Results for 'Ilkka Pyysianen'

283 found
Order:
  1. Allen, rt (1993) the structure of value (aldershot, ashgate publishing). Carter, John Ross (1993) on understanding buddhists: Essays on the theravada tradition in Sri lanka (new York, suny press). Cohen, Robert S.(1993) the birth of meaning in hindu thought (dordrecht, reidl). [REVIEW]Js Cummins, Wb Hallaq, Thomas Hudak, Phillip Olson, Ilkka Pyysianen, Isabelle Robinet, Gilbert Rozman, Paul Arthur Schlipp, Harendra Prasad Sinha & Gareth Sparham - 1994 - Asian Philosophy 4 (1):99.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Truth-Seeking by Abduction.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2018 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer.
    This book examines the philosophical conception of abductive reasoning as developed by Charles S. Peirce, the founder of American pragmatism. It explores the historical and systematic connections of Peirce's original ideas and debates about their interpretations. Abduction is understood in a broad sense which covers the discovery and pursuit of hypotheses and inference to the best explanation. The analysis presents fresh insights into this notion of reasoning, which derives from effects to causes or from surprising observations to explanatory theories. The (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  3. Critical scientific realism.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1999 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This book comes to the rescue of scientific realism, showing that reports of its death have been greatly exaggerated. Philosophical realism holds that the aim of a particular discourse is to make true statements about its subject matter. Ilkka Niiniluoto surveys different kinds of realism in various areas of philosophy and then sets out his own critical realist philosophy of science.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   176 citations  
  4. (1 other version)Abduction and truthlikeness.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2005 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 83 (1):255-275.
    This paper studies the interplay between two notions which are important for the project of defending scientific realism: abduction and truthlikeness. The main focus is the generalization of abduction to cases where the conclusion states that the best theory is truthlike or approximately true. After reconstructing the recent proposals of Theo Kuipers within the framework of monadic predicate logic, I apply my own notion of truthlikeness. It turns out that a theory with higher truthlikeness does not always have greater empirical (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  5. Degrees of truthlikeness: From singular sentences to generalisations.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1979 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 30 (4):371-376.
  6.  87
    Mahdollisuus.Ilkka Niiniluoto, Tuomas Tahko & Teemu Toppinen (eds.) - 2016 - Helsinki: Philosophical Society of Finland.
    Proceedings of the 2016 "one word" colloquium of the The Philosophical Society of Finland. The word was "Possibility".
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Survey article. Verisimilitude: the third period.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1998 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49 (1):1-29.
    The modern history of verisimilitude can be divided into three periods. The first began in 1960, when Karl Popper proposed his qualitative definition of what it is for one theory to be more truthlike than another theory, and lasted until 1974, when David Miller and Pavel Trichý published their refutation of Popper's definition. The second period started immediately with the attempt to explicate truthlikeness by means of relations of similarity or resemblance between states of affairs (or their linguistic representations); the (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  8. Theories, approximations, and idealizations.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1990 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 16:9-57.
  9. Is Science Progressive?Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1987 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (2):272-276.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  10.  34
    The Logic and epistemology of scientific change.Ilkka Niiniluoto & Raimo Tuomela (eds.) - 1979 - Amsterdam: North-Holland Pub. Co..
  11. Novel facts and bayesianism.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1983 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34 (4):375-379.
  12.  29
    (1 other version)Truthlikeness: old and new debates.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1990 - Synthese 84 (1):139-152.
    The notion of truthlikeness or verisimilitude has been a topic of intensive discussion ever since the definition proposed by Karl Popper was refuted in 1974. This paper gives an analysis of old and new debates about this notion. There is a fairly large agreement about the truthlikeness ordering of conjunctive theories, but the main rival approaches differ especially about false disjunctive theories. Continuing the debate between Niiniluoto’s min-sum measure and Schurz’s relevant consequence measure, the paper also gives a critical assessment (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  13.  66
    Explanation by Idealized Theories.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2018 - Kairos 20 (1):43-63.
    The use of idealized scientific theories in explanations of empirical facts and regularities is problematic in two ways: they don’t satisfy the condition that the explanans is true, and they may fail to entail the explanandum. An attempt to deal with the latter problem was proposed by Hempel and Popper with their notion of approximate explanation. A more systematic perspective on idealized explanations was developed with the method of idealization and concretization by the Poznan school in the 1970s. If idealizational (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  14. (2 other versions)Scientific progress.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1980 - Synthese 45 (3):427 - 462.
