Results for 'Paul Debrul'

944 found
Order:
  1. Twilight of the perfect model model.Paul Teller - 2001 - Erkenntnis 55 (3):393-415.
  2. Coincidence as overlap.L. A. Paul - 2006 - Noûs 40 (4):623–659.
    I discuss puzzles involving coinciding material objects (such as statues and their constitutive lumps of clay) and propose solutions.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  3. Function, homology and character individuation.Paul E. Griffiths - 2006 - Philosophy of Science 73 (1):1-25.
    I defend the view that many biological categories are defined by homology against a series of arguments designed to show that all biological categories are defined, at least in part, by selected function. I show that categories of homology are `abnormality inclusive'—something often alleged to be unique to selected function categories. I show that classifications by selected function are logically dependent on classifications by homology, but not vice-versa. Finally, I reject the view that biologists must use considerations of selected function (...)
    Direct download (16 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  4. Gene.Paul E. Griffiths & Karola Stotz - 2007 - In David L. Hull & Michael Ruse, The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology. New York: Cambridge University Press.
    The historian Raphael Falk has described the gene as a ‘concept in tension’ (Falk 2000) – an idea pulled this way and that by the differing demands of different kinds of biological work. Several authors have suggested that in the light of contemporary molecular biology ‘gene’ is no more than a handy term which acquires a specific meaning only in a specific scientific context in which it occurs. Hence the best way to answer the question ‘what is a gene’, and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  5. What is Relativism?Paul Boghossian - 2006 - In Patrick Greenough & Michael Patrick Lynch, Truth and realism. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 13--37.
    Many philosophers, however, have been tempted to be relativists about specific domains of discourse, especially about those domains that have a normative character. Gilbert Harman, for example, has defended a relativistic view of morality, Richard Rorty a relativistic view of epistemic justification, and Crispin Wright a relativistic view of judgments of taste.¹ But what exactly is it to be a relativist about a given domain of discourse? The term ‘‘relativism’’ has, of course, been used in a bewildering variety of senses (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  6. The value of truth.Paul Horwich - 2006 - Noûs 40 (2):347–360.
  7. Replicator II – judgement day.Paul E. Griffiths & Russell D. Gray - 1997 - Biology and Philosophy 12 (4):471-492.
    The Developmental Systems approach to evolution is defended against the alternative extended replicator approach of Sterelny, Smith and Dickison (1996). A precise definition is provided of the spatial and temporal boundaries of the life-cycle that DST claims is the unit of evolution. Pacé Sterelny et al., the extended replicator theory is not a bulwark against excessive holism. Everything which DST claims is replicated in evolution can be shown to be an extended replicator on Sterelny et al.s definition. Reasons are given (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  8. Experimental philosophy of science.Paul E. Griffiths & Karola Stotz - 2008 - Philosophy Compass 3 (3):507–521.
    Experimental philosophy of science gathers empirical data on how key scientific concepts are understood by particular scientific communities. In this paper we briefly describe two recent studies in experimental philosophy of biology, one investigating the concept of the gene, the other the concept of innateness. The use of experimental methods reveals facts about these concepts that would not be accessible using the traditional method of intuitions about possible cases. It also contributes to the study of conceptual change in science, which (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  9. A computationally-discovered simplification of the ontological argument.Paul Oppenheimer & Edward N. Zalta - 2011 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89 (2):333 - 349.
    The authors investigated the ontological argument computationally. The premises and conclusion of the argument are represented in the syntax understood by the automated reasoning engine PROVER9. Using the logic of definite descriptions, the authors developed a valid representation of the argument that required three non-logical premises. PROVER9, however, discovered a simpler valid argument for God's existence from a single non-logical premise. Reducing the argument to one non-logical premise brings the investigation of the soundness of the argument into better focus. Also, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  10.  76
    Three- and four-year-olds spontaneously use others' past performance to guide their learning.Paul Bloom - 2008 - Cognition 107 (3):1018-1034.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  11. Countable additivity and the de finetti lottery.Paul Bartha - 2004 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55 (2):301-321.
