Results for 'Weierstrass'

81 found
Order:
  1.  17
    Weierstrass and the theory of matrices.Thomas Hawkins - 1977 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 17 (2):119-163.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  2.  28
    Weierstrass's final theorem of arithmetic is not final.F. G. Asenjo & J. M. McKean - 1972 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 13 (1):91-94.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  25
    On Robust Theorems Due to Bolzano, Weierstrass, Jordan, and Cantor.Dag Normann & Sam Sanders - 2024 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 89 (3):1077-1127.
    Reverse Mathematics (RM hereafter) is a program in the foundations of mathematics where the aim is to identify the minimal axioms needed to prove a given theorem from ordinary, i.e., non-set theoretic, mathematics. This program has unveiled surprising regularities: the minimal axioms are very often equivalent to the theorem over the base theory, a weak system of ‘computable mathematics’, while most theorems are either provable in this base theory, or equivalent to one of only four logical systems. The latter plus (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  19
    Weierstrass as a reader of Poincaré׳s early works.Umberto Bottazzini - 2014 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 47:118-123.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  22
    Beth definability and the Stone-Weierstrass Theorem.Luca Reggio - 2021 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 172 (8):102990.
    The Stone-Weierstrass Theorem for compact Hausdorff spaces is a basic result of functional analysis with far-reaching consequences. We introduce an equational logic ⊨Δ associated with an infinitary variety Δ and show that the Stone-Weierstrass Theorem is a consequence of the Beth definability property of ⊨Δ, stating that every implicit definition can be made explicit. Further, we define an infinitary propositional logic ⊢Δ by means of a Hilbert-style calculus and prove a strong completeness result whereby the semantic notion of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  28
    Modular Ax–Lindemann–Weierstrass with Derivatives.Jonathan Pila - 2013 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 54 (3-4):553-565.
    In a recent paper I established an analogue of the Lindemann–Weierstrass part of Ax–Schanuel for the elliptic modular function. Here I extend this to include its first and second derivatives. A generalization is given that includes exponential and Weierstrass elliptic functions as well.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  32
    Briefwechsel zwischen Karl Weierstrass und Sofja Kowalewskaja. Karl Weierstrass, Sofja Kowalewskaja, Reinhard Bolling.Karin Reich - 1995 - Isis 86 (4):672-673.
  8.  48
    A Schanuel Condition For Weierstrass Equations.Jonathan Kirby - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (2):631-638.
    I prove a version of Schanuel's conjecture for Weierstrass equations in differential fields, answering a question of Zilber, and show that the linear independence condition in the statement cannot be relaxed.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  70
    The Bolzano–Weierstrass Theorem is the jump of Weak Kőnig’s Lemma.Vasco Brattka, Guido Gherardi & Alberto Marcone - 2012 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 163 (6):623-655.
  10. Who Gave You the Cauchy–Weierstrass Tale? The Dual History of Rigorous Calculus.Alexandre Borovik & Mikhail G. Katz - 2012 - Foundations of Science 17 (3):245-276.
    Cauchy’s contribution to the foundations of analysis is often viewed through the lens of developments that occurred some decades later, namely the formalisation of analysis on the basis of the epsilon-delta doctrine in the context of an Archimedean continuum. What does one see if one refrains from viewing Cauchy as if he had read Weierstrass already? One sees, with Felix Klein, a parallel thread for the development of analysis, in the context of an infinitesimal-enriched continuum. One sees, with Emile (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  11.  22
    The development of the concept of uniform convergence in Karl Weierstrass’s lectures and publications between 1861 and 1886.Klaus Viertel - 2021 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 75 (4):455-490.
    The history of uniform convergence is typically focused on the contributions of Cauchy, Seidel, Stokes, and Björling. While the mathematical contributions of these individuals to the concept of uniform convergence have been much discussed, Weierstrass is considered to be the actual inventor of today’s concept. This view is often based on his well-known article from 1841. However, Weierstrass’s works on a rigorous foundation of analytic and elliptic functions date primarily from his lecture courses at the University of Berlin (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Das Fotoalbum fur Weierstrass. A Photo Album for Weierstrass.R. Bolling & I. Grattan-Guinness - 1995 - Annals of Science 52 (5):527-527.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  57
    Generating signals with multiscale time irreversibility: The asymmetric weierstrass function.Anton Burykin, Madalena D. Costa, Chung-Kang Peng, Ary L. Goldberger & Timothy G. Buchman - 2011 - Complexity 16 (4):29-38.
