Results for 'verbs, transitivity, intransitivity, passive diathesis, reflexive diathesis, judicative-diathesis, pre-judicative diathesis, pre-judiciary verbs'

972 found
Order:
  1.  1
    On Double – Working of the Verbal Diathesis in the Judgements. The Necessity in Establishing a Judicative Diathesis Into the Verb From a Phenomenological Point of View.Maria-Roxana Bischin - 2018 - Studia Universitatis Babeş-Bolyai Philosophia:145-162.
    Starting with the statement that the Being is what-it-is, we have a new dilemma when we want to express something through a philosophical sentence. We will try to find out and to show how the structure of the verb, correlated with the judgement dresses up a double form: a passive one, and a reflexive one. We think the direction of transformation starts with the passive form and change into a reflexive one. This double loop of the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Familiar Verbs Are Not Always Easier Than Novel Verbs: How German Pre‐School Children Comprehend Active and Passive Sentences.Miriam Dittmar, Kirsten Abbot-Smith, Elena Lieven & Michael Tomasello - 2014 - Cognitive Science 38 (1):128-151.
    Many studies show a developmental advantage for transitive sentences with familiar verbs over those with novel verbs. It might be that once familiar verbs become entrenched in particular constructions, they would be more difficult to understand (than would novel verbs) in non-prototypical constructions. We provide support for this hypothesis investigating German children using a forced-choice pointing paradigm with reversed agent-patient roles. We tested active transitive verbs in study 1. The 2-year olds were better with familiar (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  3.  69
    Children use verb semantics to retreat from overgeneralization errors: A novel verb grammaticality judgment study.Ben Ambridge, Julian M. Pine & Caroline F. Rowland - 2011 - Cognitive Linguistics 22 (2):303-323.
    Whilst certain verbs may appear in both the intransitive inchoative and the transitive causative constructions (The ball rolled/The man rolled the ball), others may appear in only the former (The man laughed/*The joke laughed the man). Some accounts argue that children acquire these restrictions using only (or mainly) statistical learning mechanisms such as entrenchment and pre-emption. Others have argued that verb semantics are also important. To test these competing accounts, adults (Experiment 1) and children aged 5–6 and 9–10 (Experiment (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  4. Adverbial account of intransitive self-consciousness.Roberto Sá Pereira - 2015 - Abstracta 8 (2).
    This paper has two aims. First, it aims to provide an adverbial account of the idea of an intransitive self-consciousness and, second, it aims to argue in favor of this account. These aims both require a new framework that emerges from a critical review of Perry’s famous notion of the “unarticulated constituents” of propositional content. First, I aim to show that the idea of an intransitive self-consciousness can be phenomenologically described in an analogy with the adverbial theory of perception. In (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5. Transitive meanings for intransitive verbs.François Recanati & Anouch Bourmayan - 2013 - In Laurence Goldstein (ed.), Brevity. Oxford University Press. pp. 122-142.
    In their chapter, Bourmayan and Recanati discuss the intransitive use of 'eat' and cognate verbs which take (on such uses) an indefinite implicit argument. Sometimes, Recanati pointed out in early work, the implicit argument of intransitive 'eat' seems definite ; there are also seemingly anaphoric and bound uses. How to account for them ? Recanati's early account invoked free enrichment, but Marti's negation test provides counter-examples to that account. Bourmayan and Recanati offer a new, situation-theoretic account, show that it (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6. Passive and Antipassive in a Functional Description of French Reflexive Verbs.Michael Herslund - 1997 - Hermes 19:75-92.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  24
    On Some Verbs Both Transitive and Intransitive in the Turkic Runic Inscriptions.Şi̇ri̇n User Hatice - 2011 - Journal of Turkish Studies 6:589-593.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  31
    The Rise of Positional Licensing.Paul Kiparsky - unknown
    The transition from Middle English to Modern English in the second half of the 14th century is a turning point in the syntax of the language. It is at once the point when several constraints on nominal arguments that had been gaining ground since Old English become categorical, and the point when a reorganization of the functional category Infl is initiated, whose completion over the next several centuries yields essentially the syntactic system of the present day. From this time on, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  9.  41
    Young children's earliest transitive and intransitive constructions.Michael Tomasello & Patricia J. Brooks - 1998 - Cognitive Linguistics 9 (4):379-396.
