Results for 'transcendental ideal'

971 found
Order:
See also
  1. The Transcendental Ideality of Space and the Neglected Alternative.Peter Herissone-Kelly - 2007 - Kant Studien 98 (3):269-282.
    In the Transcendental Aesthetic, Kant famously makes the following startling claim, which we can call the transcendental ideality thesis concerning the nature of space, or, for ease of reference in what follows, simply “TI”: Der Raum stellt gar keine Eigenschaft irgend einiger Dinge an sich, oder sie in ihrem Verhältniß auf einander vor, d.i. keine Bestimmung derselben, die an Gegenständen selbst haftete, und welche bliebe, wenn man auch von allen subjectiven Bedingungen der Anschauung abstrahirte.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  2.  94
    The Transcendental Ideal and the Unity of the Critical System.Béatrice Longuenesse - 1995 - Proceedings of the Eighth International Kant Congress 1:521-537.
  3.  96
    The Transcendental Ideality and Empirical Reality of Kant's Space and Time.George A. Schrader - 1951 - Review of Metaphysics 4 (4):507 - 536.
    There is a second way in which the question is capable of a twofold interpretation. One might begin with a priori concepts which have no empirical reference and ask how they can apply to objects. Or, one might deny the dichotomy between the a priori and experience and inquire how synthetic a priori judgments about experience can be accounted for. Initially Kant regarded the problem of schematism in the former way as that of bringing together two divorced realms. From this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  15
    The Transcendental Ideality of Sets and Objects.D. L. C. Maclachlan - 1989 - Proceedings of the Sixth International Kant Congress 2 (1):251-258.
  5. Transcendental ideality or absolute reality of time? Time for the subject and time for the world in Kant.Christophe Bouton - 2012 - Kant Studien 103 (4).
  6.  12
    Leibniz, Kant, the Transcendental Ideality of Space and Modern Geometry.Ricardo Parellada - 2003 - Studia Leibnitiana 35 (2):244 - 254.
    Kants Argument zugunsten der Idealität und Subjektivität des Raumes stellt eine Erklärung dar für die Möglichkeit, Geometrie für die Kenntnis der Natur anzuwenden. Gemäß dem transzendentalen Idealismus können geometrische Sätze, die notwendig und a priori sind, auf empirische Objekte angewendet werden, weil der Raum auf das Subjekt zurückgeht. Kant entwickelte seine Konzeption des synthetischen Charakters der Geometrie im Gegensatz zu Leibniz' analytischer Auffassung, aber der Verfasser argumentiert, dass die Einführung nichteuklidischer geometrischer Strukturen eher Leibniz' als Kants geometrischer Konzeption entspricht. Der (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  89
    Spinozism and Kant’s Transcendental Ideal.Christopher Ward - 2002 - Idealistic Studies 32 (3):221-236.
    Kant’s Transcendental Ideal (TI) is presented in a notoriously obscure section of the Critique of Pure Reason. Many readers know that Kant’s principal purpose in the TI is to show how reason fallaciously derives its concept of God from its idea of the world. But this argument is clothed in a language that is unfamiliar even to skilled commentators on Kant’s work. In this essay, I present the historical context of the proof, conduct a detailed exegesis of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. On the Transcendental Ideality of Space and Time in Modern Physics.Shahen Hacyan - 2006 - Kant Studien 97 (3):382-395.
    In Newtonian physics, all phenomena take place in absolute space, which is a fixed scenario, and are referred to absolute time, which rules all processes. Motion is governed by a set of basic differential equations, and it is possible, at least in principle, to deduce future events from present initial conditions.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  28
    Dworkin's Transcendental Ideal.Thomas D. Perry - 1982 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 7 (1):255-269.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Kant's transcendental ideal las fiction.Peter Klepec - 1994 - Filozofski Vestnik 15 (2):97-110.
  11.  33
    Infinity, Ideality, Transcendentality: The Idea in the Kantian Sense in Husserl and Derrida.Till Grohmann - 2024 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 55 (3):221-236.
