Results for ' the good in itself'

971 found
Order:
  1.  11
    The Good in Nature and Humanity: Connecting Science, Religion, and Spirituality with the Natural World.Stephen R. Kellert, Timothy J. Farnham & Timothy Farnham - 2002 - Island Press.
    The good in nature and humanity brings together 20 leading thinkers and writers - including Ursula Goodenough, Lynn Margulis, Dorion Sagan, Carl Safina, David Petersen, Wendell Berry, Terry Tempest Williams, and Barry Lopez - to examine the divide between faith and reason, and to seek a means for developing an environmental ethic that will help us confront two of our most imperiling crises: global environmental destruction and an impoverished spirituality. The book explores the ways in which science, spirit, and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  38
    Developing the Good itself by itself: critical strategies in Plato's Euthydemus.Mary Mccabe - 2002 - Plato Journal 2.
  3.  45
    The Refuge of the Good in the Beautiful.Tanja Staehler - 2015 - Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (1):1-20.
    In the Platonic dialogues, the enigmatic concept of the good tends to retreat at those very moments when it is supposed to show itself. This paper examines the relation between the beautiful and the good as the good takes refuge in the beautiful. Hans-Georg Gadamer holds a particular interest in these retreats since they show that there is actually an emphasis on appearances and the human good in Plato. In contrast, Emmanuel Levinas is critical of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  50
    The Will to Exist: Reflections on Desire and the Good in Western Culture.Brayton Polka - 2015 - The European Legacy 20 (1):12-24.
    In my essay I argue that the critical distinction that Spinoza makes between two concepts of desire, as also between two concepts of the good, captures the distinction that Tertullian makes in posing the question: What does Athens have to do with Jerusalem? In identifying the good with desire—desire with the good—and in denying that desire is dependent on the good in itself, Spinoza shows us that philosophy, as ethics, belongs to Jerusalem, to the Bible, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  65
    The Idea of the Good in John Dewey and Aristotle.Gregory M. Fahey - 2002 - Essays in Philosophy 3 (2):201-226.
    John Dewey looks to the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle for the general outlines of his ethical thought. In his 1932 Ethics, he describes the ethical framework that he shares with Aristotle in terms of knowledge, choice and character: "The formula was well stated by Aristotle. The doer of the moral deed must have a certain 'state of mind' in doing it. First, he must know what he is doing; secondly, he must choose it, and choose it for itself, and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  67
    Natural capacities and democracy as a good-in-itself.Josiah Ober - 2007 - Philosophical Studies 132 (1):59 - 73.
    Democracy is shown to be a non-instrumental good-in-itself (as well as an instrument in securing other goods) by extrapolation from the Aristotelian premise that humans are political animals. Because humans are by nature language-using, as well as sociable and common-end-seeking beings, the capacity to associate in public decisions is constitutive of the human being-kind. Association in decision is necessary (although insufficient) for happiness in the sense of eudaimonia. A benevolent dictator who satisfied all other conditions of justice, harms (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  7. The Metaphysics of Goodness in the Ethics of Aristotle.Samuel Baker - 2017 - Philosophical Studies 174 (7):1839-1856.
    Kraut and other neo-Aristotelians have argued that there is no such thing as absolute goodness. They admit only good in a kind, e.g. a good sculptor, and good for something, e.g. good for fish. What is the view of Aristotle? Mostly limiting myself to the Nicomachean Ethics, I argue that Aristotle is committed to things being absolutely good and also to a metaphysics of absolute goodness where there is a maximally best good that is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  8.  38
    Kant's Argument for the Formula of the End in Itself.James Furner - 2017 - Idealistic Studies 47 (3):171-189.
    One approach to Kant’s argument for the Formula of the End in Itself takes Kant to ground FEI as a possible categorical imperative with a regressive argument that rests on a non-moral conception of rational nature. This paper presents a new, logical pluralism version of this approach. In conjunction with three other steps of argument, the logical pluralism version of the regressive argument grounds FEI by showing that an agent is rationally required to adopt a self-affirming plural standpoint, and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  17
    The idea of the Good in Plato’s Republic as an ontological principle.Wiesława Sajdek - 2022 - Philosophical Discourses 4:109-125.
