Results for 'sentencing'

962 found
Order:
  1. Ivano caponigro and daphna Heller.Specificational Sentences - 2007 - In Chris Barker & Pauline I. Jacobson (eds.), Direct compositionality. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 14--237.
  2. Many toys are in box.Existential Sentences - 1971 - Foundations of Language: International Journal of Language and Philosophy 7.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. John Lyons.Locative Sentences - forthcoming - Foundations of Language.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Philip Hugly and Charles Sayward.Null Sentences - 1999 - Iyyun 48:23.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Lisa Green/Aspectual be–type Constructions and Coercion in African American English Yoad Winter/Distributivity and Dependency Instructions for Authors.Pauline Jacobson, Paycheck Pronouns, Bach-Peters Sentences, Inflectional Head, Thomas Ede Zimmermann, Free Choice Disjunction, Epistemic Possibility, Sigrid Beck & Uli Sauerland - 2000 - Natural Language Semantics 8 (373).
  6. La boadi.Existential Sentences In Akan - 1971 - Foundations of Language 7:19.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Learning to Discriminate: The Perfect Proxy Problem in Artificially Intelligent Criminal Sentencing.Benjamin Davies & Thomas Douglas - 2022 - In Jesper Ryberg & Julian V. Roberts (eds.), Sentencing and Artificial Intelligence. Oxford: OUP.
    It is often thought that traditional recidivism prediction tools used in criminal sentencing, though biased in many ways, can straightforwardly avoid one particularly pernicious type of bias: direct racial discrimination. They can avoid this by excluding race from the list of variables employed to predict recidivism. A similar approach could be taken to the design of newer, machine learning-based (ML) tools for predicting recidivism: information about race could be withheld from the ML tool during its training phase, ensuring that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8. Reconciliation as the Aim of a Criminal Trial: Ubuntu’s Implications for Sentencing.Thaddeus Metz - 2019 - Constitutional Court Review 9:113-134.
    In this article, I seek to answer the following cluster of questions: What would a characteristically African, and specifically relational, conception of a criminal trial’s final end look like? What would the Afro-relational approach prescribe for sentencing? Would its implications for this matter forcefully rival the kinds of penalties that judges in South Africa and similar jurisdictions typically mete out? After pointing out how the southern African ethic of ubuntu is well understood as a relational ethic, I draw out (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  9. Abolish! Against the Use of Risk Assessment Algorithms at Sentencing in the US Criminal Justice System.Katia Schwerzmann - 2021 - Philosophy and Technology 34 (4):1883-1904.
    In this article, I show why it is necessary to abolish the use of predictive algorithms in the US criminal justice system at sentencing. After presenting the functioning of these algorithms in their context of emergence, I offer three arguments to demonstrate why their abolition is imperative. First, I show that sentencing based on predictive algorithms induces a process of rewriting the temporality of the judged individual, flattening their life into a present inescapably doomed by its past. Second, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  10. Iudicium ex Machinae – The Ethical Challenges of Automated Decision-Making in Criminal Sentencing.Frej Thomsen - 2022 - In Julian Roberts & Jesper Ryberg (eds.), Principled Sentencing and Artificial Intelligence. Oxford University Press.
    Automated decision making for sentencing is the use of a software algorithm to analyse a convicted offender’s case and deliver a sentence. This chapter reviews the moral arguments for and against employing automated decision making for sentencing and finds that its use is in principle morally permissible. Specifically, it argues that well-designed automated decision making for sentencing will better approximate the just sentence than human sentencers. Moreover, it dismisses common concerns about transparency, privacy and bias as unpersuasive (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  79
    Freedom of thought as freedom of expression: Hate crime sentencing enhancement and first amendment theory.Martin H. Redish - 1992 - Criminal Justice Ethics 11 (2):29-42.
    . Freedom of thought as freedom of expression: Hate crime sentencing enhancement and first amendment theory. Criminal Justice Ethics: Vol. 11, No. 2, pp. 29-42.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  17
    Retributivism and Current Sentencing Practices.Margaret R. Holmgren - 2014 - Criminal Justice Ethics 33 (1):58-69.
