View year:

  1.  45
    On justifying case verdicts. A dialectical hypothesis.Adriano Angelucci - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):297-317.
    The method of cases (MOC), as standardly construed, involves an evidential appeal to intuitions. Philosophers, however, often argue for their case verdicts, they offer reasons for accepting their truth. According to Max Deutsch and Herman Cappelen – whose ground-breaking case studies first drew attention to this underappreciated phenomenon – their reason-giving would constitute compelling evidence that, contrary to the received view, philosophers relying on MOC regard arguments, not intuitions, as their main justificatory source. This explanatory hypothesis has met with substantial (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  5
    Logical contextualism.Paal Fjeldvig Antonsen - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):854-873.
    This paper outlines a contextualist version of logical pluralism. One motivation for this idea comes from a desire to block a principal argument against pluralism called ‘the meaning-variance objection’. The paper also gives two contextualist analyses of validity: one according to which ‘is valid’ is use-sensitive, another according to which it is assessment-sensitive. It argues that local pluralists should accept the former, while global pluralists should accept the latter.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  7
    Rules as constitutive practices defined by correlated equilibria.Ásgeir Berg - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):874-908.
    In this paper, I present a game-theoretic solution to the rule-following paradox in terms of what I will call basic constitutive practices. The structure of such a practice P constitutes what it is to take part in P by defining the correctness conditions of our most basic concepts as those actions that lie on the correlated equilibrium of P itself. Accordingly, an agent S meant addition by his use of the term ‘+’ because S is taking part in a basic (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Time-Slice Epistemology for Bayesians.Lisa Cassell - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):428–451.
    Recently, some have challenged the idea that there are genuine norms of diachronic rationality. Part of this challenge has involved offering replacements for diachronic principles. Skeptics about diachronic rationality believe that we can provide an error theory for it by appealing to synchronic updating rules that, over time, mimic the behavior of diachronic norms. In this paper, I argue that the most promising attempts to develop this position within the Bayesian framework are unsuccessful. I sketch a new synchronic surrogate that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  12
    Transformative experiences and the equivocation objection.Yuri Cath - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):570-591.
    Paul, L. A. (2014. Transformative Experience. Oxford University Press) argues that one cannot rationally decide whether to have a transformative experience by trying to form judgments, in advance, about (i) what it would feel like to have that experience, and (ii) the subjective value of having such an experience. The problem is if you haven’t had the experience then you cannot know what it is like, and you need to know what it is like to assess its value. However, in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  25
    Towards an ethics of conceptual engineering.Roger Crisp - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):755-768.
    This paper is a prolegomenon to an ethics of conceptual engineering. Ethics is construed as primarily concerned with reasons for action, not belief, and it is argued that most such reasons are to be understood in terms of their connection with well-being. In the case of conceptual engineering, this is the well-being of the engineer and of others. There are alethic reasons for conceptual engineering, but they are derivative, as are many of the philosophical norms applying within conceptual engineering itself, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  22
    Two notions of resemblance and the semantics of ‘what it's like’.Justin D'Ambrosio & Daniel Stoljar - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):743-754.
    According to the resemblance account of ‘what it's like’ and similar constructions, a sentence such as ‘there is something it's like to have a toothache’ means ‘there is something having a toothache resembles’. This account has proved controversial in the literature; some writers endorse it, many reject it. We show that this conflict is illusory. Drawing on the semantics of intensional transitive verbs, we show that there are two versions of the resemblance account, depending on whether ‘resembles’ is construed notionally (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  8
    Future, truth, and probability.Ciro De Florio & Aldo Frigerio - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):251-263.
    According to some scholars, universalist semantics of the future are incompatible with classical ascriptions of probability. This alleged fact is used as an argument for the linearist semantics of the future. In this paper, we show that, on the contrary, universalist semantics of the future are in harmony with the theory of probability, while the advocates of linearist semantics have to pay high theoretical costs to maintain the coherence with the classical theory of probability.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  83
    Haecceitism without individuals.Catharine Diehl - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):909-935.
    According to anti-individualism, the basic building blocks of the world are not individuals. The anti-individualist argues that standard, individual-entailing claims–for instance, that Theia is a cat–are mistaken in presupposing that there are individuals, but that such claims correspond to statements in a feature-placing language devoid of these presuppositions. Instead, the world is entirely made up of non-individualistic features–structurally akin to familiar examples such as it's raining or it's snowing–that are arranged in particular ways. Since features do not carve out individual (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  37
    Pluralist conceptual engineering.Tamara Dobler - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):224-250.