  14.  77
    Historians and Philosophers of Logic: Are They Compatible? The Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem as a Case Study.Gregory H. Moore - 1999 - History and Philosophy of Logic 20 (3-4):169-180.
    This paper combines personal reminiscences of the philosopher John Corcoran with a discussion of certain conflicts between historians of logic and philosophers of logic. Some mistaken claims about the history of the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem are analyzed in detail and corrected.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15.  28
    Eléments d'analyse de Karl Weierstrass.Pierre Dugac - 1973 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 10 (1):41-174.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  16.  24
    (2 other versions)Elements of Intuitionistic Analysis II the Stone‐Weierstrass Theorem and Ascoli's Theorem.H. de Swart - 1976 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 22 (1):501-508.
  17.  31
    Addendum to: “The Bolzano–Weierstrass theorem is the jump of weak Kőnig's lemma” [Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 163 (6) (2012) 623–655]. [REVIEW]Vasco Brattka, Andrea Cettolo, Guido Gherardi, Alberto Marcone & Matthias Schröder - 2017 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 168 (8):1605-1608.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Bolzano and the Traditions of Analysis Russell, in his History of Western Philosophy, wrote that modern analytical philosophy had its origins in the construction of modem functional analysis by Weierstrass and others.P. Rusnock - forthcoming - Grazer Philosophische Studien.
  19.  21
    Corrigendum to “A Schanuel Condition for Weierstrass Equations”.Jonathan Kirby - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (3):1023-1023.
  20.  47
    Billing J.. A failure of the Bolzano-Weierstrass lemma. Arkiv för matematik, astronomi och fysik, vol. 34B , no. 11, 2 pp. [REVIEW]Alonzo Church - 1947 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 12 (3):94-94.
  21.  15
    Nondefinability Results for Elliptic and Modular Functions.Raymond Mcculloch - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-20.
    Let $\Omega $ be a complex lattice which does not have complex multiplication and $\wp =\wp _\Omega $ the Weierstrass $\wp $ -function associated with it. Let $D\subseteq \mathbb {C}$ be a disc and $I\subseteq \mathbb {R}$ be a bounded closed interval such that $I\cap \Omega =\varnothing $. Let $f:D\rightarrow \mathbb {C}$ be a function definable in $(\overline {\mathbb {R}},\wp |_I)$. We show that if f is holomorphic on D then f is definable in $\overline {\mathbb {R}}$. The proof (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  25
    The Strength of an Axiom of Finite Choice for Branches in Trees.G. O. H. Jun Le - 2023 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 88 (4):1367-1386.
    In their logical analysis of theorems about disjoint rays in graphs, Barnes, Shore, and the author (hereafter BGS) introduced a weak choice scheme in second-order arithmetic, called the $\Sigma ^1_1$ axiom of finite choice (hereafter finite choice). This is a special case of the $\Sigma ^1_1$ axiom of choice ( $\Sigma ^1_1\text {-}\mathsf {AC}_0$ ) introduced by Kreisel. BGS showed that $\Sigma ^1_1\text {-}\mathsf {AC}_0$ suffices for proving many of the aforementioned theorems in graph theory. While it is not known (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  18
    Hermann Cohen’s logic of the pure knowledge as a philosophy of science.Zinaida A. Sokuler - 2022 - RUDN Journal of Philosophy 26 (3):658-671.
    The connection of Hermann Сohen’s “The Logic of Pure Knowledge” with the revolutionary transformations in physics and mathematics at the end of the 19th century is shown. Сohen criticised Kant’s answer to the question “How is mathematics possible”? If Kant refers to a priori forms of pure intuition, Сohen sees in it a restriction of freedom of mathematical thinking by limits of intuition. It has been shown that Cohen's position is in accordance with the main development of mathematics in the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24. A Burgessian Critique of Nominalistic Tendencies in Contemporary Mathematics and its Historiography.Karin Usadi Katz & Mikhail G. Katz - 2012 - Foundations of Science 17 (1):51-89.