    Retributivism Has a Past: Has It a Future? is the first volume of a series to be published by Oxford University Press: Studies in Penal Theory and Philosophy. Clearly the series is off to a fine st...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  27
    Vague comparisons and proportional sentencing.Jacob Bronsther - 2019 - Legal Theory 25 (1):26-52.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14. The "Race-of-the-Victim" Effect in Capital Sentencing: McClesky v. Kemp and Underadjustment Bias.William A. Edmundson - 1990 - Jurimetrics 32:125-41.
    This is a critical discussion of the Baldus study of capital sentencing in Georgia. It concludes that the Baldus finding of a "race-of-the-victim" effect is less robust than capital-punishment abolitionists have claimed. But the flaws in the Baldus study should not comfort death-penalty advocates, for they reveal an epistemological barrier to the US Supreme Court's ever being able to satisfy itself both that the sentence reflects particularized consideration of the circumstances and character of the defendant and that it is (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  59
    Remaking the corporation: The 1991 U.s. Sentencing guidelines. [REVIEW]Robert J. Rafalko - 1994 - Journal of Business Ethics 13 (8):625 - 636.
    This is an essay about the philosophical and practical problems associated with the concept of punishment for corporations that have grievously broken the law. It is specifically an essay about the special incentives that the U.S. Government has put in place to encourage American corporations to create comprehensive ethics programs and observe them faithfully. First, I will look at the sorts of obstacles to effective punishment of recalcitrant corporations that eventually prompted extraordinary measures by the U.S. Government. Then I will (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  16.  35
    Collateral Legal Consequences and Criminal Sentencing.Zachary Hoskins - 2023 - American Philosophical Quarterly 60 (2):117-130.
    A criminal conviction can trigger numerous burdensome legal consequences beyond the formal sentence. Some charge that these “collateral” legal consequences (CLCs) constitute additional measures of punishment, which raises the further question of whether judges should consider these CLCs when making sentencing decisions, reducing the formal sentence in proportion to the severity of the CLCs the defendant will face. The idea that all CLCs constitute forms of punishment reflects a particular conception of punishment, which I call the “minimalist view.” In (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  22
    Rethinking judicial paternalism:: Gender, work-family relations, and sentencing.Kathleen Daly - 1989 - Gender and Society 3 (1):9-36.
    Many scholars think that women are sentenced more leniently than men because judges are paternalistic toward women. In this article, I suggest that paternalism is a multilayered concept and that it is important to distinguish between judicial concerns for protecting women and those for protecting children and families. To learn what factors judges consider in sentencing and whether these differ for men and women defendants, I interviewed 20 men and 3 women judges in two state criminal courts. I learned (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  18.  74
    Criteria for Assessing AI-Based Sentencing Algorithms: A Reply to Ryberg.Thomas Douglas - 2024 - Philosophy and Technology 37 (1):1-4.
  19. Dealing with potential terrorists within a censure-based model of sentencing.Alessandro Corda - 2019 - In Antje du Bois-Pedain & Anthony E. Bottoms (eds.), Penal censure: engagements within and beyond desert theory. New York: Hart Publishing.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  15
    Corporate culture and ethical leadership under the federal sentencing guidelines: what should boards, management and policymakers do now?Michael D. Greenberg - 2012 - Santa Monica, CA: RAND.
    On May 16, 2012, RAND brought together a group of public company directors and executives, chief ethics and compliance officers, and stakeholders from the government, academic, and nonprofit sectors for a series of conversations about organizational culture, as well as to explore the business and policy ramifications of efforts to build better ethical cultures in corporations.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  26
    Purposes of punishment under the Minnesota sentencing guidelines.Richard S. Frase - 1994 - Criminal Justice Ethics 13 (1):11-20.
    (1994). Purposes of punishment under the Minnesota sentencing guidelines. Criminal Justice Ethics: Vol. 13, No. 1, pp. 11-20. doi: 10.1080/0731129X.1994.9991956.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22. Consideration of the Victim's Behavior when Sentencing a Person who Commits Intentional and Unintentional Homicide in a State of Intense Emotional Excitement Under Uzbekistan Law.Niyozova Salomat Saparovna - forthcoming - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique:1-18.