    Building on Wittgenstein’s ideas, I defend a brand of pluralism that associates words with conceptual families and appeals to this notion in the course of philosophical problem solving. I argue that certain problems that the received view of conceptual engineering (‘improvement by replacement’) faces can be more easily overcome if we adopt a pluralist perspective. I show that the proposed approach can circumvent the problem of topic discontinuity, whilst also avoiding the threat of trivialisation, since it can easily accommodate both (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11.  3
    Grounding and properties.August Faller - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):592-616.
    Metaphysical grounding is often presented as a relation of directed dependence analogous to causation. The relationship between causation, properties, and laws of nature is hotly debated. I ask: what is the relationship between grounding, properties, and laws of metaphysics? I begin by considering the grounding analogue of Humean quidditism. Finding it implausible, I turn to the primitive-laws account of grounding, recently defended by Jonathan Schaffer and others. I argue this view is also unsatisfactory. I then present several possible dispositionalist-like accounts (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  3
    On Frege’s supposed hierarchy of senses.Nicholas Georgalis - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):696-717.
    This paper argues against the claim that Frege is committed to an infinite hierarchy of senses. Carnap and Kripke, along with many others, argue the contrary; I expose where all such arguments go astray. Invariably these arguments assume (without citation) that Frege holds that sense and reference are always distinct. This is the fulcrum upon which the hierarchy is hoisted. The counter to this assumption is based on two important but neglected passages. The locution ‘indirect sense’ has no ontological significance (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  62
    The embodied, relational self: extending or rejecting the mind?Joseph Gough - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):663-695.
    In putting forward the modern concept of mind, Descartes identified the mind with the self. Recently, communitarian and feminist scholars have argued in favor of a conception of the self according to which it includes relations to the social world and parts of the body. If they are correct, it initially seems damning for the view that the self is the mind. I examine whether this is so, by considering whether the identification of self and mind can be saved by (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. The Fundamental Divisions in Ethics.Matthew Hammerton - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):318-341.
    What are the fundamental divisions in ethics? Which divisions capture the most important and basic options in moral theorizing? In this article, I reject the ‘Textbook View’ which takes the tripartite division between consequentialism, deontology, and virtue ethics to be fundamental. Instead, I suggest that moral theories are fundamentally divided into three independent divisions, which I call the neutral/relative division, the normative priority division, and the maximizing division. I argue that this account of the fundamental divisions of ethics better captures (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  5
    The fundamental divisions in ethics.Matthew Hammerton - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):318-341.
    What are the fundamental divisions in ethics? Which divisions capture the most important and basic options in moral theorizing? In this article, I reject the ‘Textbook View’ which takes the tripartite division between consequentialism, deontology, and virtue ethics to be fundamental. Instead, I suggest that moral theories are fundamentally divided into three independent divisions, which I call the neutral/relative division, the normative priority division, and the maximizing division. I argue that this account of the fundamental divisions of ethics better captures (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  81
    Russellians should have a no proposition view of empty names.Thomas Hodgson - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):826-853.
    Empty names are a problem for Russellians. I describe three ways to approach solving the problem. These are positing gappy propositions as contents, nonsingular propositions as contents, or denying that sentences containing empty names have contents. I discuss methods for deciding between solutions. I then argue for some methods over others and defend one solution using those methods. I reject the arguments that either intuitions about truth value, truth, content, or meaningfulness can decide between the solutions. I give an alternative (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  9
    Pistols, pills, pork and ploughs: the structure of technomoral revolutions.J. K. G. Hopster, C. Arora, C. Blunden, C. Eriksen, L. E. Frank, J. S. Hermann, M. B. O. T. Klenk, E. R. H. O’Neill & S. Steinert - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):264-296.
    The power of technology to transform religions, science, and political institutions has often been presented as nothing short of revolutionary. Does technology have a similarly transformative influence on societies’ morality? Scholars have not rigorously investigated the role of technology in moral revolutions, even though existing research on technomoral change suggests that this role may be considerable. In this paper, we explore what the role of technology in moral revolutions, understood as processes of radical group-level moral change, amounts to. We do (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18. Pistols, pills, pork and ploughs: the structure of technomoral revolutions.Jeroen Hopster, Chirag Arora, Charlie Blunden, Cecilie Eriksen, Lily Frank, Julia Hermann, Michael Klenk, Elizabeth O'Neill & Steffen Steinert - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):264-296.