    De Finetti would claim that we can make sense of a draw in which each positive integer has equal probability of winning. This requires a uniform probability distribution over the natural numbers, violating countable additivity. Countable additivity thus appears not to be a fundamental constraint on subjective probability. It does, however, seem mandated by Dutch Book arguments similar to those that support the other axioms of the probability calculus as compulsory for subjective interpretations. These two lines of reasoning can be (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  12. Ethology, sociobiology and evolutionary psychology.Paul Edmund Griffiths - 2008 - In Sahorta Sarkar & Anya Plutynski, Companion to the Philosophy of Biology. Blackwell. pp. 393-414.
    In the years leading up to the Second World War the ethologists Konrad Lorenz and Nikolaas Tinbergen, created the tradition of rigorous, Darwinian research on animal behavior that developed into modern behavioral ecology. At first glance, research on specifically human behavior seems to exhibit greater discontinuity that research on animal behavior in general. The 'human ethology' of the 1960s appears to have been replaced in the early 1970s by a new approach called ‘sociobiology’. Sociobiology in its turn appears to have (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  13.  58
    A response to "stimulus meaning".Paul Ziff - 1970 - Philosophical Review 79 (1):63-74.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  14. Free Will, Art and Morality.Paul Russell - 2008 - The Journal of Ethics 12 (3-4):307 - 325.
    The discussion in this paper begins with some observations regarding a number of structural similarities between art and morality as it involves human agency. On the basis of these observations we may ask whether or not incompatibilist worries about free will are relevant to both art and morality. One approach is to claim that libertarian free will is essential to our evaluations of merit and desert in both spheres. An alternative approach, is to claim that free will is required only (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  15. The shooting-room paradox and conditionalizing on measurably challenged sets.Paul Bartha & Christopher Hitchcock - 1999 - Synthese 118 (3):403-437.
    We provide a solution to the well-known “Shooting-Room” paradox, developed by John Leslie in connection with his Doomsday Argument. In the “Shooting-Room” paradox, the death of an individual is contingent upon an event that has a 1/36 chance of occurring, yet the relative frequency of death in the relevant population is 0.9. There are two intuitively plausible arguments, one concluding that the appropriate subjective probability of death is 1/36, the other that this probability is 0.9. How are these two values (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  16. David Hume's reductionist epistemology of testimony.Paul Faulkner - 1998 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 79 (4):302–313.
    David Hume advances a reductionist epistemology of testimony: testimonial beliefs are justified on the basis of beliefs formed from other sources. This reduction, however, has been misunderstood. Testimonial beliefs are not justified in a manner identical to ordinary empirical beliefs; it is true, they are justified by observation of the conjunction between testimony and its truth, it is the nature of the conjunctions that has been misunderstood. The observation of these conjunctions provides us with our knowledge of human nature and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  17. Moral worth.Paul Benson - 1987 - Philosophical Studies 51 (3):365 - 382.
  18. Mistakes.Paul A. Roth - 2003 - Synthese 136 (3):389-408.
    A suggestion famously made by Peter Winch and carried through to present discussions holds that what constitutes the social as a kind consists of something shared – rules or practices commonly learned, internalized, or otherwise acquired by all members belonging to a society. This essays argues against the explanatory efficacy of appeals to this shared something as constitutive of a social kind by examining a violation of social norms or rules, viz., mistakes. I argue that an asymmetric relation exists between (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  19. Heisenberg’s Uncertainty Principle.Paul Busch, Teiko Heinonen & Pekka Lahti - 2007 - \em Phys. Rep 43:155-176.
    Heisenberg's uncertainty principle is usually taken to express a limitation of operational possibilities imposed by quantum mechanics. Here we demonstrate that the full content of this principle also includes its positive role as a condition ensuring that mutually exclusive experimental options can be reconciled if an appropriate trade-off is accepted. The uncertainty principle is shown to appear in three manifestations, in the form of uncertainty relations: for the widths of the position and momentum distributions in any quantum state; for the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  20. What is social construction?Paul A. Boghossian - 2001 - TLS.
