Key works |
Regarding the notion of levels in science, Craver 2007 provides a good discussion of the difference between levels understood in terms of parts for mechanisms versus such things as part-whole composition, mere aggregation, and spatial containment. For discussion of the difference between theories about inter-level causal transitions versus inter-level property instantiation or realization relations, see also Cummins 1983, Craver & Bechtel 2007, and the recent anthology Brooks et al 2021. For reduction, important ideas includes reduction as a derivation
by bridge principles (Nagel 1961), approximate
reduction (Schaffner 1967), an expanded continuum of strong to
weak reduction that advertises no bridge laws (Churchland 1979; Hooker 1981; Bickle 1997; Endicott 1998), compositional or mechanistic reduction (Wimsatt 1975; Rosenberg 2006; Bechtel 2007),
and functional reduction (Kim 1998; Marras 2002). For emergence, there are views that involve epistemic, metaphysical,
synchronic, and diachronic ideas (Mclaughlin 1992; Wimsatt 1997; Humphreys 2008; Wilson 2013),
as well as issues about actual cases in the sciences (Batterman 2002; Davies 2006). For supervenience, there are weak, strong, global, and mereological varieties (Kim 1993; Horgan 1993; McLaughlin 1995; Paull & Sider 1992), as well as debates over their significance for issues of explanation and dependence (Grimes 1988; Bennett 2004) and their adequacy to express a doctrine of physicalism
(Wilson 2005). For realization, the are accounts in terms of functional roles and
occupation (Papineau 1993; Melnyk 1994; Kim 1998), parts and wholes of mechanisms (Cummins 1983; Gillett 2002; Craver 2007), determinables and
determinates (MacDonald & MacDonald 1986; Yablo 1992; Wilson 2009), and
subsets of causal powers (Wilson 1999, 2011; Shoemaker 2001, 2007). There is also an interesting discussion of inter-level explanation in terms of why questions and answers by grounds in Skow 2016. |