    Plato gradually reaches the concept of the “Good itself” in the most extensive dialogue (apart from The Laws). The dramaturgy of Republic was included in the pedagogical idea. Plato’s own brothers, Glaucon and Adeimantus, representatives of the aristoia, want to hear from Socrates logically based instruction on what is really good and why, regardless of the prevailing public opinion in Athenian society. They both know that the most valued asset is the wealth and political influence that the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  23
    Reason and the Good in Plato’s Republic.Allan Silverman - 2024 - In David Keyt & Christopher Shields, Principles and Praxis in Ancient Greek Philosophy: Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy in Honor of Fred D. Miller, Jr. Springer Verlag. pp. 135-158.
    Let me begin with some of the background worries that motivate the paper. First, for years I have been working on the relation of the Timaeus to the Republic guided by this triple analogy: as the demiurge is to the cosmos, so the philosopher-ruler is to the polis, so reason is to the soul or individual. The key claim is Tim. 29e: the demiurge is good and so wants to make everything it makes like it itself is, i.e., (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  31
    Existence and the Good: Metaphysical Necessity in Morals and Politics by Franklin I. Gamwell.William Meyer - 2014 - Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 34 (1):228-230.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Existence and the Good: Metaphysical Necessity in Morals and Politics by Franklin I. GamwellWilliam MeyerExistence and the Good: Metaphysical Necessity in Morals and Politics FRANKLIN I. GAMWELL Albany: State University of New York Press, 2011. 219 pp. $24.95In the current era, a few prominent philosophers have called into question the antiteleological tendencies of modern thought. For instance, Thomas Nagel argues that we should reject the antiteleology (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  34
    The Good and its Relation to Music Education.Yaroslav Senyshyn - 2008 - Philosophy of Music Education Review 16 (2):174-192.
    An aesthetic distinction between good music and the good in music is crucial for a philosophy of music education. Ultimately, it is not the music's fault, as it were, that someone may view it as being 'not good' in either a social or aesthetic context. Regardless of how music is colored it remains an entity unto itself and thus untouched by our pronouncements. Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations recognized the falseness of such propositions as biased pronouncements taking the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  50
    The status and power of the good in Plato’s Republic.Fiona Leigh - 2023 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 31 (6):1269-1278.
    What is it for a judgement, action, or character state to be itself a good thing, so genuinely worth pursuing? Readers of Plato's Republic discover that that it is by standing in the right relation to the Form of the Good that other things are, or become, good. In her recent monograph, Plato's Sun-Like Good, Sarah Broadie inverts the standard interpretive strategy by focusing primarily on the role of the Good in dialectic, and drawing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  23
    The Good of Recognition: Phenomenology, Ethics, and Religion in the Thought of Lévinas and Ricœur by Michael Sohn. [REVIEW]Levi Checketts - 2017 - Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 37 (2):207-208.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content: Michael Sohn's book The Good of Recognition: Phenomenology, Ethics, and Religion in the Thought of Lévinas and Ricœur explores the philosophical and religious writings of two of twentieth-century France's most significant thinkers, Paul Ricœur and Emmanuel Lévinas, "to gain, by thinking with and through them, an insight into the phenomenon of recognition" (128). Recognition, to these authors, is not merely an act of re-cognition (identifying something one (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  3
    The Value of Mere Willing: Revisiting Kant’s Argument for the Formula of the End in Itself.Tom Bailey - 2025 - Kant Studien 116 (1):1-21.
    In this article I attempt to explain Kant’s notoriously obscure argument for the principle that every rational being should be treated as an “end,” and not merely as a means. I take my lead from the appearance in the argument of terms and ideas that he uses earlier in the Groundwork to express two distinctive features of moral value and to make a related claim about how moral value is achieved. I argue that, of the candidates for the “end” of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. The Radical Unknowability of the Thing in Itself.Stephen Palmquist - unknown
    Few commentators (if any) would question Schrader's poignant obser­vation that 'the doctrine of the thing in itself presents the single greatest stumbling block in the Kantian philosophy' [S5:49]. Understanding what Kant meant by the doctrine i.e., the role it plays both in his overall System and in his transcendental idealism can help prevent it from being discarded 'as a per­versity' [49], inasmuch as it can be interpreted in such a way that it makes quite good sense [see VI.2]. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  84
    Knowledge, Nature, and the Good: Essays on Ancient Philosophy.John M. Cooper - 2004 - Princeton University Press.
