Results for ' Keith Haring'

956 found
Order:
  1.  50
    Keith Haring, Felix Gonzalez-Torres, Wolfgang Tillmans, and the AIDS Epidemic: The Use of Visual Art in a Health Humanities Course.Jason A. Smith - 2019 - Journal of Medical Humanities 40 (2):181-198.
    Contemporary art can be a powerful pedagogical tool in the health humanities. Students in an undergraduate course in the health humanities explore the subjective experience of illness and develop their empathy by studying three artists in the context of the AIDS epidemic: Keith Haring, Felix Gonzalez-Torres, and Wolfgang Tillmans. Using assignments based in narrative pedagogy, students expand their empathic response to pain and suffering. The role of visual art in health humanities pedagogy is discussed.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  43
    Depression reduces perceptual sensitivity for positive words and pictures.Ruth Ann Atchley, Stephen S. Ilardi, Keith M. Young, Natalie N. Stroupe, Aminda J. O'Hare, Steven L. Bistricky, Elizabeth Collison, Linzi Gibson, Jonathan Schuster & Rebecca J. Lepping - 2012 - Cognition and Emotion 26 (8):1359-1370.
  3.  14
    Keith Haring. Artre per Tutti.Curtis Carter - unknown
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  83
    Hare's route from universal prescriptivism to utilitarianism.Keith Dowling - 1992 - Philosophical Papers 21 (1):65-81.
  5.  38
    The invisible within: Dispersing masculinity in art.Gregory Minissale - 2015 - Angelaki 20 (1):71-83.
    :Visual culture – art, film, entertainment, advertising – are saturated with images of normative heterosexual masculinity. They form visual narratives that project a largely coherent kind of masculinity where heterosexual men are shown to be creative and powerful; they initiate heroic action, take the moral high ground and preserve traditional roles and the status quo. This widely extensive visual field, peopled with normative images of masculinity, also affects and infiltrates the domain of art exemplified by Jackson Pollock and abstract expressionism (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Proceedings of the British Academy, Volume 124. Biographical Memoirs of Fellows, III.P. Marshall (ed.) - 2004 - British Academy.
    Keith Thomas: Gerald Edward Aylmer, 1926-2000 Adrian Hollis: William Spencer Barrett, 1914-2001 Bruce Williams: Charles Frederick Carter, 1919-2002 Malcolm Mackintosh: John Erickson, 1929-2002 J. H .R. Davis: Raymond William Firth, 1901-2002 F. M. L. Thompson: Hrothgar John Habakkuk, 1915-2002 A. W. Price: Richard Mervyn Hare, 1919-2002 Hugh Lloyd-Jones: Geoffrey Stephen Kirk, 1921-2003 Michael Lapidge and Peter Matthews: Vivien Anne Law, 1954-2002 Ann Moss: John Lough, 1913-2000 Terence Cave: Ian Dalrymple McFarlane, 1915-2002 Ludwig Paul: David Neil MacKenzie, 1926-2001 Peter Birks: (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Abstract particulars.Keith Campbell - 1990 - Cambridge, Mass., USA: Blackwell.
  8. The ethics of carbon offsetting.Keith Hyams & Tina Fawcett - 2013 - Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Climate Change 4 (2):91-98.
    Carbon offsetting can be loosely characterized as a mechanism by which an organization or individual contributes to a scheme that is projected either to remove carbon dioxide from the atmosphere or to deliver carbon dioxide emission reductions on the part of other organizations or individuals. An activity that has been offset therefore purports to make no long-term net contribution to atmospheric greenhouse gas concentrations. The ethical basis for using carbon offsetting as an approach to tackling climate change is very much (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  9. Proper names and identifying descriptions.Keith S. Donnellan - 1970 - Synthese 21 (3-4):335 - 358.
  10. Proceedings of the British Academy, Volume 139, 2005 Lectures.Wrightson Keith - 2006
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. (1 other version)Condorcet: From Natural Philosophy to Social Mathematics.Keith Michael Baker - 1975 - Political Theory 3 (4):469-474.