    This article describes issues related to the consideration of the victim’s behavior when sentencing a person who intentionally killed someone in a state of strong emotional excitement. Also, the author analyzed in the article that the main reason for the strong emotional excitement of the culprit is the illegal act of the victim, therefore, the sudden emotional excitement is defined in the law as a mitigating circumstance. In addition, the article analyzes the objective aspect of the crime of intentional (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  25
    The role of criminal record in the federal sentencing guidelines.Julian V. Roberts - 1994 - Criminal Justice Ethics 13 (1):21-30.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  23
    Amendments in the route to sentencing reform.Ronald F. Wright - 1994 - Criminal Justice Ethics 13 (1):58-66.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  66
    Justice in the age of sentencing guidelines.David Dolinko - 2000 - Ethics 110 (3):563-585.
  26. Mitigation is difficult : a moral evaluation of a mitigation practice at sentencing.Allan McCay - 2019 - In Allan McCay & Michael Sevel (eds.), Free Will and the Law: New Perspectives. New York, NY: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  13
    Commentary: Reaffirming the rule of law in federal sentencing.Tom Feeney - 2003 - Criminal Justice Ethics 22 (2):2-73.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  27
    Punishment as reluctant moralism: Review of Andrew von Hirsch and Andrew Ashworth, ‘Proportionate Sentencing: Exploring the principles’ Oxford University Press, Hardback £54.95, ISBN-10: 0-19-927260-3.Youngjae Lee - 2007 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 1 (2):227-231.
  29.  81
    A Conditional Defense of the Use of Algorithms in Criminal Sentencing.Ken Daley - 2023 - Techné Research in Philosophy and Technology 27 (1):1-20.
    The presence of predictive AI has steadily expanded into ever-increasing aspects of civil society. I aim to show that despite reasons for believing the use of such systems is currently problematic, these worries give no indication of their future potential. I argue that the absence of moral limits on how we might manipulate automated systems, together with the likelihood that they are more easily manipulated in the relevant ways than humans, suggests that such systems will eventually outstrip the human ability (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Corporate Ethics: The Role of Internal Compliance Programmes under the US Sentencing Guidelines.Michael Goldsmith & Amy Bice Larson - 2002 - In Ian Jones & Michael G. Pollitt (eds.), Understanding how issues in business ethics develop. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  66
    Ethical compliance programs and corporate illegality: Testing the assumptions of the corporate sentencing guidelines. [REVIEW]Marie McKendall, Beverly DeMarr & Catherine Jones-Rikkers - 2002 - Journal of Business Ethics 37 (4):367 - 383.
    This paper analyses the ethical performance of foreign-investment enterprises operating in China in comparison to that of the indigenous state-owned enterprises, collectives and private enterprises. It uses both the deontological approach and the utilitarian approach in conceptualization, and applies quantitative and econometric techniques to ethical evaluations of empirical evidences. It shows that according to various ethical performance indicators, foreign-investment enterprises have fared well in comparison with local firms. This paper also tries to unravel the effect of a difference in business (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  32. The 'Abuse Excuse' in Capital Sentencing Trials: Is it Relevant to Responsibility, Punishment, or Neither?Paul Litton - 2005 - American Criminal Law Review 42 (Summer 2005):1027-72.
  33. The Business Ethics Study Team, Required Behavior: An Introduction to the US Sentencing Guidelines and Corporate Compliance.R. C. Solomon - 1994 - Journal of Business Ethics 13:170-170.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  2
    To what Extent Does English Sentencing Policy in the 1990s Accord with Garland's Conception of the Limits of the Sovereign State?David Anderson - 2004
  35.  37
    When rape isn't rape: court of appeal sentencing practice in cases of marital and relationship rape.Philip N. S. Rumney - 1999 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 19 (2):243-270.
  36.  11
    The Sentence in Language and Cognition.Tista Bagchi - 2008 - Lexington Books.