    Knowledge, Nature, and the Good brings together some of John Cooper's most important works on ancient philosophy. In thirteen chapters that represent an ideal companion to the author's influential Reason and Emotion, Cooper addresses a wide range of topics and periods--from Hippocratic medical theory and Plato's epistemology and moral philosophy, to Aristotle's physics and metaphysics, academic scepticism, and the cosmology, moral psychology, and ethical theory of the ancient Stoics.Almost half of the pieces appear here for the first time or (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  18.  43
    The quest for the good life in Rousseau's Emile: an assessment.Yossi Yonah - 1993 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 12 (2):229-243.
    Rousseau's Emile has attracted an avalanche of critical responses. His theme of negative education, or as he defines it, “well-regulated freedom”, has been denounced as outright manipulation in disguise, which instead of respecting the child's autonomy and dignity, places him at the whim of the teacher's machinations and stratagems. His recommendation that the child's imagination be curtailed (that he may not acquire desires which cannot be satisfied) is widely held to militate against one of the most cherished goals of education: (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  13
    Aiming at the good life in the datafied world: A co-productionist framework of ethics.Margarita Boenig-Liptsin - 2022 - Big Data and Society 9 (2).
    This article proposes an ethical framework to navigate life in the datafied world that combines the relational ethics approach of the philosopher Paul Ricoeur with the idiom of co-production from the field of Science and Technology Studies (STS). Mainstream data and computing ethics approaches, which tend to view ethics itself as a technology to produce particular outcomes, fail to adequately consider the context of the datafied world for ethics. The datafied world is a condition in which data and computing (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  19
    Form and Good in Plato's Eleatic Dialogues: The "'Parmenides," "Theaetetus," "Sophist," and "Statesman" (review). [REVIEW]David Ambuel - 1995 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (4):679-680.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Book Reviews Kenneth Dorter. Form and Good in Plato's Eleatic Dialogues: The "'Parmenides," "Theaetetus," "Sophist," and "Statesman." Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1994. Pp. x + 256. Cloth, $45.00. Dorter's title suggests an engagement with Eieaticism, and, certainly in three of" the dialogues, Parmenides was much on Plato's mind. In a book otherwise sensitive to implications of dramatic setting for the argument, little is said (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  22
    Guilt, Self-Awareness, and the Good Will in Kierkegaard’s Confessional Discourses.Jeffrey Morgan - 2020 - Studies in Christian Ethics 33 (3):352-370.
    The specific aim of this article is to focus on Kierkegaard’s confessional discourses and to examine his appreciation for the experience of guilt—the feeling of guilt and the acknowledgment of guilt—in a person’s efforts to act with a good will, or what he calls ‘purity of heart’. The article offers an interpretation of what Kierkegaard means by the ‘purity of heart’ that guilt serves, and it makes an argument that in this service to ‘purity of heart’ the relationship between (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Plato's Division of Goods in the Republic.Robert Heinaman - 2002 - Phronesis 47 (4):309-335.
    In the "Republic" Plato draws a distinction among goods between (1) those that are good in themselves but not good for their consequences, (2) those that are good both in themselves and for their consequences, and (3) those that are not good in themselves but are good for their consequences. This paper presents an interpretation of this classification, in particular its application to the case of justice. It is argued that certain causal consequences of justice (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  23.  60
    Constructing Good Decisions in Ethically Charged Situations: The Role of Dramatic Rehearsal.John F. McVea - 2007 - Journal of Business Ethics 70 (4):375-390.
    This paper develops a pragmatist approach to ethical business decision-making. It draws primarily on the work of John Dewey and applies his deliberative approach to ethics to the challenges of business practitioners. In particular the paper proposes the value of Dewey’s concept of dramatic rehearsal in emphasizing the task of “constructing the good” in ethical decision-making. The contribution of the paper is, first, to build on recent foundational work to bring American pragmatism into the mainstream business ethics literature; second, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  24.  69
    Making Sense of Common Good in Contemporary Society.M. Lorenz Moises J. Festin - 2008 - Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 50:171-176.