  15.  47
    L. J. Cohen versus Bayesianism.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):349-349.
  16. Defending abduction.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1999 - Philosophy of Science 66 (3):451.
    Charles S. Peirce argued that, besides deduction and induction, there is a third mode of inference which he called " hypothesis " or " abduction." He characterized abduction as reasoning " from effect to cause," and as " the operation of adopting an explanatory hypothesis." Peirce ' s ideas about abduction, which are related also to historically earlier accounts of heuristic reasoning, have been seen as providing a logic of scientific discovery. Alternatively, abduction is interpreted as giving reasons for pursuing (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  17. Possible Worlds of History.Ilkka Lähteenmäki - 2018 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 12 (1):164-182.
    _ Source: _Page Count 19 The theory of possible worlds has been minimally employed in the field of theory and philosophy of history, even though it has found a place as a tool in other areas of philosophy. Discussion has mostly focused on arguments concerning counterfactual history’s status as either useful or harmful. The theory of possible worlds can, however be used also to analyze historical writing. The concept of textual possible worlds offers an interesting framework to work with for (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  48
    Truth-Seeking by Abduction.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2004 - Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 11:57-82.
    In a seminar with the title “Deduction and Induction in the Sciences”, it is intriguing to ask the following questions: Is there a third type of inference besides deduction and induction? Does this third type of inference play a significant role within scientific inquiry? A positive answer to both of these questions was advocated by Charles S. Peirce throughout his career, even though his opinions changed in important ways during the fifty years between 1865 and 1914. Peirce called the third (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  19. Scientific progress as increasing verisimilitude.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2014 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 46:73-77.
    According to the foundationalist picture, shared by many rationalists and positivist empiricists, science makes cognitive progress by accumulating justified truths. Fallibilists, who point out that complete certainty cannot be achieved in empirical science, can still argue that even successions of false theories may progress toward the truth. This proposal was supported by Karl Popper with his notion of truthlikeness or verisimilitude. Popper’s own technical definition failed, but the idea that scientific progress means increasing truthlikeness can be expressed by defining degrees (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  20.  61
    Dual-process theories and hybrid systems.Ilkka Pyysiäinen - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (5):617-618.
    The distinction between such differing approaches to cognition as connectionism and rule-based models is paralleled by a distinction between two basic modes of cognition postulated in the so-called dual-process theories. Integrating these theories with insights from hybrid systems might help solve the dilemma of combining the demands of evolutionary plausibility and computational universality. No single approach alone can achieve this.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  30
    Jñānagarbha and the “God's‐eye view”.Ilkka Pyysiäinen - 1996 - Asian Philosophy 6 (3):197-206.
    In trying to define the difference between conventional and ultimate truth, the Mādhyamika Buddhist author Jñānagarbha ends up in paradoxical formulations. Putnam's discussion of Nietzsche's remark that “as the circle of science grows larger it touches paradox at more places” is presented as an illustration for Jñānagarbha's case. No comparison of Putnam and Jñānagarbha is intended as regards the contents of their presentations, the focus being only on the logical form of their argumentation. The paradoxical nature of Jñānagarbha's doctrinal system (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  27
    No evidence of a specific adaptation.Ilkka Pyysiäinen - 2006 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 29 (5):483-484.
    Bering's findings about the mental representation of dead agents are important, although his opposition between “endemic” and “cultural” concepts is misleading. Endemic and cultural are overlapping, not exclusive categories. It is also diffcult to see why reasoning about the dead would require a specific cognitive mechanism. Bering presents no clear evidence for the claim that the postulated mechanism is an adaptation.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Realism, relativism, and constructivism.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1991 - Synthese 89 (1):135 - 162.
    This paper gives a critical evaluation of the philosophical presuppositions and implications of two current schools in the sociology of knowledge: the Strong Programme of Bloor and Barnes; and the Constructivism of Latour and Knorr-Cetina. Bloor's arguments for his externalist symmetry thesis (i.e., scientific beliefs must always be explained by social factors) are found to be incoherent or inconclusive. At best, they suggest a Weak Programme of the sociology of science: when theoretical preferences in a scientific community, SC, are first (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  24.  77
    Social aspects of scientific knowledge.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2020 - Synthese 197 (1):447-468.
    From its inception in 1987 social epistemology has been divided into analytic and critical approaches, represented by Alvin I. Goldman and Steve Fuller, respectively. In this paper, the agendas and some basic ideas of ASE and CSE are compared and assessed by bringing into the discussion also other participants of the debates on the social aspects of scientific knowledge—among them Raimo Tuomela, Philip Kitcher and Helen Longino. The six topics to be analyzed include individual and collective epistemic agents; the notion (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25.  24
    On the Philosophy of Applied Social Sciences.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2013 - In Hanne Andersen, Dennis Dieks, Wenceslao J. Gonzalez, Thomas Uebel & Gregory Wheeler (eds.), New Challenges to Philosophy of Science. Springer Verlag. pp. 265--274.