    When Derrida translated and commented on Husserl’s manuscript The Origin of Geometry in 1962, he gave a central place to what Husserl called the Idea “in the Kantian sense”. This article reflects on the use and function of this Idea in Derrida’s reading of Husserl. It critically interrogates the relationship between the Idea in the Kantian sense and mathematical ideality, as well as the use of this Idea in the interpretation of the Thing (Ding) and the stream of experience (Erlebnisstrom). (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Argumentación transcendental e ideales valorativos de la razón.Lorenzo Peña - 1988 - Analogía Filosófica 2 (2):31.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. ‘Must the Transcendental Conditions for the Possibility of Experience be Ideal?’.Kenneth R. Westphal - 2004 - In Cinzia Ferrini (ed.), Eredità Kantiane (1804–2004): questioni emergenti e problemi irrisolti. Bibliopolis.
    Three genuinely transcendental conditions for the possibility of self-conscious experience are and can only be material (§§2–4). Identifying these conditions shows that the link between transcendental proof and transcendental idealism is not direct, but must be justified by substantive argument (§§ 4, 5). This illuminates the prospect of separating transcendental proofs from transcendental idealism. Indeed, examining these conditions reveals a powerful strategy for using transcendental proof to defend realism sans phrase. Strikingly, this prospect illuminates (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14.  8
    O Ideal transcendental da razão em Kant e a génese das explicações míticas.António Machuco Rosa - 2003 - Phainomenon 5-6 (1):389-400.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15.  27
    Marguerite porete, um corpo que se fez espelho de deus - estudo sobre O problema da inacessibilidade do transcendente E do ideal de inalterabilidade na obra mística de Marguerite porete: Le miroir Des 'mes simples E anéanties.Ceci Baptista Mariani - 2003 - Veritas – Revista de Filosofia da Pucrs 48 (3):427-440.
    Este estudo aprofunda o sentido da experiência relatada por Marguerite Porete, mistica medieval, condenada como herética e queimada em 1310, acusada de ultrapassar e transcender as Escrituras, errar nos artigos da fé e dossacramentos e dizer palavras contrárias e prejudiciais. No entanto, ela traz uma contribuição importante para o pensamento filosófico-teológico e literário, na medida em que levanta questões e articula respostas sobre o problema da inacessibilidade do transcendente. O aniquilamento é o seu tema, perigoso para um tempo em que (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. A priori intuition and transcendental necessity in Kant's idealism.Markus Kohl - 2020 - European Journal of Philosophy 29 (4):827-845.
    I examine how Kant argues for the transcendental ideality of space. I defend a reading on which Kant accepts the ideality of space because it explains our (actual) knowledge that mathematical judgments are necessarily true. I argue that this reading is preferable over the alternative suggestion that Kant can infer the ideality of space directly from the fact that we have an a priori intuition of space. Moreover, I argue that the reading I propose does not commit Kant to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17.  77
    The Way from the Ideal of Science: The Other Motivation for the Transcendental Phenomenological Reduction in the Doctoral Dissertation of Dorion Cairns.Lester Embree - 2012 - Human Studies 35 (4):555-561.
    Cairns presents a plausible two-part, step by step, approach seemingly developed in Husserl’s “workshop” to transcendental phenomenology that is independent of culture and history, refines a concept of knowledge and its references to worldly things, encounters a difficulty, and resolves it through recognition of a non-worldly apodictic core of consciousness distinct from being in the real temporal, spatial, and causal world.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18. Truth, Scholastic Transcendentals, and the Implications of Ideal-Realism.Marco Stango - 2022 - Filosofia 67:201-224.
    The paper explores the possibility of philosophical cooperation between Thomism and American pragmatism by resurrecting a largely forgotten debate between Wilmon Henry Sheldon and Jacques Maritain. The discussion focuses primarily on the problem of truth as it is discussed by Peirce and by some contemporary Thomists, including Maritain but also Milbank, Pickstock, Lonergan, Balthasar, Pieper, and Ulrich. The paper claims that, if we bring Peirce’s version of pragmatism into the picture, cooperation is not possible but likely to be fruitful for (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19. Transcendental Idealism and Material Reality: Metaphysics of Scientific Objectivity in Husserl, Deleuze, and Kant.Bilge Akbalik - 2018 - Dissertation, University of Memphis
    This dissertation engages critically with the metaphysical implications of the respective transcendentalisms of Husserl, Deleuze, and Kant in an attempt to disclose their largely untapped resources for a renewed consideration of the ability of science to grasp reality as it is in-itself. Chapter 1 examines the metaphysical implications of Husserl’s critique of natural scientific objectivity in his later transcendental philosophy in connection to his early formulations of phenomenological objectivity around the axis of the distinction between metaphysics as the science (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. The "A Priori" Moment of the Subject-Object Dialectic in Transcendental Phenomenology: The Relationship between "A Priori" and "Ideality".Hans KÖchler - 1974 - Analecta Husserliana 3:183.