    The main purpose of the paper is to investigate the relevance and significance of the concept of common good in contemporary society. First, I make a brief historical remark about the philosophical concept of common good. I will argue that the concept is rooted in the ancient Greek philosophical understanding of society, namely as polis, whereby human being is thought to have an end that is not merely individual but also collective. I then discuss how societies have significantly (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. The Ethics of Motion: Self-Preservation, Preservation of the Whole, and the ‘Double Nature of the Good’ in Francis Bacon.Manzo Silvia - 2016 - In Lancaster Gilgioni, Motion and Power in Francis Bacon's Philosophy. Springer. pp. 175-200.
    This chapter focuses on the appetite for self-preservation and its central role in Francis Bacon’s natural philosophy. In the first part, I introduce Bacon’s classification of universal appetites, showing the correspondences between natural and moral philosophy. I then examine the role that appetites play in his theory of motions and, additionally, the various meanings accorded to preservation in this context. I also discuss some of the sources underlying Bacon’s ideas, for his views about preservation reveal traces of Stoicism, Telesian natural (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. The Final Good in Aristotle's Ethics.W. F. R. Hardie - 1965 - Philosophy 40 (154):277-295.
    Aristotle maintains that every man has, or should have, a single end, a target at which he aims. The doctrine is stated in E.N. I 2. ‘If, then, there is some end of the things we do which we desire for its own sake, and if we do not choose everything for the sake of something else, clearly this must be the good and the chief good. Will not the knowledge of it, then, have a great influence on (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  27. Pleasure and the Good Life: Concerning the Nature Varieties and Plausibility of Hedonism.Fred Feldman - 2004 - Oxford, GB: Clarendon Press. Edited by Fred Feldman.
    Fred Feldman's fascinating new book sets out to defend hedonism as a theory about the Good Life. He tries to show that, when carefully and charitably interpreted, certain forms of hedonism yield plausible evaluations of human lives. Feldman begins by explaining the question about the Good Life. As he understands it, the question is not about the morally good life or about the beneficial life. Rather, the question concerns the general features of the life that is (...) in itself for the one who lives it. Hedonism says (roughly) that the Good Life is the pleasant life. After showing that received formulations of hedonism are often confused or incoherent, Feldman presents a simple, clear, coherent form of sensory hedonism that provides a starting point for discussion. He then presents a catalogue of classic objections to hedonism, coming from sources as diverse as Plato, Aristotle, Brentano, Ross, Moore, Rawls, Kagan, Nozick, Brandt, and others. One of Feldman's central themes is that there is an important distinction between the forms of hedonism that emphasize sensory pleasure and those that emphasize attitudinal pleasure. Feldman formulates several kinds of hedonism based on the idea that attitudinal pleasure is the Good. He claims that attitudinal forms of hedonism - which have often been ignored in the literature -- are worthy of more careful attention. Another main theme of the book is the plasticity of hedonism. Hedonism comes in many forms. Attitudinal hedonism is especially receptive to variations and modifications. Feldman illustrates this plasticity by formulating several variants of attitudinal hedonism and showing how they evade some of the objections. He also shows how it is possible to develop forms of hedonism that are equivalent to the allegedly anti-hedonistic theory of G. E. Moore and the Aristotelian theory according to which the Good Life is the life of virtue, or flourishing. He also formulates hedonisms relevantly like the ones defended by Aristippus and Mill. Feldman argues that a carefully developed form of attitudinal hedonism is not refuted by objections concerning 'the shape of a life'. He also defends the claim that all of the alleged forms of hedonism discussed in the book genuinely deserve to be called 'hedonism'. Finally, after dealing with the last of the objections, he gives a sketch of his hedonistic vision of the Good Life. (shrink)
  28.  16
    Nietzsche’s Philosophy of Education: Rethinking Ethics, Equality and the Good Life in a Democratic Age.Mark E. Jonas & Douglas Yacek - 2018 - New York: Routledge. Edited by Douglas W. Yacek.