  12. Testimony and trustworthiness.Keith Lehrer - 2006 - In Jennifer Lackey & Ernest Sosa (eds.), The epistemology of testimony. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 145--159.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  13.  41
    The Case for Investment Advising as a Virtue-Based Practice.Keith D. Wyma - 2015 - Journal of Business Ethics 127 (1):231-249.
    Contemporary virtue ethics was revolutionized by Alasdair MacIntyre’s reconfiguration using practices as the starting point for understanding virtues. However, MacIntyre has very pointedly excluded the professions of the financial world from the reformulation. He does not count these professions as practices, and further charges that virtue would actually hinder or even rule out one’s pursuit of these professions. This paper addresses three tasks, in regard to the financial profession of investment advising. First, the paper lays out MacIntyre’s soon-to-be-published charges against (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  14. Spinoza on Turning the Other Cheek.Keith Green - 2018 - Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy 8:96-133.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Content and Consciousness.Keith Gunderson - 1972 - And the Mind-Body Problem.
  16. The Taming of Content: Some Thoughts About Domains and Modules.Keith J. Holyoak & Patricia W. Cheng - forthcoming - Thinking and Reasoning.
  17. “Bamboozled by Our Own Words”: Semantic Blindness and Some Arguments Against Contextualism.Keith Derose - 2006 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (2):316 - 338.
    The best grounds for accepting contextualism concerning knowledge attributions are to be found in how knowledge-attributing (and knowledge-denying) sentences are used in ordinary, nonphilosophical talk: What ordinary speakers will count as “knowledge” in some non-philosophical contexts they will deny is such in others. Contextualists typically appeal to pairs of cases that forcefully display the variability in the epistemic standards that govern ordinary usage: A “low standards” case (henceforth, “LOW”) in which a speaker seems quite appropriately and truthfully to ascribe knowledge (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  18. Plurals and complexes.Keith Hossack - 2000 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51 (3):411-443.
    Atomism denies that complexes exist. Common-sense metaphysics may posit masses, composite individuals and sets, but atomism says there are only simples. In a singularist logic, it is difficult to make a plausible case for atomism. But we should accept plural logic, and then atomism can paraphrase away apparent reference to complexes. The paraphrases require unfamiliar plural universals, but these are of independent interest; for example, we can identify numbers and sets with plural universals. The atomist paraphrases would fail if plurals (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  19.  4
    What Colour Are Numbers?Keith McVeigh - 2020 - Philosophy Now 139:58-58.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  13
    Reason and consistency.Keith Lehrer - 1975 - In Roderick M. Chisholm & Keith Lehrer (eds.), Analysis and metaphysics: essays in honor of R. M. Chisholm. Boston: D. Reidel Pub. Co.. pp. 57--74.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  21. Paradigm-Case Argument.Keith S. Donnellan - 1967 - In Paul Edwards (ed.), The Encyclopedia of philosophy. New York,: Macmillan. pp. 103-116.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22.  40
    Perceptions and representations: the theoretical bases of brain research and psychology.Keith Oatley - 1978 - London: Methuen.
    problems in psychology The three themes of this book are the relation of the brain's structure to psychological function, the problem of how people perceive ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  23.  27
    Buddhist philosophy in India and Ceylon.Arthur Berriedale Keith - 1923 - New York: Gordon Press.
    Asl. Atthasalinl of Buddhaghosa, ed. PTS. 1897. BB. Bibliotheca Buddhica, Petrograd. BC. Buddhacarita, ed. Cowell, Oxford, 1893. BCA. ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  24. Partial Belief and Flat-out Belief.Keith Frankish - 2009 - In Franz Huber & Christoph Schmidt-Petri (eds.), Degrees of belief. London: Springer. pp. 75--93.