  21. The Ideality of Space and Time: Trendelenburg versus Kant, Fischer and Bird.Edward Kanterian - 2013 - Kantian Review 18 (2):263-288.
    Trendelenburg argued that Kant's arguments in support of transcendental idealism ignored the possibility that space and time are both ideal and real. Recently, Graham Bird has claimed that Trendelenburg (unlike his contemporary Kuno Fischer) misrepresented Kant, confusing two senses of . I defend Trendelenburg's : the ideas of space and time, as a priori and necessary, are ideal, but this does not exclude their validity in the noumenal realm. This undermines transcendental idealism. Bird's attempt to show (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  22. Kant’s Neglected Alternative and the Unavoidable Need for the Transcendental Deduction.Justin B. Shaddock - 2019 - Kantian Review 24 (1):127-152.
    The problem of Kant’s Neglected Alternative is that while his Aesthetic provides an argument that space and time are empirically real – in applying to all appearances – its argument seems to fall short of the conclusion that space and time are transcendentally ideal, in not applying to any things in themselves. By considering an overlooked passage in which Kant explains why his Transcendental Deduction is ‘unavoidably necessary’, I argue that it is not solely in his Aesthetic but (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23. Will to Power: Nietzsche's Transcendental Idealism.Tom Bailey - 2021 - Journal of Nietzsche Studies 52 (2):260-289.
    This article argues that in Beyond Good and Evil (BGE) Nietzsche defends “will to power” as a transcendentally ideal condition of objectivity, in the sense in which Kant considers, say, space, time, or the concepts of substance and causation to be such conditions. The article shows how Nietzsche’s engage-ment with the transcendental idealist arguments of his Kantian contemporaries leads him to reject naturalism and to adopt a peculiarly transcendental kind of skepticism, which rejects as unjustified the conditions (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  61
    Husserl’s existentialism: ideality, traditions, and the historical apriori.Steven Crowell - 2016 - Continental Philosophy Review 49 (1):67-83.
    Husserl’s concept of an “historical apriori” is marked by a tension: It simultaneously departs from, and develops his long-standing commitment to philosophy as transcendental phenomenology. This paper looks at some reasons for this tension in the context of Husserl’s attempt to determine philosophy as a “tradition” in The Origin of Geometry. Husserl is convinced that philosophy is a scientific tradition, and the historical apriori serves in the analysis of the conditions that define a distinctively scientific “handing down.” The key (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25.  30
    Transcendental Subjectivity and Reductionism.James R. Kuehl - 1986 - Idealistic Studies 16 (2):97-111.
    My goal in this paper is nothing less than to make philosophical sense of the term “transcendental” as it is used in twentieth-century philosophy. I want to do this by constructing a notion of philosophical reductionism which not only defines the term “transcendental” but also renders explicit the idealistic theses implicit in transcendental philosophies. While I intend an ideal construction of the notions “transcendental” and “idealism,” I think that the notions I develop apply to the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  47
    The Highest Good as the Ideal of Reason in the Canon of the first Critique .Luigi Filieri - 2024 - Kant Studien 115 (1):24-45.
    In the Dialectic of the first Critique, Kant claims that a highest being is the transcendental ideal of speculative reason. However, the Canon of the Doctrine of Method presents the highest good as an ideal of both the speculative and the practical use of reason. In this paper, I argue (1) that the highest good is the ideal of the unity of reason – unlike the ideal in the Dialectic – insofar as (2) the highest (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Allais on Transcendental Idealism.Andrew F. Roche - 2011 - Kantian Review 16 (3):351-374.
    Lucy Allais argues that we can better understand Kant's transcendental idealism by taking seriously the analogy of appearances to secondary qualities that Kant offers in theProlegomena. A proper appreciation of this analogy, Allais claims, yields a reading of transcendental idealism according to which all properties that can appear to us in experience are mind-dependent relational properties that inhere in mind-independent objects. In section 1 of my paper, I articulate Allais's position and its benefits, not least of which is (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  28. Die partielle Bestimmung des transzendentalen Ideals. Eine Untersuchung über Kants Gottesbegriff.Leon-Philip Schäfer - 2014 - Incipiens 2 (1):29-55.