    Much of children's early syntactic development can be seen as the acquisition of sentence-level constructions that correspond to relatively complex events and states of affairs. The current study was an attempt to determine the relative concreteness (verb-specificity) or abstractness (verb-generality) of such constructions for children just beginning to produce large numbers of multi-word utterances. Sixteen children at 2.0 years of age and sixteen children at 2,5 years of age participated (all English speaking). Each child was taught two novel verbs (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  10.  75
    Reflexivity and Reciprocity with(out) Underspecification.Sarah E. Murray - 2008 - In Alte Grø nn (ed.), Proceedings of Sinn Und Bedeutung 12 (2007). Ilos. pp. 455--469.
    In languages like English, reflexivity and reciprocity are expressed by distinct proforms. However, many languages, such as Cheyenne, express reflexivity and reciprocity with a single proform. In this paper I utilize Dynamic Plural Logic (van den Berg, 1996) to a draw a semantic parallel between reflexive and reciprocal anaphors in English. I propose that they contribute overlapping but distinct requirements on the relations introduced by transitive verbs, requirements which fully specify reflexivity and reciprocity. This parallel is then extended (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11.  12
    The relationship between verb meaning and argument realization: What we learn from the processing of agent-implying intransitive verbs in Japanese.Zoe Pei-sui Luk - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13:928649.
    This study investigated whether some Japanese intransitive verbs, called agent-implying intransitive verbs, are processed differently from other ordinary intransitive verbs. These verbs are special in that they denote agentive events, but they are intransitive verbs, which only allow the patient/theme to be the only nominatively marked argument. The priming experiment was designed based on the situation model theory, assuming that verbs with an agentive semantic structure (e.g., ordinary transitive verbs) has a shorter causal (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  81
    Names, verbs and quantification again.Nicholas Denyer - 1999 - Philosophy 74 (3):439-440.
    There are enormous differences between quantifying name-variables only, quantifying verb-variables only, and quantifying both. These differences are found only in the logic of polyadic predication; and this presumably is why Richard Gaskin thinks that they distinguish names from transitive verbs only, and not from verbs generally. But that thought is mistaken: these differences also distinguish names from intransitive verbs. They thus vindicate the common idea that on the difference between names and verbs we may base grandiose (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  42
    Anticipatory Processing in a Verb‐Initial Mayan Language: Eye‐Tracking Evidence During Sentence Comprehension in Tseltal.Gabriela Garrido Rodriguez, Elisabeth Norcliffe, Penelope Brown, Falk Huettig & Stephen C. Levinson - 2023 - Cognitive Science 47 (1):e13292.
    We present a visual world eye-tracking study on Tseltal (a Mayan language) and investigate whether verbal information can be used to anticipate an upcoming referent. Basic word order in transitive sentences in Tseltal is Verb–Object–Subject (VOS). The verb is usually encountered first, making argument structure and syntactic information available at the outset, which should facilitate anticipation of the post-verbal arguments. Tseltal speakers listened to verb-initial sentences with either an object-predictive verb (e.g., “eat”) or a general verb (e.g., “look for”) (e.g., (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  54
    Agency and Voice: The Semantics of the Semitic Templates. [REVIEW]Edit Doron - 2003 - Natural Language Semantics 11 (1):1-67.
    Semitic templates systematically encode two dimensions of verb meaning: (a) agency, the thematic role of the verb’s external argument, and (b) voice. The assumption that this form-meaning correspondence is mediated by syntax allows the parallel compositional construction of the form and the meaning of a verb from the forms and the meanings of its root and template. The root and its arguments are optionally embedded under a light verb v which introduces the agent (Hale and Keyser 1993; Kratzer 1994). But (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15.  2
    Attraction or differentiation: diachronic changes in the causative alternation of Chinese change of state verbs.Jing Du, Shan Zuo & Fuyin Thomas Li - forthcoming - Cognitive Linguistics.
    This study examines the interplay of attraction and differentiation through the diachronic encoding of causative alternations in Chinese. A corpus-based analysis is conducted to profile the use of two Change of State verbs (COS verbs), pò ‘break’ and kāi ‘open’, focusing on their argument structure constructions. The analysis yields two main insights: (i) In Chinese, there are four pairs of causative alternations. The first pair, CA1, involving the alternation between NP1+COS+NP2 and NP2+COS, serves as the source for two (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  30
    Effects of Case and Transitivity on Processing Dependencies: Evidence From Niuean.Rebecca Tollan, Diane Massam & Daphna Heller - 2019 - Cognitive Science 43 (6):e12736.
