Results for 'attribution'

979 found
Order:
  1.  27
    Derek W STRIJBOS Radboud University Nijmegen Leon C. de BRUIN Ruhr—University of Bochum.Reason Attribution - 2012 - Grazer Philosophische Studien, Vol. 86-2012 86:157 - 180.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Malinee somchiwong.Attributed To Congenital - 1990 - Journal of Biosocial Science 22:159.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  21
    Philosophy, Solipsism and Thought, HO MOUNCE.Knowing-Attributions as Endorsements - 1997 - Philosophy 47 (186).
  4. Leonard wj Van der kuijp.Logic Attributed to Klong Chen Rab - 2003 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 31:380.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. The neural and cognitive mechanisms of knowledge attribution: An EEG study.Adam Michael Bricker - 2020 - Cognition 203 (C):104412.
    Despite the ubiquity of knowledge attribution in human social cognition, its associated neural and cognitive mechanisms are poorly documented. A wealth of converging evidence in cognitive neuroscience has identified independent perspective-taking and inhibitory processes for belief attribution, but the extent to which these processes are shared by knowledge attribution isn't presently understood. Here, we present the findings of an EEG study designed to directly address this shortcoming. These findings suggest that belief attribution is not a component (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  6. Cross-Cultural Convergence of Knowledge Attribution in East Asia and the US.Yuan Yuan & Minsun Kim - 2023 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 14 (1):267-294.
    We provide new findings that add to the growing body of empirical evidence that important epistemic intuitions converge across cultures. Specifically, we selected three recent studies conducted in the US that reported surprising effects of knowledge attribution among English speakers. We translated the vignettes used in those studies into Mandarin Chinese and Korean and then ran the studies with participants in Mainland China, Taiwan, and South Korea. We found that, strikingly, all three of the effects first obtained in the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  7. Embedded mental action in self-attribution of belief.Antonia Peacocke - 2017 - Philosophical Studies 174 (2):353-377.
    You can come to know that you believe that p partly by reflecting on whether p and then judging that p. Call this procedure “the transparency method for belief.” How exactly does the transparency method generate known self-attributions of belief? To answer that question, we cannot interpret the transparency method as involving a transition between the contents p and I believe that p. It is hard to see how some such transition could be warranted. Instead, in this context, one mental (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  8.  85
    Severe weather event attribution: Why values won't go away.Eric Winsberg, Naomi Oreskes & Elisabeth Lloyd - 2020 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 84:142-149.
  9. Effects of subliminal priming of self and God on self-attribution of authorship for events.Daniel Wegner, Dijksterhuis, A., Preston, J. & H. Aarts - manuscript
  10. Morality or modality?: What does the attribution of intentionality depend on?Bence Nanay - 2010 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 40 (1):pp. 25-39.
    It has been argued that the attribution of intentional actions is sensitive to our moral judgment. I suggest an alternative, where the attribution of intentional actions depends on modal (and not moral) considerations. We judge a foreseen side-effect of an agent’s intentionally performed action to be intentional if the following modal claim is true: if she had not ignored considerations about the foreseen side-effect, her action might have been different (other things being equal). I go through the most (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  11. Perspective in intentional action attribution.Adam Feltz, Maegan Harris & Ashley Perez - 2012 - Philosophical Psychology 25 (5):673-687.
    In two experiments, we demonstrate that intentional action intuitions vary as a function of whether one brings about or observes an event. In experiment 1a (N?=?38), participants were less likely to judge that they intended (M?=?2.53, 7 point scale) or intentionally (M?=?2.67) brought about a harmful event compared to intention (M?=?4.16) and intentionality (M?=?4.11) judgments made about somebody else. Experiments 1b and 1c confirmed and extended this pattern of actor-observer differences. Experiment 2 suggested that these actor-observer differences are not likely (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  12. Timescale bias in the attribution of mind.Daniel Wegner - manuscript
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  13. (1 other version)Hermeneutical Injustice in the Attribution of Psychotic Symptoms with Religious Content.José Eduardo Porcher - 2024 - Philosophy Psychiatry and Psychology 31 (3):223-234.
    In this paper, I argue that a special kind of hermeneutical injustice occurs when someone is not permitted to interpret their experiences in a meaning-making way. I suggest that this occurs in certain cases where the possibility that the patient has a genuine religious experience is excluded by a medical diagnosis. In such cases, it is not that an experience is incomprehensible because of the absence of a valid interpretation. Instead, one perspective is not only dominant but exclusive, so the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Plato on the Attribution of Conative Attitudes.Rachana Kamtekar - 2006 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 88 (2):127-162.