  26.  49
    Igor Douven, The Art of Abduction.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2024 - Journal of Philosophy 121 (3):175-179.
  27.  96
    Tarski's definition and truth-makers.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2004 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 126 (1-3):57-76.
    A hallmark of correspondence theories of truth is the principle that sentences are made true by some truth-makers. A well-known objection to treating Tarski’s definition of truth as a correspondence theory has been put forward by Donald Davidson. He argued that Tarski’s approach does not relate sentences to any entities (like facts) to which true sentences might correspond. From the historical viewpoint, it is interesting to observe that Tarski’s philosophical teacher Tadeusz Kotarbinski advocated an ontological doctrine of reism which accepted (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  28.  42
    Truthlikeness.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1987 - Dordrecht: Reidel.
    The modern discussion on the concept of truthlikeness was started in 1960. In his influential Word and Object, W. V. O. Quine argued that Charles Peirce's definition of truth as the limit of inquiry is faulty for the reason that the notion 'nearer than' is only "defined for numbers and not for theories". In his contribution to the 1960 International Congress for Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science at Stan­ ford, Karl Popper defended the opposite view by defining a compara­tive (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  29. Optimistic realism about scientific progress.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2017 - Synthese 194 (9):3291-3309.
    Scientific realists use the “no miracle argument” to show that the empirical and pragmatic success of science is an indicator of the ability of scientific theories to give true or truthlike representations of unobservable reality. While antirealists define scientific progress in terms of empirical success or practical problem-solving, realists characterize progress by using some truth-related criteria. This paper defends the definition of scientific progress as increasing truthlikeness or verisimilitude. Antirealists have tried to rebut realism with the “pessimistic metainduction”, but critical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  30.  26
    Sequential order and sequence structure: the case of incommensurable studies on mobile phone calls.Ilkka Arminen - 2005 - Discourse Studies 7 (6):649-662.
    Two recent conversation analytical studies draw contrary conclusions from seemingly very similar materials. Hutchby and Barnett ‘show that, far from revolutionizing the organization of telephone conversation, mobile phone talk retains many of the norms associated with landline phone talk’. Arminen and Leinonen, however, state that landline and mobile calls differ systematically from each other. These incommensurate findings raise the question of why the comparisons between landline and mobile call openings have not been able to determine whether social and communicative practices (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31. Inductive systematization: Definition and a critical survey.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1972 - Synthese 25 (1-2):25 - 81.
    In 1958, to refute the argument known as the theoretician's dilemma, Hempel suggested that theoretical terms might be logically indispensable for inductive systematization of observational statements. This thesis, in some form or another, has later been supported by Scheffler, Lehrer, and Tuomela, and opposed by Bohnert, Hooker, Stegmüller, and Cornman. In this paper, a critical survey of this discussion is given. Several different putative definitions of the crucial notion inductive systematization achieved by a theory are discussed by reference to the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  32. Truthlikeness and bayesian estimation.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1986 - Synthese 67 (2):321 - 346.
  33. The aim and structure of applied research.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1993 - Erkenntnis 38 (1):1 - 21.
    The distinction between basic and applied research is notoriously vague, despite its frequent use in science studies and in science policy. In most cases it is based on such pragmatic factors as the knowledge and intentions of the investigator or the type of research institute. Sometimes the validity of the distinction is denied altogether. This paper suggests that there are two ways of distinguishing systematically between basic and applied research: (i) in terms of the utilities that define the aims of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  34.  68
    10 Truthlikeness and economic theories.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2002 - In Uskali Mäki (ed.), Fact and Fiction in Economics: Models, Realism and Social Construction. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 214.
    In a series of carefully argued and stimulating papers on realism, Usakli Maki has pointed out that economic theories typically are unrealistic in two senses: by violating "the-whole-truth" and "nothing-but-the-truth" (Maki 1989, 1992b, 1994b). He suggests that realism in economics can still be rescued by regarding theories as partially true descriptions of essences and as lawlike statements about tendencies. In this chapter, I defend realism by an alternative strategy: idealizational (or "isolational") statements are counterfactual conditional (Niiniluoto 1986), and the concepts (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  35. Truthlikeness: Comments on recent discussion.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1978 - Synthese 38 (2):281 - 329.
  36.  39
    Approaching probabilistic truths: introduction to the Topical Collection.Ilkka Niiniluoto, Gustavo Cevolani & Theo Kuipers - 2022 - Synthese 200 (2):1-8.
    After Karl Popper’s original work, several approaches were developed to provide a sound explication of the notion of verisimilitude. With few exceptions, these contributions have assumed that the truth to be approximated is deterministic. This collection of ten papers addresses the more general problem of approaching probabilistic truths. They include attempts to find appropriate measures for the closeness to probabilistic truth and to evaluate claims about such distances on the basis of empirical evidence. The papers employ multiple analytical approaches, and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  9
    G. H. von Wright on Logical Empiricism.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2024 - Philosophies 9 (4):108.