    We investigate the processing of wh questions in Niuean, a VSO ergative–absolutive Polynesian language. We use visual‐world eye tracking to examine how preference for subject or object dependencies is affected (a) by case marking of the subject (ergative vs. absolutive) and object (absolutive vs. oblique), and (b) by the transitivity of the verb (whether the object is obligatory). We find that Niuean exhibits (a) an effect of case, whereby dependencies of arguments with absolutive case (whether subjects or objects) are preferred (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  15
    L2 Learners Do Not Ignore Verb’s Subcategorization Information in Real-Time Syntactic Processing.Chie Nakamura, Manabu Arai, Yuki Hirose & Suzanne Flynn - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    This study addressed the question of whether L2 learners are able to utilize verb’s argument structure information in online structural analysis. Previous L2 research has shown that L2 learners have difficulty in using verb’s intransitive information to guide online syntactic processing. This is true even though L2 learners have grammatical knowledge that is correct and similar to that of native speakers. In the present study, we contrasted three hypotheses, the initial inaccessibility account, the intransitivity overriding account, and the fuzzy subcategorization (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  31
    Modeling a Cognitive Transition at the Origin of Cultural Evolution Using Autocatalytic Networks.Liane Gabora & Mike Steel - 2020 - Cognitive Science 44 (9):e12878.
    Autocatalytic networks have been used to model the emergence of self‐organizing structure capable of sustaining life and undergoing biological evolution. Here, we model the emergence of cognitive structure capable of undergoing cultural evolution. Mental representations (MRs) of knowledge and experiences play the role of catalytic molecules, and interactions among them (e.g., the forging of new associations) play the role of reactions and result in representational redescription. The approach tags MRs with their source, that is, whether they were acquired through social (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  19. Schelling and Husserl on the Concept of Passive Synthesis.Yicai Ni - 2021 - Phänomenologische Forschungen 1 (1):187-205.
    Both Schelling and Husserl reveal that any attempt to ground objective cognition in subjectivity would encounter the problem of constitution of original experience. They also endorse similar solutions to this very problem. The constitution of original experience is depicted as passive synthesis, i. e., it is the pre-conscious activity of the original ‘I’ (Ur-Ich). However, unlike Schelling’s interpretation of passive synthesis, understood as a theory of quasi-conscious willing (Wollen), Husserl relocates passive synthesis in the transition from instinct (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  34
    On Aging: a Critical Phenomenology of Transitions.Tristana Martin Rubio - 2022 - Chiasmi International 24:219-239.
    This article advances a critical phenomenology of the meaning of aging embodiment. Its broad aim is to profoundly challenge an idealized view of aging as foremost and fundamentally a natural or normative procession of “ready-made” stages pre-set “in” time (i.e., infancy, childhood, adolescence, adulthood, and “old age”) or pre-given units of time that unfurl along a timeline (i.e., chronological age), from past to present to future. Combining, defending, and adapting resources from Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology of Perception with a reading of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  2
    An Assessment of Reflexive Sociology within the Framework of Bauman's Theory of Liquid Modernity.Semanur Gürbüz Tepeler - 2022 - Marifetname 9 (2):493-523.
    Modernity has firmly laid the foundations of modern life by melting the constants that kept pre-modern human life afloat, pouring them into patterns again within its ideal framework. But the failure of modern life to fulfill the promise of absolute happiness has led to some deterioration, thawing, fragmentation and melting in its structure. Based on this approach, Bauman underlines the transition from the solid modern age to the liquid modern age. Liquid life, which lacks a certain systematic, order, and holistic (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  36
    Speech Planning at Turn Transitions in Dialog Is Associated With Increased Processing Load.Mathias Barthel & Sebastian Sauppe - 2019 - Cognitive Science 43 (7):e12768.
    Speech planning is a sophisticated process. In dialog, it regularly starts in overlap with an incoming turn by a conversation partner. We show that planning spoken responses in overlap with incoming turns is associated with higher processing load than planning in silence. In a dialogic experiment, participants took turns with a confederate describing lists of objects. The confederate’s utterances (to which participants responded) were pre‐recorded and varied in whether they ended in a verb or an object noun and whether this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  23.  44
    Not Just Lying to Oneself: An Examination of Bad Faith in Sartre.Stalin Joseph Correya - 2021 - Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research 38 (1):103-121.