    The power of technology to transform religions, science, and political institutions has often been presented as nothing short of revolutionary. Does technology have a similarly transformative influence on societies’ morality? Scholars have not rigorously investigated the role of technology in moral revolutions, even though existing research on technomoral change suggests that this role may be considerable. In this paper, we explore what the role of technology in moral revolutions, understood as processes of radical group-level moral change, amounts to. We do (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  19.  3
    Sex and the city: Rousseau on sexual freedom and its modern discontents.Gal Katz - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):617-642.
    Like some ‘second wave’ feminists, Rousseau believes that modern sexual practices are not a manifestation of a newfound autonomy—rather, they reflect its systemic deprivation. Drawing on his critique of libertine culture in eighteenth century Paris, I show how even consensual sex may lead to a chronic deficit of recognition, coupled with psychological misery. To avoid such discontents, sexual freedom must include a satisfying sexual recognition. I articulate the conditions for such recognition as cultivated in Emile’s erotic education. Informed by amour-propre, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  10
    Identity: this time it's personal.Stephen Kearns - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):342-367.
    The view that it is possible for someone to think at a time without existing at that time is not only perfectly coherent but in harmony with an attractive externalist view of the mental. Furthermore, it offers plausible solutions to various puzzles of personal identity.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  18
    On the connection between lying, asserting, and intending to cause beliefs.Vladimir Krstić - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):643-662.
    According to one influential argument put forward by, e.g. Chisholm and Feehan, Pfister, Meibauer, Dynel, Keiser, and Harris, asserting requires intending to give your hearer a reason to believe what you say (first premise) and, because liars must assert what they believe is false (second premise), liars necessarily intend to cause their hearer to believe as true what the liars believe is false (conclusion). According to this argument, that is, all genuine lies are intended to deceive. ‘Lies’ not intended to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  3
    Cognitive phenomenology: in defense of recombination.Preston Lennon - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):483-512.
    The cognitive experience view of thought holds that the content of thought is determined by its cognitive-phenomenal character. Adam Pautz argues that the cognitive experience view is extensionally inadequate: it entails the possibility of mix-and-match cases, where the cognitive-phenomenal properties that determine thought content are combined with different sensory-phenomenal and functional properties. Because mix-and-match cases are metaphysically impossible, Pautz argues, the cognitive experience view should be rejected. This paper defends the cognitive experience view from Pautz’s argument. I build on resources (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23. Is Forgiveness Openness to Reconciliation?Cathy Mason & Matt Dougherty - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):215-223.
    In a recent paper, Strabbing (2020) argues that forgiveness is openness to reconciliation relative to a relationship level. In this paper, we argue that the openness-to-reconciliation account of forgiveness does not constitute an improvement on the forswearing-resentment account. We argue that it does not fit well with our ordinary practices of forgiving and cannot allow for plausible cases of forgiveness without reconciliation. We also argue that the features Strabbing identifies as distinct advantages of her account are features of the forswearing-resentment (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  5
    There are no uninstantiated words.J. T. M. Miller - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):209-214.
    Kaplan ([1990]. “Words.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 64: 93–119; [2011]. “Words on Words.” The Journal of Philosophy 108 (9): 504–529) argues that there are no unspoken words. Hawthorne and Lepore ([2011]. “On Words.” The Journal of Philosophy 108 (9): 447–485) put forward examples that purport to show that there can be such words. Here, I argue that Kaplan is correct, if we grant him a minor variation. While Hawthorne and Lepore might be right that there can be unspoken words, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  5
    The phenomenal contribution of attention.Jonathan Mitchell - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):513-544.
    Strong or Pure Intentionalism is the view that the phenomenal character of a conscious experience is exhaustively determined by its intentional content. Contrastingly, impure intentionalism holds that there are also non content-based aspects or features which contribute to phenomenal character. Conscious attention is one such feature: arguably its contribution to the phenomenal character of a given conscious experience are not exhaustively captured in terms of what that experience represents, that is in terms of properties of its intentional object. This paper (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  7
    Nonsense: a user's guide.Manish Oza - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):452-482.