    The core idea seems clear enough. To say of something that it is socially constructed is to emphasize its dependence on contingent aspects of our social selves. It is to say: This thing could not have existed had we not built it; and we need not have built it at all, at least not in its present form. Had we been a different kind of society, had we had different needs, values, or interests, we might well have built a different (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  21. The fearless vampire conservator: Phillip Kitcher and genetic determinism.Paul E. Griffiths - 2006 - In Eva M. Neumann-Held, Christoph Rehmann-Sutter, Barbara Herrnstein Smith & E. Roy Weintraub, Genes in Development: Re-reading the Molecular Paradigm. Duke University Press. pp. 175-198.
    Genetic determinism is the idea that many significant human characteristics are rendered inevitable by the presence of certain genes. The psychologist Susan Oyama has famously compared arguing against genetic determinism to battling the undead. Oyama suggests that genetic determinism is inherent in the way we currently represent genes and what genes do. As long as genes are represented as containing information about how the organism will develop, they will continue to be regarded as determining causes no matter how much evidence (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  22.  88
    Semantic monadicity with conceptual polyadicity.Paul Pietroski - 2012 - In Markus Werning, Wolfram Hinzen & Edouard Machery, The Oxford Handbook of Compositionality. Oxford University Press.
    Many concepts, which can be constituents of thoughts, are somehow indicated with words that can be constituents of sentences. But this assumption is compatible with many hypotheses about the concepts lexicalized, linguistic meanings, and the relevant forms of composition. The lexical items simply label the concepts they lexicalize, and that composition of lexical meanings mirrors composition of the labeled concepts, which exhibit diverse adicities. If a phrase must be understood as an instruction to conjoin monadic concepts that correspond to the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  23. The epistemology of "epistemology naturalized".Paul Roth - 1999 - Dialectica 53 (2):87–110.
    Quine's “Epistemology Naturalized” has become part of the canon in epistemology and excited a widespread revival of interest in naturalism. Yet the status accorded the essay is ironic, since both friends and foes of philosophical naturalism deny that Quine makes a plausible case that the methods of naturalism can accommodate the problems of epistemology.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  24. (1 other version)Deflating compositionality.Paul Horwich - 2001 - Ratio 14 (4):369–385.
    My approach to the compositionality of meaning is deflationary in two respects. In the first place it shows that there is no need for a Tarski‐style truth‐theoretic account of it, and thereby avoids the difficult methodological and technical problems that would have to be solved on such an account. And in the second place it shows that compositionality imposes no constraint whatsoever on theories of lexical meaning. On the first of these points I am opposing Davidson and the tradition in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  25.  30
    Probabilistic networks and explanatory coherence.Paul Thagard - 1997 - In P. Thagard & C. P. Shelley, [Book Chapter].
    When surprising events occur, people naturally try to generate explanations of them. Such explanations usually involve hypothesizing causes that have the events as effects. Reasoning from effects to prior causes is found in many domains, including: Social reasoning: when friends are acting strange, we conjecture about what might be bothering them. Legal reasoning: when a crime has been committed, jurors must decide whether the prosecution's case gives a convincing explanation of the evidence. Medical diagnosis: given a set of symptoms, a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  26. Unconscious Conceiving and Leibniz's Argument for Primitive Concepts.Paul Lodge & Stephen Puryear - 2006 - Studia Leibnitiana 38 (2):177-196.
    In a recent paper, Dennis Plaisted examines an important argument that Leibniz gives for the existence of primitive concepts. After sketching a natural reading of this argument, Plaisted observes that the argument appears to imply something clearly inconsistent with Leibniz’s other views. To save Leibniz from contradiction, Plaisted offers a revision. However, his account faces a number of serious difficulties and therefore does not successfully eliminate the inconsistency. We explain these difficulties and defend a more plausible alternative. In the process, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  27. Beyond the Baldwin effect: James Mark Baldwin's 'social heredity', epigenetic inheritance, and niche construction.Paul E. Griffiths - 2003 - In Bruce H. Weber & David J. Depew, Evolution and Learning: The Baldwin Effect Reconsidered. MIT Press. pp. 193--215.