    Bad faith is commonly conceived as lying to oneself or self-deception. This folk definition is too simplistic as it undermines the rich ontological underpinnings of bad faith. While both simple self-deception and bad faith are opposed to the general phenomenon of lying (to others), for Sartre bad faith is also meant to explain both the working of consciousness and the ubiquity of pre-judicative nothingness. Together, consciousness and nothingness supply the special ontological foundation required for bad faith to operate. To (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  70
    The Order of Nature in Aristotle's Physics: Place and the Elements (review).Istvan M. Bodnar - 2001 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 39 (1):139-141.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 39.1 (2001) 139-141 [Access article in PDF] Helen S. Lang. The Order of Nature in Aristotle's Physics: Place and the Elements. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. Pp. xii + 324. £40. This is an unsuccessful book. Some of the reasons for its failure are complex, others are more simple. I cannot address all, but shall simply discuss the fundamental claims about four large (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25. Objects as Temporary Autonomous Zones.Tim Morton - 2011 - Continent 1 (3):149-155.
    continent. 1.3 (2011): 149-155. The world is teeming. Anything can happen. John Cage, “Silence” 1 Autonomy means that although something is part of something else, or related to it in some way, it has its own “law” or “tendency” (Greek, nomos ). In their book on life sciences, Medawar and Medawar state, “Organs and tissues…are composed of cells which…have a high measure of autonomy.”2 Autonomy also has ethical and political valences. De Grazia writes, “In Kant's enormously influential moral philosophy, autonomy (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  5
    Husserl, Psicologia Fenomenológica e Psicoterapia Existencial.Daniel Sousa - 2008 - Phainomenon 16-17 (1):221-234.
    The present paper intended to present a proposal for division of phenomenological psychology in two separate areas but interconnected with each other, based respectively on a static and genetic phenomenology. The former is more appropriate for a research field of human psychology, based on the concept of intentionality is presented as an eidetic psychology that can be applied to different subjects of study of psychological research and have as a research field on major issues of psychology, as perception, memory, language, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Passives and Reflexives in Phrase Structure Grammar'.Ivan Sag & Gerald Gazdar - 1981 - In Jeroen A. G. Groenendijk (ed.), Formal methods in the study of language. U of Amsterdam. pp. 131--152.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  28. Studies in Pre-Judicative Hermeneutics And Meontology (8th edition).Viorel Cernica (ed.) - 2023 - Bucharest: Bucharest University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. (1 other version)Counterexamples to the transitivity of better than.Stuart Rachels - 1998 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76 (1):71 – 83.
    Ethicists and economists commonly assume that if A is all things considered better than B, and B is all things considered better than C, then A is all things considered better than C. Call this principle Transitivity. Although it has great conceptual, intuitive, and empirical appeal, I argue against it. Larry S. Temkin explains how three types of ethical principle, which cannot be dismissed a priori, threaten Transitivity: (a) principles implying that in some cases different factors are relevant to comparing (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   104 citations  
  30. Essentially Comparative Value Does Not Threaten Transitivity.Toby Handfield - 2016 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 5 (1):3-12.
    The essentially comparative conception of value entails that the value of a state of affairs does not depend solely upon features intrinsic to the state of affairs, but also upon extrinsic features, such as the set of feasible alternatives. It has been argued that this conception of value gives us reason to abandon the transitivity of the better than relation. This paper shows that the support for intransitivity derived from this conception of value is very limited. On its most plausible (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  31.  24
    Comprehension of Argument Structure and Semantic Roles: Evidence from English-Learning Children and the Forced-Choice Pointing Paradigm.Claire H. Noble, Caroline F. Rowland & Julian M. Pine - 2011 - Cognitive Science 35 (5):963-982.
    Research using the intermodal preferential looking paradigm (IPLP) has consistently shown that English‐learning children aged 2 can associate transitive argument structure with causal events. However, studies using the same methodology investigating 2‐year‐old children’s knowledge of the conjoined agent intransitive and semantic role assignment have reported inconsistent findings. The aim of the present study was to establish at what age English‐learning children have verb‐general knowledge of both transitive and intransitive argument structure using a new method: the forced‐choice pointing paradigm. The results (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  32.  43
    Social Pathologies, Reflexive Pathologies, and the Idea of Higher-Order Disorders.Arto Laitinen - 2015 - Studies in Social and Political Thought 25:44-65.
    This paper critically examines Christopher Zurn’s suggestion mentioned above that various social pathologies (pathologies of ideological recognition, maldistribution, invisibilization, rationality distortions, reification and institutionally forced self-realization) share the structure of being ‘second-order disorders’: that is, that they each entail ‘constitutive disconnects between first-order contents and secondorder reflexive comprehension of those contents, where those disconnects are pervasive and socially caused’ (Zurn, 2011, 345-346). The paper argues that the cases even as discussed by Zurn do not actually match that characterization, but (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  33. Life, movement, and desire.Renaud Barbaras - 2008 - Research in Phenomenology 38 (1):3-17.