    In der transzendentalen Dialektik führt Kant die transzendentalen Ideen ein, deren systematischer Zusammenhang ambivalenter ist, als er zunächst erscheint. Das transzendentale Ideal, Kants Gottesbegriff, resultiert als eine der Ideen aus der Forderung der Vernunft, zu einem gegebenen Bedingten die vollständige Reihe der Bedingungen vorauszusetzen. Der ‚Grundsatz der durchgängigen Bestimmung‘ bildet Kant zufolge eine Variante dieses Prinzips. Außerdem beruht das Ideal, das hinsichtlich aller möglichen kontradiktorischen Prädikatenpaare bestimmt ist, auf seiner Grundlage. Entgegen Kants Darstellung wird gezeigt, dass dieser Begriff (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  20
    Ideal Justice and Rational Dissent. A Critique of Amartya Sen’s The Idea of Justice.Wilfried Hinsch - 2011 - Analyse & Kritik 33 (2):371-386.
    In The Idea of Justice Amartya Sen criticises ‘transcendental institutionalism’ for entertaining notions of ‘ideal justice’ that, are neither necessary nor sufficient for the advancement of justice in the real world. Sen argues in favor of a ‘realization- focused’ and ‘comparative’ understanding of justice that he associates with the names of Adam Smith, Marx, and J. S. Mill. Conceptions of ideal justice. Sen believes, are useless since in practice we do not need them to advance justice. And (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  92
    Feminist phenomenology, pregnancy, and transcendental subjectivity.Stella Sandford - 2016 - In . pp. 51–69.
    In 1930 Husserl wrote that phenomenology is ‘a transcendental idealism that is nothing more than a consequentially executed self-explication in the form of an egological science, an explication of my ego as subject of every possible cognition, and indeed with respect to every sense of what exists, wherewith the latter might be able to have a sense for me, the ego.’ In transcendental-phenomenological theory, according to Husserl, ‘every sort of existent itself, real or ideal, becomes understandable as (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31. Transcendental Phenomenology as Human Possibility: Husserl and Fink on the Phenomenologizing Subject.Denis Džanić - 2023 - Springer Nature Switzerland.
    This book focuses on Edmund Husserl’s philosophical collaboration with Eugen Fink which took place in the early 1930s, and shows how their disagreement over the nature, origin, and aim of phenomenology led to a crucial divergence on the issue of who was engaging in phenomenology, and with what motivation. It provides a philosophical investigation of a key moment in the development of Husserl’s late phenomenology. The author claims that Husserl’s meta-phenomenological exploration of the theoretical and, importantly, practical underpinnings of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Husserl’s transcendental philosophy and the critique of naturalism.Dermot Moran - 2008 - Continental Philosophy Review 41 (4):401-425.
    Throughout his career, Husserl identifies naturalism as the greatest threat to both the sciences and philosophy. In this paper, I explicate Husserl’s overall diagnosis and critique of naturalism and then examine the specific transcendental aspect of his critique. Husserl agreed with the Neo-Kantians in rejecting naturalism. He has three major critiques of naturalism: First, it (like psychologism and for the same reasons) is ‘countersensical’ in that it denies the very ideal laws that it needs for its own justification. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  33. Varieties of Transcendental Idealism: Kant and Heidegger Thinking Beyond Life.G. Anthony Bruno - 2015 - Idealistic Studies 45 (1):81-102.
    In recent work, William Blattner claims that Heidegger is an empirical realist, but not a transcendental idealist. Blattner argues that, unlike Kant, Heidegger holds that thinking beyond human life warrants no judgment about nature's existence. This poses two problems. One is interpretive: Blattner misreads Kant's conception of the beyond-life as yielding the judgment that nature does not exist, for Kant shares Heidegger's view that such a judgment must lack sense. Another is programmatic: Blattner overstates the gap between Kant's and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  65
    In Search of Collective Experience and Meaning: A Transcendental Phenomenological Methodology for Organizational Research.Gabriel Henriques - 2014 - Human Studies 37 (4):451-468.
    The Husserlian phenomenological approach to organisational research as a way to understand how collectives experience and mean their work context, is rarely used although, when it is, it often functions as a negative criticism of objectivist methods. The sociological potential of phenomenological concepts to enable understanding of subjective experience of social contexts, and the characterisation of those social contexts through ideal type construction, deserves to be used more extensively in a positive proposal of organisational research methodologies. However, a consistent (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  70
    Eidetic results in transcendental phenomenology: Against naturalization.Richard Tieszen - 2016 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 15 (4):489-515.
