Results for 'Keith Gibbins'

959 found
Order:
  1. Partial belief as a solution to the logical problem of holding simultaneous, contrary beliefs in self-deception research.Keith Gibbins - 1997 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20 (1):115-116.
    A major worry in self-deception research has been the implication that people can hold a belief that something is true and false at the same time: a logical as well as a psychological impossibility. However, if beliefs are held with imperfect confidence, voluntary self-deception in the sense of seeking evidence to reject an unpleasant belief becomes entirely plausible and demonstrably real.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Proper names and identifying descriptions.Keith S. Donnellan - 1970 - Synthese 21 (3-4):335 - 358.
  3.  41
    The Case for Investment Advising as a Virtue-Based Practice.Keith D. Wyma - 2015 - Journal of Business Ethics 127 (1):231-249.
    Contemporary virtue ethics was revolutionized by Alasdair MacIntyre’s reconfiguration using practices as the starting point for understanding virtues. However, MacIntyre has very pointedly excluded the professions of the financial world from the reformulation. He does not count these professions as practices, and further charges that virtue would actually hinder or even rule out one’s pursuit of these professions. This paper addresses three tasks, in regard to the financial profession of investment advising. First, the paper lays out MacIntyre’s soon-to-be-published charges against (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  4.  57
    Truth, Evidence, and Inference.Keith Lehrer - 1974 - American Philosophical Quarterly 11 (2):79 - 92.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5. “Bamboozled by Our Own Words”: Semantic Blindness and Some Arguments Against Contextualism.Keith Derose - 2006 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (2):316 - 338.
    The best grounds for accepting contextualism concerning knowledge attributions are to be found in how knowledge-attributing (and knowledge-denying) sentences are used in ordinary, nonphilosophical talk: What ordinary speakers will count as “knowledge” in some non-philosophical contexts they will deny is such in others. Contextualists typically appeal to pairs of cases that forcefully display the variability in the epistemic standards that govern ordinary usage: A “low standards” case (henceforth, “LOW”) in which a speaker seems quite appropriately and truthfully to ascribe knowledge (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  6. Plurals and complexes.Keith Hossack - 2000 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51 (3):411-443.
    Atomism denies that complexes exist. Common-sense metaphysics may posit masses, composite individuals and sets, but atomism says there are only simples. In a singularist logic, it is difficult to make a plausible case for atomism. But we should accept plural logic, and then atomism can paraphrase away apparent reference to complexes. The paraphrases require unfamiliar plural universals, but these are of independent interest; for example, we can identify numbers and sets with plural universals. The atomist paraphrases would fail if plurals (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  7. Evaluation and consciousness.Keith Lehrer - 1997 - In Self-trust: a study of reason, knowledge, and autonomy. New York: Oxford University Press.
  8. Partial Belief and Flat-out Belief.Keith Frankish - 2009 - In Franz Huber & Christoph Schmidt-Petri (eds.), Degrees of belief. London: Springer. pp. 75--93.
    There is a duality in our everyday view of belief. On the one hand, we sometimes speak of credence as a matter of degree. We talk of having some level of confidence in a claim (that a certain course of action is safe, for example, or that a desired event will occur) and explain our actions by reference to these degrees of confidence – tacitly appealing, it seems, to a probabilistic calculus such as that formalized in Bayesian decision theory. On (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  9. Is classical mechanics really time-reversible and deterministic?Keith Hutchison - 1993 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44 (2):307-323.
  10. Reference and paradox.Keith Simmons - 2003 - In J. C. Beall (ed.), Liars and Heaps: New Essays on Paradox. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press UK. pp. 230--252.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  11.  26
    Interpretation, representation, and deductive reasoning.Keith Stenning & Michiel van Lambalgen - 2008 - In Jonathan Eric Adler & Lance J. Rips (eds.), Reasoning: Studies of Human Inference and its Foundations. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 223-248.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  40
    The IRB paradox: Could the protectors also encourage deceit?Patricia Keith-Spiegel & Gerald P. Koocher - 2005 - Ethics and Behavior 15 (4):339 – 349.