    The Sentence in Language and Cognition is about the significant role of the sentence in linguistic cognition and in the practical domains of human existence. Dr. Tista Bagchi has written a comprehensive assessment of the structure and cognitive function of the sentence and the clause in the context of real-world discourse and activities.The notions of sentencehood and clausehood with special reference to the semantic histories of the terms sentence and clause, including their ethical, legal, and administrative uses, are assessed. This (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  28
    The Sentences Commentary of Thomas Ebendorfer : Manuscripts and question lists.Ioana Curuţ - 2022 - Archives d'Histoire Doctrinale et Littéraire du Moyen Âge 88 (1):65-111.
    L’intellectuel aux multiples facettes Thomas Ebendorfer de Haselbach est l’une des figures-clés de la Vienne du xv e siècle. Cet article est une première étape pour retracer le profil académique d’Ebendorfer à travers une lecture complète des diverses rédactions de son commentaire des Sentences conservées à l’Österreichische Nationalbibliothek. Sont analysés le contenu des manuscrits et la relation des différentes rédactions avec d’autres commentaires viennois connus. On trouvera en annexe la liste complète des questions, d’après toutes les rédactions du commentaire des (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  91
    Sentence-internal different as quantifier-internal anaphora.Adrian Brasoveanu - 2011 - Linguistics and Philosophy 34 (2):93-168.
    The paper proposes the first unified account of deictic/sentence-external and sentence-internal readings of singular different . The empirical motivation for such an account is provided by a cross-linguistic survey and an analysis of the differences in distribution and interpretation between singular different , plural different and same (singular or plural) in English. The main proposal is that distributive quantification temporarily makes available two discourse referents within its nuclear scope, the values of which are required by sentence-internal uses of singular different (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  39.  26
    Review of Hannah Maslen: Remorse, Penal Theory and Sentencing: Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2015, 212 pp. [REVIEW]Jonathan Peterson - 2019 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 13 (4):667-672.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Exception sentences and polyadic quantification.Friederike Moltmann - 1995 - Linguistics and Philosophy 18 (3):223 - 280.
    In this paper, I have proposed a compositional semantic analysis of exception NPs from which three core properties of exception constructions could be derived. I have shown that this analysis overcomes various empirical and conceptual shortcomings of prior proposals of the semantics of exception sentences. The analysis was first formulated for simple exception NPs, where the EP-complement was considered a set-denoting term and the EP-associate was a monadic quantifier. It was then generalized in two steps: first, in order to account (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  41.  61
    Sentences undecidable in formalized arithmetic: an exposition of the theory of Kurt Gödel.Andrzej Mostowski - 1952 - Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press.
    The famous theory of undecidable sentences created by Kurt Godel in 1931 is presented as clearly and as rigorously as possible. Introductory explanations beginning with the necessary facts of arithmetic of integers and progressing to the theory of representability of arithmetical functions and relations in the system (S) prepare the reader for the systematic exposition of the theory of Godel which is taken up in the final chapter and the appendix.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  42.  54
    Basic sentences and incorrigibility.Bruce Waters - 1942 - Philosophy of Science 9 (July):239-244.
    The question of basic and incorrigible sentences has appeared in connection with certain recent attempts to refine and re-define the meaning of Empiricism. More directly still, the question appears in connection with the problem of verification. It is noteworthy that the question of protocols, more than any other issue, has served to draw out the philosophical differences between the original Wiener Kreis and the Cambridge Analysts. Yet despite their differences both schools are agreed that basic sentences in some sense of (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  32
    Eternal sentences.Stephen H. Voss & Charles Sayward - 1976 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 54 (1):14 – 23.
    The paper argues that two apparently attractive conceptions of an eternal sentence are defective. An alternative conception is presented which the authors think allows greater insight into the nature of semantic concepts.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44.  1
    Scott Sentence Complexities of Linear Orderings.David Gonzalez & Dino Rossegger - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-30.