    There is a duality in our everyday view of belief. On the one hand, we sometimes speak of credence as a matter of degree. We talk of having some level of confidence in a claim (that a certain course of action is safe, for example, or that a desired event will occur) and explain our actions by reference to these degrees of confidence – tacitly appealing, it seems, to a probabilistic calculus such as that formalized in Bayesian decision theory. On (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  25. Is classical mechanics really time-reversible and deterministic?Keith Hutchison - 1993 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44 (2):307-323.
  26. Reid, Hume and common sense.Keith Lehrer & Carl Wagner - 1998 - Reid Studies 2 (1):15-26.
  27.  18
    The Theaetetus Ends Well.E. S. Haring - 1982 - Review of Metaphysics 35 (3):509 - 528.
    ON ITS surface the Theaetetus ends inconclusively. It has even been said to end in failure. Yet this dialogue is exceptionally full of promise. The speakers are singularly well disposed. Two of them are gifted and resemble one another in looks and interests. Inquiry progresses splendidly through most of a long conversation. Although Theaetetus's first two definitions have to be given up, he is in the process led through a meticulous survey of cognition. These and other circumstances are too auspicious (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  28. No Good Arguments for Causal Closure.Keith Buhler - 2020 - Metaphysica 21 (2):223-236.
    Many common arguments for physicalism begin with the principle that the cosmos is “causally closed.” But how good are the arguments for causal closure itself? I argue that the deductive, a priori arguments on behalf of causal closure tend to beg the question. The extant inductive arguments fare no better. They commit a sampling error or a non-sequitur, or else offer conclusions that remain compatible with causal openness. In short, we have no good arguments that the physical world is causally (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  29.  10
    God, man, and religion.Keith E. Yandell - 1973 - New York,: McGraw-Hill.
  30. Richard R. LaCroix, Proslogion II and III: A Third Interpretation of Anselm's Argument.Keith E. Yandell - 1974 - Journal of Value Inquiry 8 (2):143.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  26
    Interpretation, representation, and deductive reasoning.Keith Stenning & Michiel van Lambalgen - 2008 - In Jonathan Eric Adler & Lance J. Rips (eds.), Reasoning: Studies of Human Inference and its Foundations. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 223-248.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  32. The Disorder of Political Inquiry.Keith Topper - 2007 - Human Studies 30 (3):275-280.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  33.  40
    The IRB paradox: Could the protectors also encourage deceit?Patricia Keith-Spiegel & Gerald P. Koocher - 2005 - Ethics and Behavior 15 (4):339 – 349.
    The efforts of some institutional review boards (IRBs) to exercise what is viewed as appropriate oversight may contribute to deceit on the part of investigators who feel unjustly treated. An organizational justice paradigm provides a useful context for exploring why certain IRB behaviors may lead investigators to believe that they have not received fair treatment. These feelings may, in turn, lead to intentional deception by investigators that IRBs will rarely detect. Paradoxically, excessive protective zeal by IRBs may actually encourage misconduct (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  34.  79
    Matter and Consciousness: A Contemporary Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind.Keith Gunderson - 1986 - Philosophy of Science 53 (1):145-148.
  35.  21
    Home dissatisfaction, body image and sociocultural attitudes.Keith Allen, Nicholas Pleace & Daryl Martin - 2023 - Housing, Theory and Society 1.
    This article explores home dissatisfaction using methods modelled on those used to understand negative body image and its causes. We found that a substantial proportion of UK participants (13–39%) expressed dissatisfaction with their homes. Although the strongest association was between home dissatisfaction and reported physical problems, there was evidence that dissatisfaction is also predicted by experiencing pressure from the media and your family to improve your home, as well as reporting a greater tendency to compare your home to others’. The (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  67
    Probability amalgamation and the independence issue: A reply to Laddaga.Keith Lehrer & Carl Wagner - 1983 - Synthese 55 (3):339 - 346.