    Plato’s Socrates famously claims that we want (bou9lesqai) the good, rather than what we think good (Gorgias 468bd). My paper seeks to answer some basic questions about this well-known but little-understood claim: what does the claim mean, and what is its philosophical motivation and significance? How does the claim relate to Socrates’ claim that we desire (e7piqumei=n)1 things that we think are good, which..
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  15.  43
    A schematic model of dispositional attribution in interpersonal perception.Glenn D. Reeder & Marilynn B. Brewer - 1979 - Psychological Review 86 (1):61-79.
  16.  25
    Harmful situations, impure people: An attribution asymmetry across moral domains.Alek Chakroff & Liane Young - 2015 - Cognition 136 (C):30-37.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  17.  66
    The early origins of goal attribution in infancy.Ildikó Király, Bianca Jovanovic, Wolfgang Prinz, Gisa Aschersleben & György Gergely - 2003 - Consciousness and Cognition 12 (4):752-769.
    We contrast two positions concerning the initial domain of actions that infants interpret as goal-directed. The 'narrow scope' view holds that goal-attribution in 6- and 9-month-olds is restricted to highly familiar actions (such as grasping) (). The cue-based approach of the infant's 'teleological stance' (), however, predicts that if the cues of equifinal variation of action and a salient action effect are present, young infants can attribute goals to a 'wide scope' of entities including unfamiliar human actions and actions (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  18. The measure of mind: propositional attitudes and their attribution.Robert J. Matthews - 2007 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    A prospective introduction -- The received view -- Troubles with the received view -- Are propositional attitudes relations? -- Foundations of a measurement-theoretic account of the attitudes -- The basic measurement-theoretic account -- Elaboration and explication of the proposed measurement-theoretic account.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  19.  70
    Thought-contents: on the ontology of belief and the semantics of belief attribution.Steven E. Boër - 2007 - Dordrecht: Springer.
    This book provides a formal ontology of senses and the belief-relation that grounds the distinction between de dicto, de re, and de se beliefs as well as the opacity of belief reports. According to this ontology, the relata of the belief-relation are an agent and a special sort of object-dependent sense (a "thought-content"), the latter being an "abstract" property encoding various syntactic and semantic constraints on sentences of a language of thought. One bears the belief-relation to a thought-content T just (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  20.  50
    Identification, Situational Constraint, and Social Cognition: Studies in the Attribution of Moral Responsibility.Rob Woolfolk, John Doris & John Darley - 2008 - In Joshua Knobe & Shaun Nichols (eds.), Experimental Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 61.
  21. The need to explain behavior: Predicting, explaining, and the social function of mental state attribution.Kristin Andrews - 2007
    According to both the traditional model of folk psychology and the social intelligence hypothesis, our folk psychological notions of belief and desire developed in order to make better predictions of behavior, and the fundamental role for our folk psychological notions of belief and desire are for making more accurate predictions of behavior (than predictions made without appeal to folk psychological notions). My strategy in this paper is to show that these claims are false. I argue that we need not appeal (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  43
    Informed consent, vulnerability and the risks of group-specific attribution.Berta M. Schrems - 2014 - Nursing Ethics 21 (7):829-843.
    People in extraordinary situations are vulnerable. As research participants, they are additionally threatened by abuse or exploitation and the possibility of harm through research. To protect people against these threats, informed consent as an instrument of self-determination has been introduced. Self-determination requires autonomous persons, who voluntarily make decisions based on their values and morals. However, in nursing research, this requirement cannot always be met. Advanced age, chronic illness, co-morbidity and frailty are reasons for dependencies. These in turn lead to limited (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  23.  62
    A Bayesian framework for knowledge attribution: Evidence from semantic integration.Derek Powell, Zachary Horne, Ángel Pinillos & Keith Holyoak - 2015 - Cognition 139 (C):92-104.
    We propose a Bayesian framework for the attribution of knowledge, and apply this framework to generate novel predictions about knowledge attribution for different types of “Gettier cases”, in which an agent is led to a justified true belief yet has made erroneous assumptions. We tested these predictions using a paradigm based on semantic integration. We coded the frequencies with which participants falsely recalled the word “thought” as “knew” (or a near synonym), yielding an implicit measure of conceptual activation. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  24.  72
    Temporal delays can facilitate causal attribution: Towards a general timeframe bias in causal induction.Marc J. Buehner & Stuart McGregor - 2006 - Thinking and Reasoning 12 (4):353 – 378.