    I argue that too much attention has been paid to the Baldwin effect. George Gaylord Simpson was probably right when he said that the effect is theoretically possible and may have actually occurred but that this has no major implications for evolutionary theory. The Baldwin effect is not even central to Baldwin's own account of social heredity and biology-culture co-evolution, an account that in important respects resembles the modern ideas of epigenetic inheritance and niche-construction.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  28. Complementarity and uncertainty in Mach-zehnder interferometry and beyond.Paul Busch & Christopher Shilladay - unknown
    A coherent account of the connections and contrasts between the principles of complementarity and uncertainty is developed starting from a survey of the various formalizations of these principles. The conceptual analysis is illustrated by means of a set of experimental schemes based on Mach-Zehnder interferometry. In particular, path detection via entanglement with a probe system and (quantitative) quantum erasure are exhibited to constitute instances of joint unsharp measurements of complementary pairs of physical quantities, path and interference observables. The analysis uses (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  29. Kant, Boole and Peirce's early metaphysics.Paul Forster - 1997 - Synthese 113 (1):43-70.
    Charles Peirce is often credited for being among the first, perhaps even the first, to develop a scientific metaphysics of indeterminism. After rejecting the received view that Peirce developed his views from Darwin and Maxwell, I argue that Peirce's view results from his synthesis of Immanuel Kant's critical philosophy and George Boole's contributions to formal logic. Specifically, I claim that Kant's conception of the laws of logic as the basis for his architectonic, when combined with Boole's view of probability, yields (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  30.  37
    Indicative introduction.Paul Teller - 1977 - Philosophical Studies 31 (3):173 - 195.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  31.  45
    Hegel, science, and set theory.Paul Thagard - 1982 - Erkenntnis 18 (3):397 - 410.
  32. David Hull’s Natural Philosophy of Science.Paul E. Griffiths - 2000 - Biology and Philosophy 15 (3):301-310.
    Throughout his career David Hull has sought to bring the philosophy of science into closer contact with science and especially with biological science (Hull 1969, 1997b). This effort has taken many forms. Sometimes it has meant ‘either explaining basic biology to philosophers or explaining basic philosophy to biologists’ (Hull 1996, p. 77). The first of these tasks, simple as it sounds, has been responsible for revolutionary changes. It is well known that traditional philosophy of science, modeled as it was on (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  33. Molecular and Developmental Biology.Paul Griffiths - 2002 - In Peter K. Machamer & Michael Silberstein, The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of science. Malden, Mass.: Blackwell. pp. 252-271.
    Philosophical discussion of molecular and developmental biology began in the late 1960s with the use of genetics as a test case for models of theory reduction. With this exception, the theory of natural selection remained the main focus of philosophy of biology until the late 1970s. It was controversies in evolutionary theory over punctuated equilibrium and adaptationism that first led philosophers to examine the concept of developmental constraint. Developmental biology also gained in prominence in the 1980s as part of a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  34. (1 other version)A Third Route to the Doomsday Argument.Paul Franceschi - 2002 - Journal of Philosophical Research 34:263-278.
    In this paper, I present a solution to the Doomsday argument based on a third type of solution, by contrast to, on the one hand, the Carter-Leslie view and, on the other hand, the Eckhardt et al. analysis. I begin by strengthening both competing models by highlighting some variations of their original models, which renders them less vulnerable to several objections. I then describe a third line of solution, which incorporates insights from both Leslie and Eckhardt’s models and fits more (...)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  35. Ontology and aesthetics of digital art.Paul Crowther - 2008 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 66 (2):161–170.
  36. Evolutionary Psychology: History and Current Status.Paul E. Griffiths - 2005 - In Sahotra Sarkar & Jessica Pfeifer, The Philosophy of Science: An Encyclopedia. New York: Routledge. pp. 263--268.