    In this paper I contrast Husserlian transcendental eidetic phenomenology with some other views of what phenomenology is supposed to be and argue that, as eidetic, it does not admit of being ‘naturalized’ in accordance with standard accounts of naturalization. The paper indicates what some of the eidetic results in phenomenology are and it links these to the employment of reason in philosophical investigation, as distinct from introspection, emotion or empirical observation. Eidetic phenomenology, unlike cognitive science, should issue in a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  22
    Culture and freedom in transcendental and speculative idealism.Christian Krijnen - 2022 - Filozofija I Društvo 33 (2):407-419.
    The founding fathers of modern philosophy of culture, the neo-Kantians, and especially the Southwest school, brought the concept of culture into play as a counter concept to that of nature. Taking Heinrich Rickert?s conception of culture as a starting point, the article shows how culture is conceived of as a self-formation of the subject. It leads to transcendental idealism of freedom, typical of a Kantian type of transcendental philosophy. However, in this self and world formation of the subject (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  20
    Fichte’s Transcendental Philosophy: The Original Duplicity of Intelligence and Will.Günter Zöller - 1998 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This is the first book in English on the major works of the German philosopher Johann Gottlieb Fichte. It examines the transcendental theory of self and world from the writings of Fichte's most influential period, and considers in detail recently discovered lectures on the Foundations of Transcendental Philosophy. At the center of that body of work stands Fichte's attempt to integrate the theories of volition and cognition into a unified but complex 'system of freedom'. The focus of this (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  38.  97
    Hegel’s Treatment of Transcendental Apperception in Kant.Sally S. Sedgwick - 1992 - The Owl of Minerva 23 (2):151-163.
    From the various discussions of Kant’s theoretical philosophy throughout Hegel’s works, it is not difficult to come away with the impression that Hegel thinks that the Kantian categories are derived from experience, and that the method of a “transcendental” investigation of the forms of subjectivity is nothing other than that of generalization upon observation. As early as the 1802-03 essay, Faith and Knowledge, for example, he characterizes the critical philosophy as the “completion and idealization” of Lockean “empirical psychology.” In (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  45
    Natural Versus Transcendental Philosophy.Pierre Kerszberg - 1995 - Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 18 (2):17-61.
    Kant argues at the beginning of his critical work that transcendental philosophy completely banishes anything that is merely of the order of an hypothesis. Does this rejection reveal his assurance that he, like Newton, makes no hypotheses? Newton’s famous “Hypothesis non fingo” was meant to stem the multiplication of redundant hypotheses in mathematical physics. Thus, according to Newton, a Cartesian vortex dragging material particles into itself does not really explain the motion of the particles. The problem of the origin (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  73
    On the Limitation of Transcendental Reflection, or, Is Intersubjectivity Transcendental?John Sallis - 1971 - The Monist 55 (2):312-333.
    Philosophical reflection proposes a return to self as the condition required of a genuinely radical transcendental philosophy. This proposal has its proper ground. It is not an ideal externally imposed upon reflection but rather springs from the very structure of reflection itself in its relation to the reflected. It has its source, specifically, in the capacity on the part of reflection to gain mastery over any proposed external condition in the sense that the very posing of such a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  11
    The transcendental and the mundane: Chinese cultural values in everyday life.Zhuoyun Xu - 2021 - Hong Kong: Chinese university of Hong Kong press. Edited by David Ownby.
    Through investigation of Chinese cultural ideals and life practices, Prof. Cho-yun Hsu constructs an original portrait of Chinese spiritual life. Apart from focusing on the exalted subtleties of the scholarly elite, Prof. Hsu pays more attention to the everyday people's cultural idea. By examining their daily practices (including eating, living, medical practices, poems, songs, art, and literature) and "collective memory" such as legends, he seeks to clarify Chinese ideas concerning the universe, human life and nature, from traditional times down to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  33
    Transcendental Phenomenology. [REVIEW]Richard E. Aquila - 1991 - Review of Metaphysics 44 (4):856-857.
    This book, assembled in large part from previous papers and talks, consists of three chapters. The first offers distinctions between types of description and between descriptive and speculative procedures in philosophy, and then a view as to the character of "philosophical facts." Then it turns to the charge that description is really interpretation. On account of the method of composition, the challenge is met in a somewhat disjointed manner. With emphasis on the question of historical and moral relativism, Mohanty returns (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Comparative Assessments of Justice, Political Feasibility, and Ideal Theory.Pablo Gilabert - 2012 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 15 (1):39-56.
