedings of the 22nd IVR World Congress, Granada 2005, volume II = Filosofía política: nuevas propuestas para nuevas cuestiones. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag.
  29.  15
    Starting a Family in Aberdeen 1961–79: The Significance of Illegitimacy and Abortion.Colin Pritchard & Barbara Thompson - 1982 - Journal of Biosocial Science 14 (2):127-139.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  9
    Disobedience, Nonideal Theory, and Historical Illegitimacy.A. John Simmons - 2016 - In Alan John Simmons (ed.), Boundaries of Authority. New York, US: Oxford University Press USA.
    Chapter 2 examines the justified aims or objects of legal disobedience. It begins with the famous theory of civil disobedience defended by John Rawls. This is contrasted with the approach taken by Henry David Thoreau. The chapter argues that Thoreau’s view permits, where Rawls’s theory is unable to allow, disobedience due to the historically illegitimate subjection of lands and peoples. The Kantian or Rawlsian approach to disobedience is unable to move beyond structural injustice as the justified object of that disobedience. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  96
    Debate: Unequal Consenters and Political Illegitimacy.Elizabeth Edenberg & Marilyn Friedman - 2013 - Journal of Political Philosophy 21 (3):347-360.
    Debates about how to incorporate the severely cognitively disabled into liberal theory typically focus on John Rawls’s assumption that citizens choosing the principles of justice should be understood as full social cooperators. In this paper, we argue that social cooperation is not the fundamental barrier to the inclusion of the severely cognitively disabled. We argue that these persons are excluded from the entire project of liberal legitimacy in virtue of the apparent inability of a severely cognitively disabled person to understand (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  29
    ‘A Healthier and more Hopeful Person’: Illegitimacy, Mental Disorder and the Improved Prognosis of the Adolescent Mother. [REVIEW]Ofra Koffman - 2015 - Journal of Medical Humanities 36 (2):113-126.
    This paper aims to contribute to the exploration of the shift from a problematisation of ‘unwed motherhood’ to ‘teenage motherhood’ in late twentieth century Britain. It does so by exploring the dominant social scientific understanding of ‘unwed mothers’ during the 1950s and 1960s which suggested that these women suffered from a psychological disorder. I then analyse the conceptualisation of ‘adolescent unwed mothers’ exploring why professionals deemed them to be less disturbed than older women in their predicament. This finding is discussed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  45
    Is/Ought Fallacy.Mark T. Nelson - 2018-05-09 - In Robert Arp, Steven Barbone & Michael Bruce (eds.), Bad Arguments. Wiley. pp. 360–363.
    This chapter focuses on one of the common fallacies in Western philosophy called the 'is/ought fallacy (IOF)'. Some philosophers conclude that the IOF is not a logical problem but an epistemological one, meaning that even if inferences like this one are logically valid, they cannot be used epistemologically to warrant anyone's real‐life moral beliefs. Arguments do not warrant their conclusions unless the premises of those arguments are themselves warranted, and in the real world, they say, no one would ever be (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  18
    Ignorantia Facti Excusat: Legal Liability and the Intercultural Significance of Greimas’ “Contrat de Véridition”.Mario Ricca - 2018 - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 31 (1):101-126.
    This essay addresses the relationships between prescription and description in legal rules. The analysis will focus on the culture-laden connotations of factual categories implied in all legal sentences and/or provisions. This investigation is spurred by the need to assess the impact of cultural difference in people’s understanding of legal imperatives and, symmetrically, how that impact is to be considered in the application of law. Differences in ways of categorizing the world could position the cultural pre-understanding required by law, and the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  35.  28
    Business News Framing of Corporate Social Responsibility in the United States and the United Kingdom: Insights From the Implicit and Explicit CSR Framework.Daniel Riffe & Tae Ho Lee - 2019 - Business and Society 58 (4):683-711.
    This study aims to contribute to the understanding of business news coverage of corporate social responsibility within a comparative international context by investigating two business newspapers, The Wall Street Journal from the United States and The Financial Times from the United Kingdom. Drawing on the news framing research and the implicit and explicit CSR framework of Matten and Moon, this content analysis shows that business news coverage of CSR in the United States and in the United Kingdom differs in terms (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  36. Wittgenstein, Carnap and the new american Wittgensteinians.P. M. S. Hacker - 2003 - Philosophical Quarterly 53 (210):01–23.