    Nietzsche's Philosophy of Education makes the case that Nietzsche's ​philosophy has ​significant import for the theory and contemporary practice of education, arguing that ​some of ​Nietzsche​'s most important ​ideas ​have been misunderstood by ​previous ​interpreters. ​In ​providing novel reinterpretations of ​Nietzsche's ​ethical theory, political​ philosophy​ and philosophical anthropology ​and outlining concrete ways in which ​these ideas can enrich teaching and learning in modern democratic schools, the book sets itself apart​ from previous works on Nietzsche​. This is one of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  26
    All Too Human:" Animal Wisdom" in Nietzsche's Account of the Good Life.Jonathan D. Singer - 2011 - Between the Species 14 (1):2.
    In this paper I argue that a certain understanding of “animality” – or that a certain problematization of the traditional human-animal hierarchy and divide – is central to Nietzsche’s account of the good life. Nietzsche’s philosophical project is primarily directed against those “metaphysical oppositions of values” that traditionally structure how we think, feel and live, and in this paper I submit that, for Nietzsche, the classical opposition between the human and the animal is the most basic and the most (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  11
    Gradual Victory of Good in Church History.Stephen R. Palmquist - 2015 - In Comprehensive commentary on Kant's Religion within the bounds of bare reason. Hoboken: Wiley. pp. 326–376.
    In this chapter, Immanuel Kant's account of the history of the true (universal) church has a clear progression. It moves from a discussion of Jesus’ radical break with all that was nonuniversal in Judaism, to the tendency of Christians down through the ages to shape their faith into something just as nonuniversal as Judaism. Kant's account concludes with reflections on why we have good reason to be optimistic for the future, because Kant's own interpretation of pure moral religion portrays (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  17
    Why It Wouldn't Be Rational to Believe You're in The Good Place (and Why You Wouldn't Want to Be There Anyway).David Kyle Johnson - 2020 - In Kimberly S. Engels, The Good Place and Philosophy. Wiley. pp. 270–282.
    The Good Place is about moral philosophy. But one reason everyone hates moral philosophers is that they think everything is about ethics. When it comes to the Good Place versus Bad Place hypothesis, the big giveaway is simplicity. The Good Place hypothesis doesn't require a grand deception and all the planning that would be necessary to keep it afloat. The Bad Place hypothesis does. The biggest worry about an eternal life in something like The Good Place (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  26
    The Good Faith of the Invisible Man.Naomi Zack - 1998 - The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 27:108-112.
    I use Ralph Ellison's Invisible Man to consider the requirements of existentialism to be relevant to racialized experience. Black existentialism is distinguished from white existentialism by its focus on anti-black racism. However, black existentialism is similar to white existentialism in its moral requirement that agents take responsibility so as to be in good faith. Ralph Ellison's invisible man displays good faith at the end of the novel by assuming responsibility for his particular situation. The idiosyncratic development of the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  63
    Evil as the good? A reply to Brook Ziporyn.David Loy - 2005 - Philosophy East and West 55 (2):348-352.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Evil as the Good?A Reply to Brook ZiporynDavid R. LoyI was surprised to receive this lengthy response to my short review—yet not displeased, for the important question is, of course, how much Professor Ziporyn's reply helps to clarify the issues at stake, which we agree deserve to be pursued. One of the many admirable aspects of his Evil and/or/as the Good is that, in addition to presenting (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  32
    Poetic Experience and the Good Life in the Writings of Michael Oakeshott.Glenn Worthington - 2005 - European Journal of Political Theory 4 (1):57-66.
    The article argues that attending to Oakeshott’s characterization of poetic experience shows his moral philosophy to possess dimensions that can be otherwise overlooked. The first of these dimensions is the authenticity or success with which a self realizes or creates itself as a moral being. The second area of Oakeshott’s moral philosophy that is brought to light by attending to his account of poetic experience is his account of society as a tapestry of moral images.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  43
    The Irrationality of the Good.C. E. M. Joad - 1926 - Philosophy 1 (4):497-506.
    The theories of most writers on Ethics, with whose works I am acquainted, appear to be based upon the assumption of the unique character of goodness or The Good. By the word unique these writers mean, I think, among other things that goodness cannot be analysed into or described in terms of anything other than itself, that it can be and is desired for its own sake and not for the sake of some other thing which is not (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  66
    The cadherin–catenin complex as a focal point of cell adhesion and signalling: new insights from three‐dimensional structures.Jane M. Gooding, Kyoko L. Yap & Mitsuhiko Ikura - 2004 - Bioessays 26 (5):497-511.