    The efforts of some institutional review boards (IRBs) to exercise what is viewed as appropriate oversight may contribute to deceit on the part of investigators who feel unjustly treated. An organizational justice paradigm provides a useful context for exploring why certain IRB behaviors may lead investigators to believe that they have not received fair treatment. These feelings may, in turn, lead to intentional deception by investigators that IRBs will rarely detect. Paradoxically, excessive protective zeal by IRBs may actually encourage misconduct (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  13. Charles Taylor: Modernity, Freedom and Community.Keith Spence - 2003 - University of Wales Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  15
    Bilateralism and Community in Treaty Law and Practice–From Warriors, Workers and (Hook-) Worms.Kenneth J. Keith - 2011 - In Ulrich Fastenrath, Rudolf Geiger, Daniel-Erasmus Khan, Andreas Paulus, Sabine von Schorlemer & Christoph Vedder (eds.), From Bilateralism to Community Interest: Essays in Honour of Judge Bruno Simma. Oxford University Press. pp. 754--767.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  26
    God and Propositions.Keith Yandell - 2011 - Philosophia Christi 13 (2):275-287.
    If there are abstract objects, they necessarily exist. The majority view among contemporary philosophers of religion who are theists is that God also necessarily exists. Nonetheless, that God has necessary existence has not been shown to be true, or even (informally) consistent. It seems consistent—at least is does not seem (informally) inconsistent—but neither does its denial. Arguments that necessary existence is a perfection, and God has all perfections, assume that Necessitarian Theism is true, and hence consistent. Thus they do not (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  16.  38
    A Gross and Palpable Contradiction?: Incarnation and Consistency.Keith E. Yandell - 1994 - Sophia 33 (3):30 - 45.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  17.  40
    Theism and evil: A reply.Keith E. Yandell - 1972 - Sophia 11 (1):1-7.
  18. Pragmatic reasoning with a point of view.Keith J. Holyoak & Patricia W. Cheng - 1995 - Thinking and Reasoning 1 (4):289 – 313.
  19.  15
    The Math Gene: How Mathematical Thinking Evolved And Why Numbers Are Like Gossip.Keith Devlin & Professor Keith Devlin - 2000
    Explains how our innate pattern-making abilities allow us to perform mathematical reasoning.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  20. Induction, reason and consistency.Keith Lehrer - 1970 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 21 (1):103-114.
  21.  38
    Ethics, evils and theism.Keith E. Yandell - 1969 - Sophia 8 (2):18-28.
  22. Is Kuhn a sociologist?Keith Jones - 1986 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37 (4):443-452.
  23.  98
    A just response to climate change: Personal carbon allowances and the normal-functioning approach.Keith Hyams - 2009 - Journal of Social Philosophy 40 (2):237-256.
  24.  6
    Before the luddites. Custom, community and machinery in the English woollen industry, 1776–1809.Keith Wrightson - 1994 - History of European Ideas 18 (2):298-299.
  25.  22
    The Nature of a Practice’s Goods.Keith Wyma - 2019 - Business Ethics Journal Review 7 (5):27-33.
    Daniel Sportiello argues that my support of financial planning as a MacIntyrean practice fails because I have misunderstood the concept of internal goods, and because financial planning then has no internal good at all. Here, I rebut those charges.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  17
    11. Divine Necessity and Divine Goodness.Keith E. Yandell - 1988 - In Thomas V. Morris (ed.), Divine and Human Action: Essays in the Metaphysics of Theism. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. pp. 313-344.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  22
    Empiricism and theism.Keith Yandell - 1968 - Sophia 7 (3):3-11.
  28.  54
    On interpreting the "bhagavadgītā".Keith E. Yandell - 1982 - Philosophy East and West 32 (1):37-46.