    James Conant, a proponent of the ‘New American Wittgenstein’, has argued that the standard inter- pretation of Wittgenstein is wholly mistaken in respect of Wittgenstein’s critique of metaphysics and the attendant conception of nonsense. The standard interpretation, Conant holds, misascribes to Wittgenstein Carnapian views on the illegitimacy of metaphysical utterances, on logical syntax and grammar, and on the nature of nonsense. Against this account, I argue that (i) Carnap is misrepresented; (ii) the so-called standard interpretation (in so far as (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  37.  38
    Direct Inference, Reichenbach's Principle, and the Sleeping Beauty Problem.Terry Horgan - 2019 - Episteme:1-14.
    A group of philosophers led by the late John Pollock has applied a method of reasoning about probability, known as direct inference and governed by a constraint known as Reichenbach's principle, to argue in support of ‘thirdism’ concerning the Sleeping Beauty Problem. A subsequent debate has ensued about whether their argument constitutes a legitimate application of direct inference. Here I defend the argument against two extant objections charging illegitimacy. One objection can be overcome via a natural and plausible definition, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38. Epistemic Vices in Organizations: Knowledge, Truth, and Unethical Conduct.Christopher Baird & Thomas S. Calvard - 2019 - Journal of Business Ethics 160 (1):263-276.
    Recognizing that truth is socially constructed or that knowledge and power are related is hardly a novelty in the social sciences. In the twenty-first century, however, there appears to be a renewed concern regarding people’s relationship with the truth and the propensity for certain actors to undermine it. Organizations are highly implicated in this, given their central roles in knowledge management and production and their attempts to learn, although the entanglement of these epistemological issues with business ethics has not been (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  39.  37
    Speak No Evil? Conscience and the Duty to Inform, Refer or Transfer Care.Mark P. Aulisio & Kavita Shah Arora - 2014 - HEC Forum 26 (3):257-266.
    This paper argues that the type of conscience claims made in last decade’s spate of cases involving pharmacists’ objections to filling birth control prescriptions and cases such as Ms. Means and Mercy Health Partners of Michigan, and even the Affordable Care Act and the Little Sisters of the Poor, as different as they appear to be from each other, share a common element that ties them together and makes them fundamentally different in kind from traditional claims of conscience about which (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  40. Mill and the Liberal Rejection of Legal Moralism.Piers Norris Turner - 2015 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 32 (1):79-99.
    This article examines John Stuart Mill's position as the principal historical opponent of legal moralism. I argue that inattention to the particular form of his opposition to legal moralism has muddied the interpretation of his liberty principle. Specifically, Mill does not endorse what I call the illegitimacy thesis, according to which appeals to harmless wrongdoings, whether or not they exist, are illegitimate in the justification of legal interference.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  4
    Past, Present, and Future: A Reply to Heyd and Benbaji.Raef Zreik - 2024 - Analyse & Kritik 46 (2):365-386.
    In this paper I respond to the replies of David Heyd and Yitzhak Benbaji to my paper ‘War and Self-Defense: Reflections on the War on Gaza’. Heyd’s relativizing of narrative overlooks the epistemic hierarchy among narratives and their important role in establishing facts, and his claim that Israel’s history is not colonialist in character fails because it is based on a misunderstanding of colonialism in general and settler colonialism in particular. Historically, I outline how Benbaji’s appeal to the legal status (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  81
    The Legitimacy of Loan Maturity Mismatching: A Risky, but not Fraudulent, Undertaking.Philipp Bagus & David Howden - 2009 - Journal of Business Ethics 90 (3):399-406.
    Barnett and Block (Journal of Business Ethics, 2009 ) attack the heart of modern banking by claiming that the practice of borrowing short and lending long is illicit. While their claim of illegitimacy concerning fractional reserve banking can be defended, their justification lacks substance. Their claim is herein strengthened by a legal analysis of deposits and loans based on Huerta de Soto (Money, Bank Credit and Economic Cycles, 2006 ). A combined legal and economic analysis shows that while lending (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  43.  65
    A Comment on Barnett and Block on Time Deposit and Bagus and Howden on Loan Maturity Mismatching.Nicolás Cachanosky - 2011 - Journal of Business Ethics 104 (2):219-221.