    We analyze the developments in mathematical rigor from the viewpoint of a Burgessian critique of nominalistic reconstructions. We apply such a critique to the reconstruction of infinitesimal analysis accomplished through the efforts of Cantor, Dedekind, and Weierstrass; to the reconstruction of Cauchy’s foundational work associated with the work of Boyer and Grabiner; and to Bishop’s constructivist reconstruction of classical analysis. We examine the effects of a nominalist disposition on historiography, teaching, and research.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  25. Infinitesimals as an issue of neo-Kantian philosophy of science.Thomas Mormann & Mikhail Katz - 2013 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science (2):236-280.
    We seek to elucidate the philosophical context in which one of the most important conceptual transformations of modern mathematics took place, namely the so-called revolution in rigor in infinitesimal calculus and mathematical analysis. Some of the protagonists of the said revolution were Cauchy, Cantor, Dedekind,and Weierstrass. The dominant current of philosophy in Germany at the time was neo-Kantianism. Among its various currents, the Marburg school (Cohen, Natorp, Cassirer, and others) was the one most interested in matters scientific and mathematical. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  26. Ten Misconceptions from the History of Analysis and Their Debunking.Piotr Błaszczyk, Mikhail G. Katz & David Sherry - 2013 - Foundations of Science 18 (1):43-74.
    The widespread idea that infinitesimals were “eliminated” by the “great triumvirate” of Cantor, Dedekind, and Weierstrass is refuted by an uninterrupted chain of work on infinitesimal-enriched number systems. The elimination claim is an oversimplification created by triumvirate followers, who tend to view the history of analysis as a pre-ordained march toward the radiant future of Weierstrassian epsilontics. In the present text, we document distortions of the history of analysis stemming from the triumvirate ideology of ontological minimalism, which identified the (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  27.  72
    Ideal convergence of bounded sequences.Rafał Filipów, Recław Ireneusz, Mrożek Nikodem & Szuca Piotr - 2007 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 72 (2):501-512.
    We generalize the Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem on ideal convergence. We show examples of ideals with and without the Bolzano-Weierstrass property, and give characterizations of BW property in terms of submeasures and extendability to a maximal P-ideal. We show applications to Rudin-Keisler and Rudin-Blass orderings of ideals and quotient Boolean algebras. In particular we show that an ideal does not have BW property if and only if its quotient Boolean algebra has a countably splitting family.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  28.  68
    Numbers in presence and absence: a study of Husserl's philosophy of mathematics.J. Philip Miller - 1982 - Hingham, MA: Distributors for the U.S. and Canada, Kluwer Boston.
    CHAPTER I THE EMERGENCE AND DEVELOPMENT OF HUSSERL'S 'PHILOSOPHY OF ARITHMETIC'. HISTORICAL BACKGROUND: WEIERSTRASS AND THE ARITHMETIZATION OF ANALYSIS In ...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  29.  29
    Pincherle's theorem in reverse mathematics and computability theory.Dag Normann & Sam Sanders - 2020 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 171 (5):102788.
    We study the logical and computational properties of basic theorems of uncountable mathematics, in particular Pincherle's theorem, published in 1882. This theorem states that a locally bounded function is bounded on certain domains, i.e. one of the first ‘local-to-global’ principles. It is well-known that such principles in analysis are intimately connected to (open-cover) compactness, but we nonetheless exhibit fundamental differences between compactness and Pincherle's theorem. For instance, the main question of Reverse Mathematics, namely which set existence axioms are necessary to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  30.  29
    Representations and the Foundations of Mathematics.Sam Sanders - 2022 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 63 (1):1-28.
    The representation of mathematical objects in terms of (more) basic ones is part and parcel of (the foundations of) mathematics. In the usual foundations of mathematics, namely, ZFC set theory, all mathematical objects are represented by sets, while ordinary, namely, non–set theoretic, mathematics is represented in the more parsimonious language of second-order arithmetic. This paper deals with the latter representation for the rather basic case of continuous functions on the reals and Baire space. We show that the logical strength of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31. Incomplete Understanding of Concepts: The Case of the Derivative.Sheldon R. Smith - 2015 - Mind 124 (496):1163-1199.