  37. Ought we to follow our evidence?Keith Derose - 2000 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (3):697-706.
    fits our evidence.[1] I will propose some potential counter-examples to test this evidentialist thesis. My main intention in presenting the “counter-examples” is to better understand Feldman’s evidentialism, and evidentialism in general. How are we to understand what our evidence is, how it works, and how are we to understand the phrase “epistemically ought to believe” such that evidentialism might make sense as a plausible thesis in light of the examples? Of course, we may decide that there’s no such way to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  38. 'Can' in theory and practice: A possible worlds analysis.Keith Lehrer - 1976 - In M. Brand & Douglas Walton (eds.), Action Theory. Reidel. pp. 241-270.
  39. Reference and paradox.Keith Simmons - 2003 - In J. C. Beall (ed.), Liars and Heaps: New Essays on Paradox. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press UK. pp. 230--252.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40. Predicting Outcomes in the Very Preterm Infant.Keith Barrington - 2015 - In Annie Janvier & Eduard Verhagen (eds.), Ethical Dilemmas for Critically Ill Babies. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  15
    Enki and the Embodied World.Keith Dickson - 2005 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 125 (4):499-515.
  42.  7
    The sociology of belief: fallacy and foundation.Keith Dixon - 1980 - Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  43.  38
    Socratic Duplicity: Theaetetus 154b1-156a3.E. S. Haring - 1992 - Review of Metaphysics 45 (3):525 - 542.
    THE PASSAGE CITED IN THE TITLE IS commonly said to deal with puzzles or paradoxes about size and other measurable attributes of bodies. Nearly all recent commentators seek to interpret this portion of the dialogue as supporting or otherwise cohering with the Protagorean position Socrates expounds in the Theaetetus. On the present analysis, however, the support or harmony is mere appearance. The puzzles Socrates brings up are indeed associated with entities rejected by Protagoras. Socrates certainly uses the puzzles to foster (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  40
    Substantial Form in Aristotle's "Metaphysics" Z; III.Ellen Stone Haring - 1957 - Review of Metaphysics 10 (4):698 - 713.
    "Wherein can consist the unity of that, the formula of which we call a definition, as for instance in the case of man, 'two-footed animal'; for let this be the formula of man. Why, then, is this one, and not many, viz. 'animal' and 'two-footed'? This is how the problem is stated. 'Animal' and 'two-footed' do make a unity, and they should, since: "The definition is a single formula and a formula of substance, so that it must be a formula (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Sensibilidad, indiscernibilidad y conocimiento.Keith Lehrer - 2000 - Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 19 (3):41-45.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. The Open Curtain: A U.S.-Soviet Philosophy Summit.Keith Lehrer & Ernest Sosa - 1994 - Studies in East European Thought 46 (4):321-323.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  20
    Human Ecology, Environmental Ecology, and a Ressourcement Theology.Keith Lemna - 2011 - Logos: A Journal of Catholic Thought and Culture 14 (3):133-154.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. On pluralism within originalism.Keith E. Whittington - 2011 - In Grant Huscroft & Bradley W. Miller (eds.), The challenge of originalism: theories of constitutional interpretation. New York: Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. The duality of mind: an historical perspective.Keith Frankish & Jsbt Evans - 2009 - In Jonathan St B. T. Evans & Keith Frankish (eds.), In Two Minds: Dual Processes and Beyond. Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  50. Heraclitus' Rebuke of Polymathy: A Core Element in the Reflectiveness of His Thought.Keith Begley - 2020 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 23 (1):21–50.
    I offer an examination of a core element in the reflectiveness of Heraclitus’ thought, namely, his rebuke of polymathy . In doing so, I provide a response to a recent claim that Heraclitus should not be considered to be a philosopher, by attending to his paradigmatically philosophical traits. Regarding Heraclitus’ attitude to that naïve form of ‘wisdom’, i.e., polymathy, I argue that he does not advise avoiding experience of many things, rather, he advises rejecting experience of things as merely many (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 956