  29.  22
    Reply to Nielsen.Keith Yandell - 1968 - Sophia 7 (3):18-19.
  30.  44
    Some reflections on Indian metaphysics.Keith E. Yandell - 2001 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 50 (1/3):171-190.
  31.  61
    Tragedy and evil.Keith E. Yandell - 1994 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 36 (1):1 - 26.
  32.  42
    The Non-Epistemic Explanation of Religious Belief.Keith E. Yandell - 1990 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 27 (1/2):87 - 120.
    The preceding two sections have considered, respectively, the discreditation of psychological belief, and of propositional belief, which begins with the claim that a belief possessed by some person is non-epistemically explicable and ends with the claim that that person is unreasonable or that that belief is (probably) false. Obviously, only certain strategies of discreditation were discussed, and those only partially. But if the examples of discrediting strategies were representative, and the remarks made about them were correct, what, if anything, follows?It (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Using Variability to Guide Dimensional Weighting: Associative Mechanisms in Early Word Learning.Keith S. Apfelbaum & Bob McMurray - 2011 - Cognitive Science 35 (6):1105-1138.
    At 14 months, children appear to struggle to apply their fairly well-developed speech perception abilities to learning similar sounding words (e.g., bih/dih; Stager & Werker, 1997). However, variability in nonphonetic aspects of the training stimuli seems to aid word learning at this age. Extant theories of early word learning cannot account for this benefit of variability. We offer a simple explanation for this range of effects based on associative learning. Simulations suggest that if infants encode both noncontrastive information (e.g., cues (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  34.  71
    The atom in the chemistry curriculum: Fundamental concept, teaching model or epistemological obstacle?Keith S. Taber - 2003 - Foundations of Chemistry 5 (1):43-84.
    Research into learners' ideas aboutscience suggests that school and collegestudents often hold alternative conceptionsabout `the atom'. This paper discusses whylearners acquire ideas about atoms which areincompatible with the modern scientificunderstanding. It is suggested that learners'alternative ideas derive – at least in part –from the way ideas about atoms are presented inthe school and college curriculum. Inparticular, it is argued that the atomicconcept met in science education is anincoherent hybrid of historical models, andthat this explains why learners commonlyattribute to atoms properties (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  35.  92
    What are conditional probabilities conditional upon?Keith Hutchison - 1999 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 50 (4):665-695.
    This paper rejects a traditional epistemic interpretation of conditional probability. Suppose some chance process produces outcomes X, Y,..., with probabilities P(X), P(Y),... If later observation reveals that outcome Y has in fact been achieved, then the probability of outcome X cannot normally be revised to P(X|Y) ['P&Y)/P(Y)]. This can only be done in exceptional circumstances - when more than just knowledge of Y-ness has been attained. The primary reason for this is that the weight of a piece of evidence varies (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  36.  74
    Social consensus and rational agnoiology.Keith Lehrer - 1975 - Synthese 31 (1):141-160.
  37.  47
    Ethics education in the consulting engineering environment: Where do we start?Keith E. Elder - 2004 - Science and Engineering Ethics 10 (2):325-336.
    As a result of in-house discussions stimulated by previous Gonzaga engineering ethics conferences, Coffman Engineers began the implementation of what is to be a company-wide ethics training program. While preparing a curriculum aimed at consulting engineers, we found very little guidance as to how to proceed with most available literature being oriented towards the academic environment. We consulted a number of resources that address the teaching of engineering ethics in higher education, but questioned their applicability for the Consulting Engineering environment. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  71
    Non-monotonic inference.Keith Frankish - 2005 - In Keith Brown (ed.), Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics. Elsevier.
    In most logical systems, inferences cannot be invalidated simply by the addition of new premises. If an inference can be drawn from a set of premises S, then it can also be drawn from any larger set incorporrating S. The truth of the original premises guarantees the truth of the inferred conclusion, and the addition of extra premises cannot undermine it. This property is known as monotonicity. Nonmonotonic inference lacks this property. The conclusions drawn are provisional, and new information may (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  39. The Double Standard.Keith Thomas - 1959 - Journal of the History of Ideas 20 (1/4):195.