    Many philosophers have discussed the ability of thinkers to think thoughts that the thinker cannot justify because the thoughts involve concepts that the thinker incompletely understands. A standard example of this phenomenon involves the concept of the derivative in the early days of the calculus: Newton and Leibniz incompletely understood the derivative concept and, hence, as Berkeley noted, they could not justify their thoughts involving it. Later, Weierstrass justified their thoughts by giving a correct explication of the derivative concept. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  32.  6
    Approximation Theorems Throughout Reverse Mathematics.Sam Sanders - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-32.
    Reverse Mathematics (RM) is a program in the foundations of mathematics where the aim is to find the minimal axioms needed to prove a given theorem of ordinary mathematics. Generally, the minimal axioms are equivalent to the theorem at hand, assuming a weak logical system called the base theory. Moreover, many theorems are either provable in the base theory or equivalent to one of four logical systems, together called the Big Five. For instance, the Weierstrass approximation theorem, i.e., that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  29
    Scientific Method in Philosophy.Russell Wahl - 2022 - Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 42 (1):81-91.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Scientific Method in PhilosophyAuthor's note: Thanks to Gregory Landini for helpful clarifications.Gregory Landini. Repairing Bertrand Russell's 1913 Theory of Knowledge. (History of Analytic Philosophy.) London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2022. Pp. x, 397. isbn: 978-3-030-66355-1, us$139 (hb); 978-3-030-66356-8, us$109 (ebook).The title of this book might suggest a rather narrow study of a problem with Russell's Theory of Knowledge and a proposed solution. But as with Landini's first book, Russell's Hidden Substitutional (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Interpreting the Infinitesimal Mathematics of Leibniz and Euler.Jacques Bair, Piotr Błaszczyk, Robert Ely, Valérie Henry, Vladimir Kanovei, Karin U. Katz, Mikhail G. Katz, Semen S. Kutateladze, Thomas McGaffey, Patrick Reeder, David M. Schaps, David Sherry & Steven Shnider - 2017 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 48 (2):195-238.
    We apply Benacerraf’s distinction between mathematical ontology and mathematical practice to examine contrasting interpretations of infinitesimal mathematics of the seventeenth and eighteenth century, in the work of Bos, Ferraro, Laugwitz, and others. We detect Weierstrass’s ghost behind some of the received historiography on Euler’s infinitesimal mathematics, as when Ferraro proposes to understand Euler in terms of a Weierstrassian notion of limit and Fraser declares classical analysis to be a “primary point of reference for understanding the eighteenth-century theories.” Meanwhile, scholars (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  35.  13
    New Periodic and Localized Traveling Wave Solutions to a Kawahara-Type Equation: Applications to Plasma Physics.Haifa A. Alyousef, Alvaro H. Salas, M. R. Alharthi & S. A. El-Tantawy - 2022 - Complexity 2022:1-15.
    In this study, some new hypotheses and techniques are presented to obtain some new analytical solutions to the generalized Kawahara equation. As a particular case, some traveling wave solutions to both Kawahara equation and modified Kawahara equation are derived in detail. Periodic and soliton solutions to this family are obtained. The periodic solutions are expressed in terms of Weierstrass elliptic functions and Jacobian elliptic functions. For KE, some direct and indirect approaches are carried out to derive the periodic and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Chapter.John Bell - manuscript
    Despite the great success of Weierstrass, Dedekind and Cantor in constructing the continuum from arithmetical materials, a number of thinkers of the late 19th and early 20th centuries remained opposed, in varying degrees, to the idea of explicating the continuum concept entirely in discrete terms. These include the mathematicians du Bois-Reymond, Veronese, Poincaré, Brouwer and Weyl, and the philosophers Brentano..
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  85
    (1 other version)Sobre los orígenes de la Matemática abstracta.Domínguez José Ferreiros - 1992 - Theoria 7 (1/2/3):473-498.
    Dedekind used to refer to Riemann as his main model concerning mathematical methodology, particularly regarding the use of abstract notions as a basis for mathematical theories. So, in passages written in 1876 and 1895 he compared his approach to ideal theory with Riemann’s theory of complex functions. In this paper, I try to make sense of those declarations, showing the role of abstract notions in Riemann’s function theory, its influence on Dedekind, and the importance of the methodological principle of avoiding (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  40
    To Let: Unsuccessful Stipulation, Bad Proof, and Paradox.Laurence Goldstein - 2013 - American Philosophical Quarterly 50 (1):93.