    Many philosophers suppose that sometimes we think we are saying or thinking something meaningful when we're not saying or thinking anything at all: we are producing nonsense. But what is nonsense? An account of nonsense must, I argue, meet two constraints. The first constraint requires that nonsense can be rationally engaged with, not just mentioned. In particular, we can reason with nonsense and use it within that-clauses. An account which fails to meet this constraint cannot explain why nonsense appears meaningful. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  3
    In touch with the facts: epistemological disjunctivism and the rationalisation of belief.Edgar Phillips - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):402-427.
    The idea of believing for a good reason has both normative and psychological content. How are these related? Recently, a number of authors have defended a ‘disjunctivist’ view of rationalisation, on which a good reason can make a subject’s responses to it intelligible in a way that mere ‘apparent reasons’ cannot. However, little has been said about the possible epistemological significance of this view or its relationship to more familiar forms of disjunctivism in the philosophy of perception. This paper examines (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Why we go wrong: beyond Kant’s dichotomy between duty and self-love.Martin Sticker & Joe Saunders - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):794-825.
    Kant holds that whenever we fail to act from duty, we are driven by self-love. In this paper, we argue that there are a variety of different ways in which people go wrong, and we show why it is unsatisfying to reduce all of these to self-love. In doing so, we present Kant with five cases of wrongdoing that are difficult to account for in terms of self-love. We end by suggesting a possible fix for Kant, arguing that he should (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  2
    The Limited Phenomenal Infallibility thesis.Christopher M. Stratman - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):368-401.
    It may be true that we are epistemically in the dark about various things. Does this fact ground the truth of fallibilism? No. Still, even the most zealous skeptic will probably grant that it is not clear that one can be incognizant of their own occurrent phenomenal conscious mental goings-on. Even so, this does not entail infallibilism. Philosophers who argue that occurrent conscious experiences play an important epistemic role in the justification of introspective knowledge assume that there are occurrent beliefs. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  13
    Moral understanding, affect, and the imagination.Daniel Vanello - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):183-208.
    The aim of this paper is to defend the view that we need to conceive our moral understanding as in part constituted by our affective and imaginative abilities suitably related. The core argument is that in order to be able to understand and explain the truth of a given moral proposition, we need to understand what the relevant moral concepts refer to, that is, we need to understand the semantic value of the relevant moral concepts. In the moral domain, I (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Holism about Fact and Value.Kenneth Walden - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):545–569.
    This paper argues for confirmational holism about facts and values. This position is similar to one defended by (among others) Hilary Putnam, but the argument is importantly different. Whereas Putnam et al. rely on examples of the putative entanglement of facts and values – a strategy which I suggest is vulnerable to parrying – my argument proceeds at a more general level. I argue that the explanation of action can not be separated from our practical reasoning, and for this reason, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  3
    Holism about fact and value.Kenneth Walden - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):545-569.
    This paper argues for confirmational holism about facts and values. This position is similar to one defended by (among others) Hilary Putnam, but the argument is importantly different. Whereas Putnam et al. rely on examples of the putative entanglement of facts and values – a strategy which I suggest is vulnerable to parrying – my argument proceeds at a more general level. I argue that the explanation of action can not be separated from our practical reasoning, and for this reason, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Functionalism about inference.Jared Warren - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):718-742.
    Inferences are familiar movements of thought, but despite important recent work on the topic, we do not yet have a fully satisfying theory of inference. Here I provide a functionalist theory of inference. I argue that the functionalist framework allows us the flexibility to meet various demands on a theory of inference that have been proposed (such as that it must explain inferential Moorean phenomena and epistemological ‘taking’). While also allowing us to compare, contrast, adapt, and combine features of extant (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  34.  20
    Moods: from diffusiveness to dispositionality.Alex Grzankowski & Mark Textor - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (1):25-46.
    The view that moods are dispositions has recently fallen into disrepute. In this paper, we want to revitalise it by providing a new argument for it and by disarming an important objection against it. A shared assumption of our competitors (intentionalists about moods) is that moods are ‘diffuse’. First, we will provide reasons for thinking that existing intentionalist views do not in fact capture this distinctive feature of moods that distinguishes them from emotions. Second, we offer a dispositionalist alternative that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Mood and Wellbeing.Uriah Kriegel - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (1):1-24.
    The two main subjectivist accounts of wellbeing, hedonism and desire-satisfactionism, focus on pleasure and desire (respectively) as the subjective states relevant to evaluating the goodness of a life. In this paper, I argue that another type of subjective state, mood, is much more central to wellbeing. After a general characterization of some central features of mood (§1), I argue that the folk concept of happiness construes it in terms of preponderance of good mood (§2). I then leverage this connection between (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36. Knowing value and acknowledging value: on the significance of emotional evaluation.Jean Moritz Müller - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (1):162-181.