  40.  57
    Deleuze IN UTERO : Deleuze-Sartre and the essence of woman.Keith W. Faulkner - 2002 - Angelaki 7 (3):25 – 43.
  41.  71
    The Ethical Implications of Illusionism.Keith Frankish - 2024 - Neuroethics 17 (2):1-15.
    Illusionism is a revisionary view of consciousness, which denies the existence of the phenomenal properties traditionally thought to render experience conscious. The view has theoretical attractions, but some think it also has objectionable ethical implications. They take illusionists to be denying the existence of consciousness itself, or at least of the thing that gives consciousness its ethical value, and thus as undermining our established ethical attitudes. This article responds to this objection. I argue that, properly understood, illusionism neither denies the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  44
    (1 other version)RepliesSelf-Trust: A Study of Reason, Knowledge and Autonomy.Keith Lehrer - 1999 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (4):1065.
  43.  95
    Social Information.Keith Lehrer - 1977 - The Monist 60 (4):473-487.
    There are those philosophers and historians of science who claim that the acceptance and rejection of scientific theories is underdetermined by experimental results. They conclude that there is no rational method for deciding such matters solely on the basis of empirical information. The acceptance and rejection of scientific theories depends on social influence and is settled by social dominance. This I call the dominance thesis. There are also those who hold, on the contrary, that the acceptance and rejection of theories (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  44. The importance of historical accuracy in philosophy of science: The case of Curd's conception of copernican rationality.Keith A. Nier - 1986 - Philosophy of Science 53 (3):372-394.
    General discussions of the appropriate relations between history and philosophy of science must be complemented by examinations of particular studies involving both fields. Martin Curd's attempt to illuminate the rationality of theory change through analysis of the Copernican Revolution is such a study; his work is undercut by serious flaws and actually displays an ahistorical approach. The result misleads both about the Copernican Revolution and the general problem of theory change in science. The study does illustrate several types of failing (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Augustine and the Good Life.Keith Hess & Matthew Flummer - forthcoming - B&H Academic.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  3
    (1 other version)Making sense of a pedagogic text.Keith S. Taber - 2021 - Foundations of Chemistry 23 (3):433-457.
  47.  37
    ‘Education for capability’: A critique.Keith Thompson - 1984 - British Journal of Educational Studies 32 (3):203-212.
  48.  34
    Coherence, justification, and Chisholm.Keith Lehrer - 1988 - Philosophical Perspectives 2:125-138.
  49. Temporal asymmetry in classical mechanics.Keith Hutchison - 1995 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46 (2):219-234.
    This paper argues against a standard view that all deterministic and conservative classical mechanical systems are time-reversible, by asking how the temporal evolution of a system modulates parametric imprecision (either ontological or epistemic). It notes that well-behaved systems (e.g. inertial motion) can possess a dynamics which is unstable enough to fail at reversing uncertainties—even though exact values are reliably reversed. A limited (but significant) source of irreversibility is thus displayed in classical mechanics, closely analogous the lack of predictability revealed by (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  50.  28
    W. J. M. Rankine and the Rise of Thermodynamics.Keith Hutchison - 1981 - British Journal for the History of Science 14 (1):1-26.
    In the history of thermodynamics, two dates stand out as especially important: 1824, when Sadi Carnot's brilliant memoirRéflexions sur la puissance motrice du feuappeared in print; and 1850, when Rudolf Clausius published his similarly titled paper ‘Ueber die bewegende Kraft der Wärme’. In this paper Clausius narrowly beat the Scottish physicist William Thomson to the solution of a puzzle which had been highlighted in the latter's recent publications: how could Carnot's theory, with all its intellectual attractions, be reconciled with the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 959