    Letting is a common practice in mathematics. For example, we let x be the sum of the first n integers and, after a short proof, conclude that x = n(n+1)/2; we let J be the point where the bisectors of two of the angles of a triangle intersect and prove that this coincides with H, the point at which another pair of bisectors of the angles of that triangle intersect. Karl Weierstrass's colleagues, in an attempt to solve optimization problems, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  64
    (1 other version)Vida en común, Vidas separadas. Sobre las interacciones entre matematicas Y lógicas desde la revolución francesa hasta la primera Guerra mundial [Living Together and Living Apart. On the Interactions Between Mathematics and Logics from the French Revolution to the First World War].Ivor Grattan-Guinness - 1997 - Theoria 12 (1):13-37.
    Este artículo presenta un alnplio panorama histórico de las conexiones existentes entre ramas de las matematícas y tipos de lógica durante el periodo 1800-1914. Se observan dos corrientes principales,bastante diferentes entre sí: la lógica algebraica, que hunde sus raíces en la logique yen las algebras de la época revolucionaria francesa y culmina, a través de Boole y De Morgan, en los sistemas de Peirce y de Schröder; y la lógica matematíca, que tiene una fuente de inspiraeión en el analisis matemático (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  21
    On the Foundations of Mathematical Economics.J. Barkley Rosser - unknown
    Kumaraswamy Vela Velupillai [74] presents a constructivist perspective on the foundations of mathematical economics, praising the views of Feynman in developing path integrals and Dirac in developing the delta function. He sees their approach as consistent with the Bishop constructive mathematics and considers its view on the Bolzano-Weierstrass, Hahn-Banach, and intermediate value theorems, and then the implications of these arguments for such “crown jewels” of mathematical economics as the existence of general equilibrium and the second welfare theorem. He also (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  87
    Bolzano and the Traditions of Analysis.Paul Rusnock - 1997 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 53 (1):61-85.
    Russell, in his History of Western Philosophy, wrote that modern analytical philosophy had its origins in the construction of modern functional analysis by Weierstrass and others. As it turns out, Bolzano, in the first four decades of the nineteenth century, had already made important contributions'to the creation of "Weierstrassian" analysis, some of which were well known to Weierstrass and his circle. In addition, his mathematical research was guided by a methodology which articulated many of the central principles of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  15
    ISCS 2013: interdisciplinary Symposium on Complex Systems.ʻAlī Ṣanāyiʻī, Ivan Zelinka & Otto E. Rössler (eds.) - 2014 - New York: Springer.
    The book you hold in your hands is the outcome of the "ISCS 2013: Interdisciplinary Symposium on Complex Systems" held at the historical capital of Bohemia as a continuation of our series of symposia in the science of complex systems. Prague, one of the most beautiful European cities, has its own beautiful genius loci. Here, a great number of important discoveries were made and many important scientists spent fruitful and creative years to leave unforgettable traces. The perhaps most significant period (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. The nature and role of intuition in mathematical epistemology.Paul Thompson - 1998 - Philosophia 26 (3-4):279-319.
    Great intuitions are fundamental to conjecture and discovery in mathematics. In this paper, we investigate the role that intuition plays in mathematical thinking. We review key events in the history of mathematics where paradoxes have emerged from mathematicians' most intuitive concepts and convictions, and where the resulting difficulties led to heated controversies and debates. Examples are drawn from Riemannian geometry, set theory and the analytic theory of the continuum, and include the Continuum Hypothesis, the Tarski-Banach Paradox, and several works by (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  37
    The Roots of Modern Logic [review of I. Grattan-Guinness, The Search for Mathematical Roots, 1870-1940 ].Alasdair Urquhart - 2001 - Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 21 (1):91-94.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviews 91 THE ROOTS OF MODERN LOGIC ALASDAIR URQUHART Philosophy/ U. ofToronto Toronro, ON, Canada M5S IAI URQUHART@CS.TORONTO.EDU I. Grattan-Guinness. The Searchfor Mathematical Roots,r870--r940: logics, Set Theoriesand the Foundations of Mathematicsfrom Cantor through Russellto Godel Princeron: Princeton U. P.,2000. Pp. xiv,690. us$45.oo. Grattan-Guinness's new hisrory of logic is a welcome addition to the literature. The title does not quite do justice ro the book, since it begins with the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  31
    Surreal Ordered Exponential Fields.Philip Ehrlich & Elliot Kaplan - 2021 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 86 (3):1066-1115.