    We study possible Scott sentence complexities of linear orderings using two approaches. First, we investigate the effect of the Friedman–Stanley embedding on Scott sentence complexity and show that it only preserves $\Pi ^{\mathrm {in}}_{\alpha }$ complexities. We then take a more direct approach and exhibit linear orderings of all Scott sentence complexities except $\Sigma ^{\mathrm {in}}_{3}$ and $\Sigma ^{\mathrm {in}}_{\lambda +1}$ for $\lambda $ a limit ordinal. We show that the former cannot be the Scott sentence complexity of a linear (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Sentencing Leniency for Black Offenders: A Procedural Defense.Benjamin S. Yost - 2021 - In Michael Cholbi, Brandon Hogan, Alex Madva & Benjamin S. Yost (eds.), The Movement for Black Lives: Philosophical Perspectives. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, Usa.
    In response to the racial disparities that plague the American criminal justice system, the Movement for Black Lives calls for an end to policing and punishment “as we know it.” But refusing to punish violent offenses leaves unprotected those most vulnerable to crime, and outright abolition thus appears to undermine black rights and liberties. I call this the decarceration dilemma. After discussing Tommie Shelby and Christopher Lewis’s attempts to resolve the dilemma, I offer my own, which employs a procedural rather (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  77
    Existential Sentences without Existential Quantification.Louise McNally - 1998 - Linguistics and Philosophy 21 (4):353-392.
    Presents a set-theoretic version of the analysis of "there be" as predicating instantiation of a property, a property-theoretic version of which was developed in McNally 1992. This paper provides a solution to the criticism that McNally 1992's analysis could not account for sentences in which postverbal nominal contains a monotone decreasing or nonmonotonic determiner.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  47.  25
    Predictive Sentencing: Normative and Empirical Perspectives.Jan W. De Keijser, Julian V. Roberts & Jesper Ryberg (eds.) - 2019 - Hart Publishing.
    Predictive Sentencing addresses the role of risk assessment in contemporary sentencing practices. Predictive sentencing has become so deeply ingrained in Western criminal justice decision-making that despite early ethical discussions about selective incapacitation, it currently attracts little critique. Nor has it been subjected to a thorough normative and empirical scrutiny. This is problematic since much current policy and practice concerning risk predictions is inconsistent with mainstream theories of punishment. Moreover, predictive sentencing exacerbates discrimination and disparity in (...). Although structured risk assessments may have replaced 'gut feelings', and have now been systematically implemented in Western justice systems, the fundamental issues and questions that surround the use of risk assessment instruments at sentencing remain unresolved. This volume critically evaluates these issues and will be of great interest to scholars of criminal justice and criminology. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48. Information structure and sentence form: topic, focus, and the mental representations of discourse referents.Knud Lambrecht - 1994 - New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    Why do speakers of all languages use different grammatical structures under different communicative circumstances to express the same idea? In this comprehensive study, Professor Lambrecht explores the relationship between the structure of sentences and the linguistic and extra-linguistic contexts in which they are used. His analysis is based on the observation that the structure of a sentence reflects a speaker's assumptions about the hearer's state of knowledge and consciousness at the time of the utterance. This relationship between speaker assumptions and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  49. Liar sentences and Soames's rejection of bivalence.Teresa Marques - 2003 - In Henrique Jales Ribeiro (ed.), 1º Encontro Nacional de Filosofia Analítica.
    Scott Soames proposes in his book Understanding Truth (1999) a motivation to reject bivalence. It is his claim that if bivalence is assumed to apply to liar sentences, contradictions will follow. However, contradictions will equally follow if bivalence is denied of liar sentences (in fact, of any truth-bearers). Soames avoids contradictions by treating truth as a partially defined predicate: for certain sentences, truth is not defined to apply or not to apply. Liar sentences are some of such cases. However, there (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  44
    Connectionist Sentence Processing in Perspective.Mark Steedman - 1999 - Cognitive Science 23 (4):615-634.
    The emphasis in the connectionist sentence‐processing literature on distributed representation and emergence of grammar from such systems can easily obscure the often close relations between connectionist and symbolist systems. This paper argues that the Simple Recurrent Network (SRN) models proposed by Jordan (1989) and Elman (1990) are more directly related to stochastic Part‐of‐Speech (POS) Taggers than to parsers or grammars as such, while auto‐associative memory models of the kind pioneered by Longuet–Higgins, Willshaw, Pollack and others may be useful for grammar (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
1 — 50 / 962