    Cadherins are a large family of single‐pass transmembrane proteins principally involved in Ca2+‐dependent homotypic cell adhesion. The cadherin molecules comprise three domains, the intracellular domain, the transmembrane domain and the extracellular domain, and form large complexes with a vast array of binding partners (including cadherin molecules of the same type in homophilic interactions and cellular protein catenins), orchestrating biologically essential extracellular and intracellular signalling processes. While current, contrasting models for classic cadherin homophilic interaction involve varying numbers of specific repeats found (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  16
    The question of the good life: an indirect approach.Eduardo Fermandois - 2019 - Veritas – Revista de Filosofia da Pucrs 44:49-68.
    Resumen Dada la renovada vigencia que la antigua pregunta socrática: ¿cómo se debería vivir? goza en nuestros días -en particular, en el ámbito anglosajón y alemán-, no extraña que los diferentes enfoques vengan acompañados a menudo por con sideraciones de índole metodológica. ¿Cómo abordar hoy la proverbial pregunta? ¿Con qué criterios de corrección debería cumplir una teoría de la vida buena? ¿Es siquiera posible una tal teoría? El propósito de la presente reflexión es contribuir al esclarecimiento de estas cuestiones mediante (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  28
    Ethical expertise: The good agent and the good citizen.David Archard - 2020 - Zeitschrift Für Ethik Und Moralphilosophie 3 (2):337-344.
    I consider whether political deference by a citizen within a liberal democracy to moral experts is morally problematic. I compare and contrast deference in the political and personal domains. I set to one side consequentialist worries about political deference and evaluate its possible intrinsic wrongness, expressed as a worry that deference is inconsistent with the grant to individuals of the power exercised in a democratic vote, just as personal deference is inconsistent with the grant of a power of moral choice. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  13
    Willing the good: empirical challenges to the explanation of human behavior.Gabriele De Anna (ed.) - 2012 - Newcastle upon Tyne, UK: Cambridge Scholars Press.
    Science increasingly deals with human behavior: biology, neuroscience, genetics, psychology, evolutionary theory, and ethology all bring new insights into our actions and uncover new facts about our agency. However, what is the philosophical significance of their findings? The answer to this question varies according to one's background philosophical views. On the one hand, the dominant empiricist view contends that the sciences can in principle tell us everything there is to know about human agency. On the other hand, there are other (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  67
    In the name of the spirits -- a reading of solov'ëv's justification of the good.Anton Simons - 1999 - Studies in East European Thought 51 (3):177-198.
    In this contribution, the author analyzes Vladimir Solov''ëv''s intention to study the idea of the Good as something relatively independent from religion and metaphysics. Some implications of Solov''ëv''s definition of moral philosophy in The Justification of the Good are investigated, and illustrated with his applied ethics of war in chapter 18 of this book. It appears that Solov''ëv''s moral philosophy and his account of war must be understood in connection with the central place of the cult of ancestors (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  30
    Don Quijote and the Law of Literature.Carl Good - 1999 - Diacritics 29 (2):44-67.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Don Quijote and the Law of LiteratureCarl Good (bio)The part is one of these beings, the whole minus this part the other. But the whole minus a part is not the whole and as long as this relationship persists, there is no whole, only two unequal parts.—Rousseau, Social Contract, cited by Paul de Man in Allegories of ReadingBut it is not just that, because it is also a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  83
    The Two Categorizations of Goods in Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics.Bradford Jean-Hyuk Kim - 2021 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 38 (4):297-315.