    Georg Henrik von Wright (1916–2003) started his studies in theoretical philosophy at the University of Helsinki in 1934. His teacher, Professor Eino Kaila (1890–1958), was an associate of the Vienna Circle who had changed the course of Finnish philosophy with his own version of logical empiricism. Under Kaila’s supervision, von Wright wrote his early studies on probability and defended his doctoral thesis The Logical Problem of Induction in 1941. Von Wright met Ludwig Wittgenstein in Cambridge in 1939 and 1947 and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. 'God'as ultimate reality in religion and in science.Ilkka Pyysiäinen - 1999 - Ultimate Reality and Meaning 22 (2):106-123.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  17
    Interdisciplinarity from the Perspective of Critical Scientific Realism.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2020 - In Wenceslao J. Gonzalez (ed.), New Approaches to Scientific Realism. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 231-250.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  37
    On a K-Dimensional System of Inductive Logic.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1976 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1976:425 - 447.
  41.  69
    Handbook of Epistemology.Ilkka Niiniluoto, Matti Sintonen & Jan Woleński (eds.) - 2004 - Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.
    The twenty-eight essays in this Handbook, all by leading experts in the field, provide the most extensive treatment of various epistemological problems, ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  42.  15
    The Role of al-Madāʾinī’s Students in the Transmission of His Material.Ilkka Lindstedt - 2014 - Der Islam: Journal of the History and Culture of the Middle East 91 (2):295-340.
    Name der Zeitschrift: Der Islam Jahrgang: 91 Heft: 2 Seiten: 295-340.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  9
    Explicating Inference to the Best Explanation.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2022 - In Wenceslao J. Gonzalez (ed.), Current Trends in Philosophy of Science: A Prospective for the Near Future. Springer. pp. 235-260.
    Inference to the best explanation (IBE) is a pattern of everyday and scientific reasoning, where a hypothesis is accepted if it gives a better explanation of the known evidence than any alternative hypothesis. This term was introduced by Gilbert Harman in 1965, and ever since IBE has been a central theme in the agenda of logic, artificial intelligence, and philosophy of science. However, a similar idea of a special kind of ampliative reasoning (besides deduction and induction) had been advocated by (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Revising Beliefs Towards the Truth.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2011 - Erkenntnis 75 (2):165-181.
    Belief revision (BR) and truthlikeness (TL) emerged independently as two research programmes in formal methodology in the 1970s. A natural way of connecting BR and TL is to ask under what conditions the revision of a belief system by new input information leads the system towards the truth. It turns out that, for the AGM model of belief revision, the only safe case is the expansion of true beliefs by true input, but this is not very interesting or realistic as (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  45.  16
    Does meditation swamp working memory?Pyysiainen Ilkka - 2006 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 29 (6).
  46. On the Human Condition : Philosophical Essays in Honour of the Centennial Anniversary of Georg Henrik von Wright.Ilkka Niiniluoto & Thomas Wallgren (eds.) - 2017
    Academician Georg Henrik von Wright (1916-2003) was an internationally leading analytic philosopher and philosophical logician but also an open-minded bridge-builder between philosophical schools and an inspiring intellectual and cultural personality. His centenary year 2016 was celebrated with several conferences, lecture series, books, and exhibitions in Helsinki, Cambridge, and Cairo. One of the main events was the conference The Human Condition, organized by the Philosophical Society of Finland and the University of Helsinki on 18–20 May 2016. This volume contains five keynote (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Abduction and Scientific Realism.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2018 - In Truth-Seeking by Abduction. Cham, Switzerland: Springer.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  23
    Escepticismo, falibilismo y verosimilitud.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2020 - Contrastes: Revista Internacional de Filosofía 25 (3):115-142.
    En la epistemología moderna, el falibilismo es una vía media entre el dogmatismo y el escepticismo. Su origen histórico se encuentra en una rama de la antigua escuela del escepticismo académico. Ya que la diferencia entre las formas fuerte y débil del falibilismo, así como la distinción entre probabilidad epistémica y verosimilitud, sólo han sido comprendidas en las últimas dos décadas, no podemos esperar encontrar formulaciones claras de dichas doctrinas entre los filósofos griegos y romanos. Pero hemos mostrado que las (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  11
    Reappraisals of Eino Kaila's philosophy.Ilkka Niiniluoto & Sami Pihlström (eds.) - 2012 - Helsinki: Philosophical Society of Finland.
  50.  7
    Tiede, filosofia ja maailmankatsomus: filosofisia esseitä tiedosta ja sen arvosta.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1984 - Helsingissä: Otava.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 283