    Two variables are usually recognised as determinants of human causal learning: the contingency between a candidate cause and effect, and the temporal and/or spatial contiguity between them. A common finding is that reductions in temporal contiguity produce concomitant decrements in causal judgement. This finding had previously (Shanks & Dickinson, 1987) been interpreted as evidence that causal induction is based on associative learning processes. Buehner and May (2002, 2003, 2004) have challenged this notion by demonstrating that the impact of temporal delay (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  25.  11
    How important is Kelley’s model of the attribution process when men and women discuss rape in conversation?Irina Anderson & Geoffrey Beattie - 1996 - Semiotica 110 (1-2):1-22.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  26.  20
    When one cause casts doubt on another: A normative analysis of discounting in causal attribution.Michael W. Morris & Richard P. Larrick - 1995 - Psychological Review 102 (2):331-355.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  27. Simulation is not enough: A hybrid model of disgust attribution on the basis of visual stimuli.Luca Barlassina - 2013 - Philosophical Psychology 26 (3):401-419.
    Mindreading is the ability to attribute mental states to other individuals. According to the Theory-Theory (TT), mindreading is based on one's possession of a Theory of Mind. On the other hand, the Simulation Theory (ST) maintains that one arrives at the attribution of a mental state by simulating it in one's own mind. In this paper, I propose a ST-TT hybrid model of the ability to attribute disgust on the basis of visual stimuli such as facial expressions, body postures, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  28. The Army as Textual Community: Exploring Mismatches in the Concepts of Attribution, Appropriation, and Shared Goals.Chris Anson & Shawn Neely - 2010 - Kairos: A Journal of Rhetoric, Technology, and Pedagogy 14 (3):n3.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  48
    The Measure of Mind: Propositional Attitudes and their Attribution * By ROBERT J. MATTHEWS.Robert Matthews - 2009 - Analysis 69 (1):185-187.
    The deflationary aim of this book, which occupies Part I, is to show that a widely held view has little to be said for it. The constructive aim, pursued in Part II, is to make plausible a measure-theoretic account of propositional attitudes. The discussion is throughout instructive, illuminating and sensitive to the many intricacies surrounding attitude ascriptions and how they can carry information about a subject's psychology. There is close engagement with cognitive science. The book should be read by anyone (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  30. Conversational and linguistic processes in causal attribution.William Turnbull & Ben Slugoski - 1988 - In Denis J. Hilton (ed.), Contemporary science and natural explanation: commonsense conceptions of causality. New York: New York University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  31.  15
    The effects of asymmetric liking on the attribution of dominance in dyads.Eileen G. Thompson & James L. Phillips - 1977 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 9 (6):449-451.
  32. Angry Men, Sad Women: Large Language Models Reflect Gendered Stereotypes in Emotion Attribution.Flor Miriam Plaza-del Arco, Amanda Cercas Curry & Alba Curry - 2024 - Arxiv.
    Large language models (LLMs) reflect societal norms and biases, especially about gender. While societal biases and stereotypes have been extensively researched in various NLP applications, there is a surprising gap for emotion analysis. However, emotion and gender are closely linked in societal discourse. E.g., women are often thought of as more empathetic, while men's anger is more socially accepted. To fill this gap, we present the first comprehensive study of gendered emotion attribution in five state-of-the-art LLMs (open- and closed-source). (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  42
    Dissociation, self-attribution, and redescription.George Graham - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):719-719.
  34.  8
    Economic Profiling of Physician Specialists: Use of Outlier Treatment and Episode Attribution Rules.J. W. Thomas & K. Ward - 2006 - Inquiry: The Journal of Health Care Organization, Provision, and Financing 43 (3):271-282.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  30
    Some Correspondences and Similarities of Shamanism and Cognitive Science: Interconnectedness, Extension of Meaning, and Attribution of Mental States.Timothy L. Hubbard - 2002 - Anthropology of Consciousness 13 (2):26-45.
    Correspondences and similarities between ideas in shamanism and ideas in contemporary cognitive science are considered. The importance of interconnectedness in the web of life worldview characteristic of shamanism and in connectionist models of semantic memory in cognitive science, and the extension of meaning to elements of the natural world in shamanism and indistributed cognition, are considered. Cognitive consequences of such an extension (e.g., use of representativeness and intentional stance heuristics, magical thinking, social attribution errors, and social in‐group/out‐group differences) are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  36. Identification, situational constraint, and social cognition : Studies in the attribution of moral responsibility.Robert L. Woolfolk, John M. Doris & & John M. Darley - 2008 - In Joshua Knobe & Shaun Nichols (eds.), Experimental Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  37. Purposes in law and in life: An experimental investigation of purpose attribution.Almeida Guilherme, Joshua Knobe, Noel Struchiner & Ivar Hannikainen - forthcoming - Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence.