    In Time Deposits, Dimension, and Fraud (2009), William Barnett and Walter Block argue that by borrowing short and lending long there is an over issuance of property rights. Their article, however, does not fully extend the consequences of their contribution. Once this is done, it becomes clearer that their argument suits a great impediment to banking, becoming a possible reason to support rather than to oppose fractional reserve banking. Bagus and Howden (J Bus Ethics 90(3):399–406, 2009) comment on Barnett and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  44.  34
    Empirical Realism and the Legitimacy of Ontology: A Dialogue.Dustin McWherter - 2015 - Journal of Critical Realism 14 (5):449-460.
    The purpose of this dialogue between an ‘empirical realist’ and a ‘traditional ontologist’ is to clarify and evaluate the presuppositions of the kind of anti-ontological position exemplified by empirical realism. After ontology is defined and the empirical realist's position explained, the traditional ontologist pursues a series of dialectical developments and criticisms of the empirical realist's claim to have a coherently non-ontological position. The eventual conclusion is that the empirical realist's opposition to ontology just arbitrarily assumes ontology to be associated with (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45. The meaning of meaning.A. Cornelius Benjamin - 1937 - Philosophy of Science 4 (2):282.
    The term qittīer designates the act of burning the food offerings, the 'iššîm, within the ritual sequence of all three types of sacrifice, the zébach, the ōlāh, and the minchāh. Incense is not an 'iššeh substance and is never associated with this piel conjugation. Qittēr appears to have been limited to intransitive use, while the synonyms hiqtîr and heelāh were used predominantly in transitive constructions. By the exilic or post-exilic period, hiqtîr seems to have become the preferred form for intransitive (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  33
    Rethinking religion and political legitimacy across the Islam–West divide.Nader Hashemi - 2014 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 40 (4-5):439-447.
    The relationship between religion and politics is a bone of political contention and a source of deep confusion across the Islam–West divide. When most western liberals cast their gaze on Muslim societies today, what they see is deeply disconcerting. From their perspective there is simply too much religion in public life in the Arab-Islamic world, which raises serious questions for them about the prospects for democracy in this part of the world. This article critically explores the relationship between religion and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  35
    Natural diversity: A neo-essentialist misconstrual of homeostatic property cluster theory in natural kind debates.Joachim Lipski - 2020 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 82 (C):94-103.
    In natural kind debates, Boyd's famous Homeostatic Property Cluster theory (HPC) is often misconstrued in two ways: Not only is it thought to make for a normative standard for natural kinds, but also to require the homeostatic mechanisms underlying nomological property clusters to be uniform. My argument for the illegitimacy of both overgeneralizations, both on systematic as well as exegetical grounds, is based on the misconstrued view's failure to account for functional kinds in science. I illustrate the combination of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48.  17
    (1 other version)Is the Concept of Violence Normative?Jason Wyckoff - 2006 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 235 (1):337-352.
    Legitimist definitions of 'violence' are those that make explicit reference to the illegality, illegitimacy, or wrongfulness of the acts classified as acts of violence. All acts of violence, according to the legitimist definitions, involve a violation of some kind. I defend the view that legitimist definitions are defective—that notions like “wrongness” and “violation” are not part of the concept of violence. I offer three lines of argument: (1) that legitimist definitions of “violence” reduce the doctrine of nonviolence to a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Cavell and the Comedy of Remarriage.Edwin Curley - 1988 - Philosophy Research Archives 14:581-603.
    This paper deals critically with Stanley Cavell’s Pursuits of Happiness, a study of seven film comedies from the 30’s and 40’s, among them The Philadelphia Story, His Girl Friday, Adam’s Rib, and It Happened One Night. Negatively, I argue that Cavell’s interpretations of the films he deals with are often extravagant, if held to any objective standard; that his conception of the genre of the comedy of remarriage is highly arbitrary, both in its inclusions and exclusions, and in its contention (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Tolerance and religious pluralism in Bayle.Marta García-Alonso - 2019 - History of European Ideas 45 (6):803-816.
    For the philosopher of Rotterdam, religious coercion has two essential sources of illegitimacy: the linking of religious and ecclesiastical belief and the use of politics for religious purposes. Bayle responds to it, with his doctrine of freedom of conscience, on one hand and by means of the essential distinction between voluntary religious affiliation and political obligation, on the other hand. From my perspective, his doctrine of tolerance does not involve an atheist state, nor does it mean the rejection of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
1 — 50 / 111