    It is widely assumed that emotions are evaluative. Moreover, many authors suppose that emotions are important or valuable as evaluations. According to the currently dominant version of cognitivism, emotions are evaluative insofar as they make us aware of value properties of their intentional objects. In attributing to emotions an epistemic role, this view conceives of them as epistemically valuable. In this paper, I argue that proponents of this account mischaracterize the evaluative character of emotions and, a fortiori, their value. Moreover, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37. (2 other versions)Emotions as states.Hichem Naar - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (1):71-90.
    A common distinction in emotion theory is between ‘occurrent emotions’ and ‘dispositional emotions’, ‘emotional episodes’ and ‘emotional states’, ‘emotions’ and ‘sentiments’, or more neutrally between ‘short-term emotions’ and ‘long-term emotions’. While short-term emotions are, or necessarily comprise, experiences, long-term emotions are generally seen as states that can exist without experience. Given the theoretical importance of experience for emotion theorists, long-term emotions are often cast aside as of secondary importance, or at any rate as in need of separate treatment. In this (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  35
    Emotional sinking in.Matthew Ratcliffe - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (1):142-161.
    In reflecting on events of considerable significance, it is commonplace to remark that ‘it hasn’t sunk in yet’ or ‘it’s still sinking in’. Such talk is sometimes associated with things seeming unreal, surreal, unfathomable, or somehow impossible. In this paper, I develop an account of what these experiences consist of. First of all, I suggest that they involve explicitly acknowledging the reality of one’s situation, while at the same time experiencing it as inconsistent with the organization of one’s life. I (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  21
    Emotions and their reasons.Laura Silva - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (1):47-70.
    Although it is now commonplace to take emotions to be the sort of phenomena for which there are reasons, the question of how to cash out the reason-responsiveness of emotions remains to a large extent unanswered. I highlight two main ways of thinking about reason-responsiveness, one that takes agential capacities to engage in norm-guided deliberation to underlie reason-responsiveness, and another which instead takes there to be a basic reason-relation between facts and attitudes. I argue that the latter approach should be (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Why are emotions epistemically indispensable?Fabrice Teroni & Julien Deonna - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68 (1):91-113.
    Contemporary philosophers are attracted by the Indispensability Claim, according to which emotions are indispensable in acquiring knowledge of some important values. The truth of this claim is often thought to depend on that of Emotional Dogmatism, the view that emotions justify evaluative judgements because they (seem to) make us aware of the relevant values. The aim of this paper is to show that the Indispensability Claim does not stand or fall with Emotional Dogmatism and that there is actually an attractive (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  41. The Proverbial Strategy. Free Relatives and Logical Relations.Tomas Barrero - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy (Online):1-24.
    Sentences that ascribe action are logically related, but it is not always obvious why. According to event semantics, implications and non-implications result from referential relations between unpronounced constituents. Taking as starting point examples including free relative clauses, this paper advances the alternative view that examples as such present logical relations as forms of predicative dependence indicated with pronounced constituents. To this end, I argue that Verbal Phrases and verbal traces follow the pattern of Verbal Phrase Anaphora and, more controversially, that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  9
    Deviance and the literal-metaphorical distinction revisited.Chris Genovesi & Jacob Hesse - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy:1-25.
    Classical deviance theories about metaphor argue that the metaphorical sense of a word or expression, w, deviates from the sense of the word or expression interpreted literally. Developments in lexical pragmatics challenge these theories by claiming that deviance pervades (nearly) all aspects of linguistic communication. If deviance is the norm, then classical explanans offer little to no insight. In fact, many theorists have abandoned the idea of the literal-metaphorical distinction. This move carries significant consequences for theories of language and communication. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Conceptually Engineering the Post-Truth Crisis.Tom Kaspers - 2025 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy.
    This article uses the current post-truth crisis to level a charge against deflationism. It argues that a post-truth society rejects the normativity of truth, thereby deflating truth, by treating disagreements about, say, scientific facts, as mere disagreements of taste. To have substantive disagreements, the notion of truth at stake must be substantive as well. To ward off the perils of post-truth politics, truth must be taken to be more than what deflationists can account for. If we want our disagreements to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
 Previous issues
  
Next issues