    There has been considerable debate in legal philosophy about how to attribute purposes to rules. Separately, within cognitive science, there has been a growing body of research concerned with questions about how people ordinarily attribute purposes. Here, we argue that these two separate fields might be connected by experimental jurisprudence. Across four studies, we find evidence for the claim that people use the same criteria to attribute purposes to physical objects and to rules. In both cases, purpose attributions appear to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Nanotechology and the Attribution of Responsibility.Katrina Sifferd - 2008 - Nanotechnology, Law and Business 5 (2):177.
  39.  31
    The role of surprise in the attribution process.Joachim Stiensmeier-Pelster, Alice Martini & Rainer Reisenzein - 1995 - Cognition and Emotion 9 (1):5-31.
  40.  17
    A Single Belief-Changing Psychedelic Experience Is Associated With Increased Attribution of Consciousness to Living and Non-living Entities.Sandeep M. Nayak & Roland R. Griffiths - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    IntroductionAlthough the topic of consciousness is both mysterious and controversial, psychedelic drugs are popularly believed to provide unique insights into the nature of consciousness despite a lack of empirical evidence.MethodsThis study addresses the question of whether psychedelics change the attribution of consciousness to a range of living and non-living entities. A survey was conducted in 1,606 respondents who endorsed a belief changing psychedelic experience.ResultsParticipants rated their attributions of consciousness to a range of living and non-living entities before and after (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41. Side effects and asymmetry in act-type attribution.Lilian O'Brien - 2015 - Philosophical Psychology 28 (7):1012-1025.
    Joshua Knobe's work has marshaled considerable support for the hypothesis that everyday judgments of whether an action is intentional are systematically influenced by evaluations of the action or agent. The main source of evidence for this hypothesis is a series of surveys that involve an agent either helping or harming something as a side effect. Respondents are much more likely to judge the side effect intentional if harm is involved. It is a remarkable feature of the discussion so far that (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42.  47
    Perceived Insider Status and Feedback Reactions: A Dual Path of Feedback Motivation Attribution.Weijiong Wu, Wei Zhang, Xiao Chen & JianQiao Liao - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43. Distinguishing Knowledge Possession and Knowledge Attribution: The Difference Metaphilosophy Makes.Kristie Dotson - 2018 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 96 (2):475-482.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  44. Peer Disagreement and the Limits of Coherent Error Attribution.Nicholas Tebben - 2013 - Logos and Episteme 4 (2):179-197.
    I argue that, in an important range of cases, judging that one disagrees with an epistemic peer requires attributing, either to one's peer or to oneself, a failure of rationality. There are limits, however, to how much irrationality one can coherently attribute, either to oneself or to another. I argue that these limitations on the coherent attribution of rational error put constraints on permissible responses to peer disagreement. In particular, they provide reason to respond to one-off disagreements with a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  47
    Lost in the crowd: Entitative group membership reduces mind attribution.Carey K. Morewedge, Jesse J. Chandler, Robert Smith, Norbert Schwarz & Jonathan Schooler - 2013 - Consciousness and Cognition 22 (4):1195-1205.
    This research examined how and why group membership diminishes the attribution of mind to individuals. We found that mind attribution was inversely related to the size of the group to which an individual belonged . Mind attribution was affected by group membership rather than the total number of entities perceived at once . Moreover, mind attribution to an individual varied with the perception that the individual was a group member. Participants attributed more mind to an individual (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  46. Epistemic Akrasia, Higher-order Evidence, and Charitable Belief Attribution.Hamid Vahid - 2015 - International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 5 (4):296-314.
    _ Source: _Page Count 19 Epistemic akrasia refers to the possibility of forming an attitude that fails to conform to one’s best judgment. In this paper, I will be concerned with the question whether epistemic akrasia is rational and I will argue that it is not. Addressing this question, in turn, raises the question of the epistemic significance of higher-order evidence. After examining some of the views on this subject, I will present an argument to show why higher-order evidence is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  47. Imitation as a measure of attribution.C. Boesch - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15:149.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Le sermon du Bon pasteur: Un problème d'attribution.Th Dufour - forthcoming - Bibliothèque d'Humanisme Et Renaissance.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  15
    Collective Narcissism and In-Group Satisfaction Predict Opposite Attitudes Toward Refugees via Attribution of Hostility.Karolina Dyduch-Hazar, Blazej Mrozinski & Agnieszka Golec de Zavala - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  24
    On the import and rationale of value attribution.Nicholas Rescher - 2005 - Mind and Society 4 (1):115-127.
    The article urges a negative answer to the question if values merely lie ‘‘in the eyes of the beholder’’. It argues the objectivity of values via their status as tertiary properties that are neither on dispositionally inherent in their objects nor yet affective (dispositionally evoked in the interaction between objects and sense–observers), but rather reflective in being dispositionally evoked in suitably competent minds considering the matters involved.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 979