    The development of evolutionary approaches to psychology from Classical Ethology through Sociobiology to Evolutionary Psychology is outlined and the main tenets of today's Evolutionary Psychology briefly examined: the heuristic value of evolutionary thinking for psychology, the massive modularity thesis and the monomorphic mind thesis.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  37.  61
    Demonstrative utterances.Paul Berckmans - 1990 - Philosophical Studies 60 (3):281 - 295.
  38.  85
    The dynamic turn in twentieth century logic.Paul Gochet - 2002 - Synthese 130 (2):175 - 184.
    The dynamic nature ofGame-Theoretical Semantics is emphasized. The role of strategic meaning in accounting for linguistic competence is examined. The semantics of epistemic possibility is shown to involve a dynamic ingredient. Update semantics has been designed to capture it. The paper focuses on the interplay betweenlogical and linguistic competences indiscourse understanding.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  39.  57
    Coherence.Paul Ziff - 1984 - Linguistics and Philosophy 7 (1):31 - 42.
  40. Of Goodness and Healthiness: A Viable Moral Ontology.Paul Bloomfield - 1997 - Philosophical Studies 87 (3):309-332.
  41.  62
    Necessity viewed as a semantical predicate.Paul Schweizer - 1987 - Philosophical Studies 52 (1):33 - 47.
  42. On causal relevance: A reply to Sullivan.Paul Raymont - 2004 - Dialogue (2):367-7.
  43.  63
    Reduplication in stratal OT.Paul Kiparsky - manuscript
    In Stratal OT, morphology and phonology are stratified and interleaved, as in traditional Lexical Phonology (Mohanan 1986), but the strata (Stem, Word, Postlexical) are characterized by systems of parallel constraints. The output of each morphological operation is submitted to the phonological constraints on its stratum: stems must satisfy the stem phonology, words must satisfy the word phonology, and Phrase must satisfy the phrasal phonology.1 For example, an affix which is added to stems to form words would enter into the derivation (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44. (1 other version)Explaining musical experience.Paul Boghossian - 2007 - In Kathleen Stock, Philosophers on Music: Experience, Meaning, and Work. New York: Oxford University Press UK. pp. 117.
    I start with the observation that we often respond to a musical performance with emotion -- even if it is just the performance of a piece of absolute music, unaccompanied by text, title or programme. We can be exhilarated after a Rossini overture brought off with subtlety and panache; somber and melancholy after Furtlanger’s performance of the slow movement of the Eroica. And so forth. These emotions feel like the real thing to me – or anyway very close to the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45. A Dichotomic Analysis of the Surprise Examination Paradox.Paul Franceschi - 2005 - Philosophiques 32 (2):399-421.
    This paper proposes a new framework to solve the surprise examination paradox. I survey preliminary the main contributions to the literature related to the paradox. I introduce then a distinction between a monist and a dichotomic analysis of the paradox. With the help of a matrix notation, I also present a dichotomy that leads to distinguish two basically and structurally different notions of surprise, which are respectively based on a conjoint and a disjoint structure. I describe then how Quine's solution (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  47
    Dedication.Paul E. Griffiths - 2000 - Biology and Philosophy 15 (3):299-299.
  47. Complements to a Theory of Cognitive Distortions.Paul Franceschi - 2007 - Journal de Thérapie Comportementale Et Cognitive 17 (2):1-6.
    The purpose of this study is to describe a conceptual framework for cognitive distortions, which notably allows to specify more accurately their intrinsic relationships. This conceptual framework aims at inserting itself within the apparatus of cognitive therapy and of critical thinking. The present analysis is based on the following fundamental concepts: the reference class, the duality and the system of taxa. With the help of these three notions, each cognitive distortion can be defined. A distinction is also made between, on (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  94
    Constructive and axiomatic mathematics.Paul Lorenzen - 1960 - Synthese 12 (1):114 - 119.
  49. The cow on the roof.Paul Ziff - 1973 - Journal of Philosophy 70 (19):713-723.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. The space-volume relation in the history of town planning.Paul Zucker - 1956 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 14 (4):439-444.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 944