    This article resolves some difficulties with Aristotle's discussion of the choice-worthy (haireton). Nicomachean Ethics I posits goods that are choice-worthy for themselves and for something else, but Nicomachean Ethics X appears to present being choice-worthy for itself as mutually exclusive with being choice-worthy for something else; moreover, Nicomachean Ethics X seems to claim that action is choice-worthy for itself and, therefore, not choice-worthy for something else but also seems to claim that action is choice-worthy for something else and, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  52
    Rights, Capabilities, and the Good Society.Robin West - unknown
    In Part I this essay explores and then criticizes the two major arguments behind the conventional wisdom that rights undermine efforts to secure a state role in ensuring the material preconditions for a good society, and therefore, the material preconditions for the development of those human capabilities essential to a fully human life. I conclude in this part that this understanding of rights is mistaken. In Part II, I urge that the pragmatic argument put forward by rights critics and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  48
    Review: Nature in american philosophy. [REVIEW]James Good - 2008 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 44 (3):pp. 541-547.
    Although he had intermittently toiled over his translation of Hegel's Science of Logic for nearly half a century without finding a publisher, Henry Conrad Brokmeyer, the petulant visionary of St. Louis Hegelian fame, concluded it was naive to expect an infant nation to devote itself to philosophical reflection while it was "carving civilization out of wilderness." Brokmeyer's difficulties may have had more to do with his disdain for the grammatical and spelling conventions of the English language than he cared (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. My Duty and the Morality of Others: Lying, Truth, and the Good Example in Fichte’s Normative Perfectionism.Stefano Bacin - 2021 - In Stefano Bacin & Owen Ware, Fichte's _System of Ethics_: A Critical Guide. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. pp. 201-220.
    The aim of the paper is to shed light on some of the most original elements of Fichte’s conception of morality as expressed in his account of specific obligations. After some remarks on Fichte’s original classification of ethical duties, the paper focuses on the prohibition of lying, the duty to communicate our true knowledge, and the duty to set a good example. Fichte’s account of those duties not only goes beyond the mere justification of universally acknowledged demands, but also (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  46. Realism About the Good For Human Beings.Nandi Theunissen - 2023 - In Paul Bloomfield & David Copp, Oxford Handbook of Moral Realism. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
    Against those who contend that there is a basic duality between the moral and the non-moral good, or the right and the good, I articulate a form of realism that works with a unified conception of the good in which virtue and benefit are key concepts, and in which the “moral good” is not foundationally distinctive, but explicable in terms of the good for human beings. I argue: (a) that virtuous actions are such because and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  10
    The Centrality of the Good: Reflections on Politics and Being.Scott John Hammond - 2010 - Lexington Books, a Division of Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
    Introduction -- Structuring principles -- On right -- From interest and pleasure to the good in-itself -- Good in-itself and the rights of the ensouled person -- The good and friendship in the community of free souls -- The rehabilitation of politics through the recovery of its essence.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  49
    Why the Good is supremely good: a defence of the Monologion proof.Christophe de Ray - forthcoming - Religious Studies:1-17.
    The opening chapters of Anselm's Monologion contain a ‘proof’ of a perfect being, which has received far less attention than the more famous Proslogion proof, and the ontological arguments derived from it. I wish to rectify this by developing an argument in defence of a crucial premise of the Monologion proof. This premise states that ‘the Good’, i.e. that in virtue of which numerically distinct things may all be good, must itself be a supremely good thing. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  12
    "A World Against Itself": The Dynamics of Good Nature and Virtue in Henry Fielding's Plays.Amel Ben Ahmed - 2019 - Labyrinth: An International Journal for Philosophy, Value Theory and Sociocultural Hermeneutics 21 (2):177-196.
    In the eighteenth-century England, the aesthetic vision of most contemporary writers of the time was closely related to the social, political and religious system of belief. Augustan writers, satirists particularly, sought to reclaim for literature the morally privileged status, they thought, it supposedly held in the context of the Latitudinarian system of thought; the very rationale behind the ethic of good nature that distinguishes major writings of the time, namely the dramatic, journalistic and fictional works of the major eighteenth (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Virtue as Loving the Good.Thomas Hurka - 1992 - Social Philosophy and Policy 9 (2):149.
    In a chapter of The Methods of Ethics entitled “Ultimate Good”, Henry Sidgwick defends hedonism, the theory that pleasure and only pleasure is intrinsically good, that is, good in itself and apart from its consequences. First, however, he argues against the theory that virtue is intrinsically good. Sidgwick considers both a strong version of this theory — that virtue is the only intrinsic good — and a weaker version — that it is one intrinsic (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
1 — 50 / 971