    What should our theorizing about social justice aim at? Many political philosophers think that a crucial goal is to identify a perfectly just society. Amartya Sen disagrees. In The Idea of Justice, he argues that the proper goal of an inquiry about justice is to undertake comparative assessments of feasible social scenarios in order to identify reforms that involve justice-enhancement, or injustice-reduction, even if the results fall short of perfect justice. Sen calls this the “comparative approach” to the theory of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  44.  41
    Ideals of justice: goals vs. constraints.Anthony Simon Laden - 2013 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 16 (2):205-219.
    Amartya Sen describes John Rawls?s ?justice as fairness? as ?transcendental institutionalism? and develops his realization-focused approach in contrast. But Rawls is no transcendental institutionalist, and Sen?s construal of their opposition occludes a third, relation-based position and a valuable and practical form of ideal theory. What Sen calls transcendental institutionalism and realization-focused comparative theory each treat justice as something to bring about, a problem for experts. A third position treats justice in terms of how we relate to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  91
    Kant On The Ideality Of Space.Kenneth Rogerson - 1988 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 18 (2):271-286.
    The purpose of my paper is to interpret kant 's transcendental idealism by looking at his claim that space is "nothing but" ideal. My position is that if we grant to kant the thesis that space is an "a priori" condition for knowing objects, Then it follows that our notion of space can only refer to the character of our experience, Not to properties of things as they may be "in themselves." and this, I argue, Yields a sense (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  20
    Does Philosophy Require De-Transcendentalization? Habermas, Apel, and the Role of Transcendentals in Philosophical Discourse and Social-Scientific Explanation.Anna Michalska - 2019 - Acta Universitatis Lodziensis. Folia Philosophica. Ethica-Aesthetica-Practica 34:11--30.
    The heritage of transcendental philosophy, and more specifically its viability when it comes to the problematic of the philosophy of social sciences, has been a key point of dissensus between Jürgen Habermas and Karl-Otto Apel. Whereas Apel has explicitly aimed at a transcendental-pragmatic transformation of philosophy, Habermas has consequently insisted that his formal pragmatics, and the theory of communicative action which is erected upon it, radically de-transcendentalizes the subject. In a word, the disagreement concerns whether transcendental entities (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  83
    The omnitemporality of idealities.James Sares - 2024 - Continental Philosophy Review 57 (1):113–134.
    This article develops an interpretation and defense of Husserl’s account of the omnitemporality of idealities. I first examine why Husserl rejects the atemporality and temporal individuation of idealities on phenomenological grounds, specifically that these attributions prove countersensical in how they relate idealities to consciousness. As an alternative to these conceptions, I develop a two-sided interpretation of omnitemporality expressed in modal terms of actuality and possibility, the actual referring to appearances in time and the possible, to reactivation at any time. In (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. “The Key to Transcendental Philosophy”: Space, Time and the Body in Kant.Matthew S. Rukgaber - 2009 - Kant Studien 100 (2):166-186.
    The thesis of this essay is that Kant's theory of the “forms of intuition” can be regarded as an account of the structure of our embodied perspective. The ideality and subjectivity of space is concluded to be an account of the perspective relative nature of the figure-ground relationship or how it is that objects emerge for us in empirical experience as being orientated in a spatio-temporal field. Time is regarded similarly as the event-series relationship. The significant role of embodiment in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  49.  95
    Ideal Embodiment. Kant's Theory of Sensibility.Angelica Nuzzo - 2008 - Indiana University Press.
    Angelica Nuzzo offers a comprehensive reconstruction of Kant's theory of sensibility in his three Critiques. By introducing the notion of "transcendental embodiment," Nuzzo proposes a new understanding of Kant's views on science, nature, morality, and art. She shows that the issue of human embodiment is coherently addressed and key to comprehending vexing issues in Kant's work as a whole. In this penetrating book, Nuzzo enters new terrain and takes on questions Kant struggled with: How does a body that feels (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  50. The ideality of idealism : Fichte's battle against dogmatic Kantianism.Kien-how Goh - 2014 - In Tom Rockmore & Daniel Breazeale (eds.), Fichte and Transcendental Philosophy. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 971