    In 2001, the algebraico-tree-theoretic simplicity hierarchical structure of J. H. Conway’s ordered field${\mathbf {No}}$of surreal numbers was brought to the fore by the first author and employed to provide necessary and sufficient conditions for an ordered field (ordered$K$-vector space) to be isomorphic to an initial subfield ($K$-subspace) of${\mathbf {No}}$, i.e. a subfield ($K$-subspace) of${\mathbf {No}}$that is an initial subtree of${\mathbf {No}}$. In this sequel, analogous results are established forordered exponential fields, making use of a slight generalization of Schmeling’s conception of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  16
    Husserl.Rudolf Bernet - 1998 - In Simon Critchley & William Ralph Schroeder, A Companion to Continental Philosophy. Malden, Mass.: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 198–207.
    Edmund Husserl (1859–1938) is the founder of the phenomenological movement which has profoundly influenced twentieth‐century Continental philosophy. The historical setting in which his thought took shape was marked by the emergence of a new psychology (Herbart, von Helmholtz, James, Brentano, Stumpf, Lipps), by research into the foundation of mathematics (Gauss, Rieman, Cantor, Kronecker, Weierstrass), by a revival of logic and theory of knowledge (Bolzano, Mill, Boole, Lotze, Mach, Frege, Sigwart, Meinong, Erdmann, Schröder), as well as by the appearance of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  47. Deleuze and the conceptualizable character of mathematical theories.Simon B. Duffy - 2017 - In Nathalie Sinclair & Alf Coles Elizabeth de Freitas, What is a Mathematical Concept? Cambridge University Press.
    To make sense of what Gilles Deleuze understands by a mathematical concept requires unpacking what he considers to be the conceptualizable character of a mathematical theory. For Deleuze, the mathematical problems to which theories are solutions retain their relevance to the theories not only as the conditions that govern their development, but also insofar as they can contribute to determining the conceptualizable character of those theories. Deleuze presents two examples of mathematical problems that operate in this way, which he considers (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Frege on the Foundation of Geometry in Intuition.Jeremy Shipley - 2015 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 3 (6).
    I investigate the role of geometric intuition in Frege’s early mathematical works and the significance of his view of the role of intuition in geometry to properly understanding the aims of his logicist project. I critically evaluate the interpretations of Mark Wilson, Jamie Tappenden, and Michael Dummett. The final analysis that I provide clarifies the relationship of Frege’s restricted logicist project to dominant trends in German mathematical research, in particular to Weierstrassian arithmetization and to the Riemannian conceptual/geometrical tradition at Göttingen. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  49.  86
    Mathematical roots of phenomenology: Husserl and the concept of number.Mirja Hartimo - 2006 - History and Philosophy of Logic 27 (4):319-337.
    The paper examines the roots of Husserlian phenomenology in Weierstrass's approach to analysis. After elaborating on Weierstrass's programme of arithmetization of analysis, the paper examines Husserl's Philosophy of Arithmetic as an attempt to provide foundations to analysis. The Philosophy of Arithmetic consists of two parts; the first discusses authentic arithmetic and the second symbolic arithmetic. Husserl's novelty is to use Brentanian descriptive analysis to clarify the fundamental concepts of arithmetic in the first part. In the second part, he (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  50. Infinitesimals and Other Idealizing Completions in Neo-Kantian Philosophy of Mathematics.Mikhail G. Katz & Thomas Mormann - manuscript
    We seek to elucidate the philosophical context in which the so-called revolution of rigor in inifinitesimal calculus and mathematical analysis took place. Some of the protagonists of the said revolution were Cauchy, Cantor, Dedekind, and Weierstrass. The dominant current of philosophy in Germany at that time was neo-Kantianism. Among its various currents, the Marburg school (Cohen, Natorp, Cassirer, and others) was the one most interested in matters scientific and mathematical. Our main thesis is that Marburg Neo-Kantian philosophy formulated a (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 81