    In French, the verb "to live" designates both being alive and the experience of something. This ambiguity has a philosophical meaning. The task of a phenomenology of life is to describe an originary sense of living from which the very distinction between life in the intransitive sense and life in the transitive, or intentional, sense proceeds. Hans Jonas is one of those rare authors who has tried to give an account of the specificity of life instead of reducing life to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  34.  20
    Finding Structure in One Child's Linguistic Experience.Wentao Wang, Wai Keen Vong, Najoung Kim & Brenden M. Lake - 2023 - Cognitive Science 47 (6):e13305.
    Neural network models have recently made striking progress in natural language processing, but they are typically trained on orders of magnitude more language input than children receive. What can these neural networks, which are primarily distributional learners, learn from a naturalistic subset of a single child's experience? We examine this question using a recent longitudinal dataset collected from a single child, consisting of egocentric visual data paired with text transcripts. We train both language-only and vision-and-language neural networks and analyze the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  50
    The Wind Chilled the Spectators, but the Wine Just Chilled: Sense, Structure, and Sentence Comprehension.Mary Hare, Jeffrey L. Elman, Tracy Tabaczynski & Ken McRae - 2009 - Cognitive Science 33 (4):610-628.
    Anticipation plays a role in language comprehension. In this article, we explore the extent to which verb sense influences expectations about upcoming structure. We focus on change of state verbs like shatter, which have different senses that are expressed in either transitive or intransitive structures, depending on the sense that is used. In two experiments we influence the interpretation of verb sense by manipulating the thematic fit of the grammatical subject as cause or affected entity for the verb, and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  36.  43
    Ergativity: Argument Structure and Grammatical Relations.Christopher D. Manning - unknown
    I wish to present a codi cation of syntactic approaches to dealing with ergative languages and argue for the correctness of one particular approach, which I will call the Inverse Grammatical Relations hypothesis.1 I presume familiarity with the term `ergativity', but, brie y, many languages have ergative case marking, such as Burushaski in (1), in contrast to the accusative case marking of Latin in (2). More generally, if we follow Dixon (1979) and use A to mark the agent-like argument of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  37.  32
    Putting the argument back into argument structure constructions.Laurence Romain - 2022 - Cognitive Linguistics 33 (1):35-64.
    This paper shows that low-level generalisations in argument structure constructions are crucial to understanding the concept of alternation: low-level generalisations inform and constrain more schematic generalisations and thus constructional meaning. On the basis of an analysis of the causative alternation in English, and more specifically of the theme, I show that each construction has its own schematic meaning. This analysis is conducted on a dataset composed of 11,554 instances of the intransitive non-causative construction and the transitive causative construction. The identification (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  67
    Dispositions and ergativity.John Maier - 2015 - Philosophical Quarterly 65 (260):381-395.
    Attempts to give necessary and sufficient conditions for demarcating ‘dispositional’ predicates (such as ‘is fragile’) from other predicates are generally acknowledged to fail. This leaves unresolved the question of what it is about paradigm instances of dispositional predicates in virtue of which their application to an object constitutes a disposition ascription. This essay proposes that dispositional predicates are generally derived from ergative verbs, those verbs that allow for certain entailments from transitive to intransitive forms (as ‘Sam broke the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  39.  23
    A note on the complexity of S4.2.Aggeliki Chalki, Costas D. Koutras & Yorgos Zikos - 2021 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 31 (2):108-129.
    S4.2 is the modal logic of directed partial pre-orders and/or the modal logic of reflexive and transitive relational frames with a final cluster. It holds a distinguished position in philosophical...
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  62
    Semantic and Pragmatic Conditions for the Dative Alternation.Manfred Krifka - unknown
    One of the difficult areas for persons learning a foreign language is to grasp the range of usages of syntactic patterns that exist in the foreign language. It is not sufficient to learn how passive formation works, or how pre- or postpositional phrases are constructed, or how perfect tenses are expressed. One also has to learn which verbs can passivize at all, which verbs go with which pre- or postpositions, and, in case perfect tenses are expressed, as (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  41.  78
    Intransitive choices based on transitive preferences: The case of menu-dependent information.Georg Kirchsteiger & Clemens Puppe - 1996 - Theory and Decision 41 (1):37-58.
  42.  51
    Reciprocals in Malagasy.Edward L. Keenan - unknown
    a transitive verb, Lt b) is its minimal correspondent built with a reciprocal verb.* (I) a. m+aN+enjika (Manenjika) an-dRabe Rakoto. pREs+AcT+cltase Acc-Rabe Rakoto..
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43. Education and Responsiveness: On the Agency of Intersubjectivity.Brian Bruya - 2007 - In Roger T. Ames & Peter D. Hershock (eds.), Educations and Their Purposes: A Conversation among Cultures. University of Hawai'i Press.
    In typical monotransitive verbs, such as "to touch," the patient is a passive recipient of action. In this paper, I discuss a special class of monotransitive verbs in which the patient is not, and cannot be, just a passive recipient of action. These verbs, such as "to educate," hinge on intersubjective experience. This intersubjectivity throws a wrench into classical descriptions of grammatical transitivity, transforming the recipient of action from a passive patient receiving the action (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44. Wonder, Imagination, and the Matter of Theatre in The Tempest.Mary B. Moore - 2006 - Philosophy and Literature 30 (2):496-511.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Wonder, Imagination, and the Matter of Theatre in The TempestMary MooreAriel occurs. Recounting his performance of "the tempest" in Act I, scene 1 of The Tempest, he presents himself as being and action, fracturing grammar, spatial and temporal logic in ways that amaze and confound:I boarded the King's ship; now on the beak, Now in the waist, the deck, in every cabin, I flamed amazement. Sometime I'd divide, And (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  17
    Transitive and Intransitive Selection Processes and Their Effects.Addy D. Donason - 2023 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 68 (1):9-34.
    Karen Neander’s (1991a, b) Selected Effects (SE) theory of biological proper functions argues that the function of a trait is the action for which it was “caused” to be selected by natural selection. Her life’s work has already left a lasting impact, however SE theory has yet to be more properly formalized as a conceptual analysis of biological functions. Although other SE theories have sought to build upon Neander’s work (e.g., Garson, 2017), there remains an ambiguity in the theory’s use (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  19
    Cough-Anal Reflex May Be the Expression of a Pre-Programmed Postural Action.Paolo Cavallari, Francesco Bolzoni, Roberto Esposti & Carlo Bruttini - 2017 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 11.
  47.  28
    The Ontology of the Judicative.Viorel Cernica - 2016 - Balkan Journal of Philosophy 8 (2):143-148.
    In this paper, I will attempt to formulate some observations about the limits of a traditional ontology that is in its essence a judicative one. The main goal is to explore the possibility of constructing a pre-judicative ontology; in other words, to describe the cognitive and affective elements that are “under” the main ontological judgments, related naturally to being. The arguments in favor of a pre-judicative ontology offer a new perspective on judicative ontology itself. This pre- (...) ontology is nevertheless a kind of judicative ontology that covers a nonspecific realm of values. The paper has three parts: 1) a description of the main characteristics of traditional ontology from a judicative perspective; 2) the formulation of some logical conditions of possibility for a pre-judicative ontology; and 3) the outline of a pre-judicative ontology as an ontology of values. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  21
    The Role of The Morphological Deviation for Meaning in the Qur`ān.Yaşar Daşkiran - 2018 - Cumhuriyet İlahiyat Dergisi 22 (2):1347-1368.
    In the article, the phenomenon of deviation, which is one of the important subjects of stylistics and rhetoric is discussed. The deviation is divided into three categories in terms of phonetic, word and grammar. The study was limited to morphological deviation defined as a transition from form to another. The morphological deviations and their relation with meaning reveal the importance of changes in word level. The linguistic and contextual elements are considered as two complementary parties in contextual linguistics. From phonetic (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Canonical and Reverse Predication in the Syntax of the Active/Passive Diathesis Alternation.Marcel den Dikken - 2020 - In Adriana Belletti & Chris Collins (eds.), Smuggling in syntax. New York: Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  22
    Null se constructions in Brazilian and European Portuguese: Morphosyntactic deletion or emergence of new constructions?Karlien Franco, Dafne Palú, Susana Afonso & Augusto Soares da Silva - 2021 - Cognitive Linguistics 32 (1):159-193.
    Se constructions designate a set of polysemous constructions along a transitivity continuum marked by the clitic se that perform various functions: reflexive/reciprocal, middle, anticausative, passive, and impersonal. A counterpart of these constructions without the clitic – the null se construction – is also attested. Based on an extensive usage-feature and profile-based analysis, and using multivariate statistical methods, we analyze, considering Cognitive Grammar, the conceptual, structural, and lectal factors that determine the choice between overt and null se constructions. The (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 972