Results for 'self-defense'

970 found
Order:
See also
  1.  45
    Self-defence and National Defence [1].Frank de Roose - 1990 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 7 (2):159-168.
    ABSTRACT The paper begins with the suggestion that the aura of respectability that surrounds the notion of self‐defence may render that notion suitable as a rallying point for agreement on the ethical legitimacy of warfare. I first argue that self‐defensive killing by a person X is morally justified if three conditions obtain: (1) X is together with at least one other person in a situation in which one of the persons will be killed through actions of the other (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2. 'Self-defence' and sovereignty: the reception and application of German political thought in England and Scotland, 1628-69.R. Friedeburg - 2002 - History of Political Thought 23 (2):238-265.
    Historians of political thought have begun to discover how contemporaries attempted to argue about armed conflict within the body politic without giving licence to anyone to escape order and subjection. During the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, the concept of 'self-defence' became of overriding importance. English and Scottish interest in German affairs grew after the battle at the White Mountain in 1620. English and Scottish pamphleteers and writers subsequently began to recognize some of the argument concerning 'self-defence' that had (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  93
    Self-Defence, Just War, and a Reasonable Prospect of Success.Suzanne Uniacke - 2014 - In Helen Frowe & Gerald R. Lang, How We Fight: Ethics in War. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 62-74.
    The Just War principle of jus ad bellum explicitly requires a reasonable prospect of success; the prevailing view about personal self-defence is that it can be justified even if the prospect of success is low. This chapter defends the existence of this distinction and goes on to explore the normative basis of this difference between defensive war and self-defence and its implications. In particular, the chapter highlights the rationale of the ‘success condition’ within Just War thinking and argues (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  4. Self-Defence and the Principle of Non-Combatant Immunity.Helen Frowe - 2011 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 8 (4):530-546.
    The reductivist view of war holds that the moral rules of killing in war can be reduced to the moral rules that govern killing between individuals. Noam Zohar objects to reductivism on the grounds that the account of individual self-defence that best supports the rules of war will inadvertently sanction terrorist killings of non-combatants. I argue that even an extended account of self-defence—that is, an account that permits killing at least some innocent people to save one's own life—can (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  5.  83
    ‘Death to Tyrants’: Self-Defence, Human Rights and Tyrannicide-Part II.Shannon K. Brincat - 2009 - Journal of International Political Theory 5 (1):75-93.
    This is the final part of a series of two papers that have examined the conceptual development of the philosophical justifications for tyrannicide. While Part I focused on the classical, medieval, and liberal justifications for tyrannicide, Part II aims to provide the tentative outlines of a contemporary model of tyrannicide in world politics. It is contended that a reinvigorated conception of self-defence, when coupled with the modern understanding of universal human rights, may provide the foundation for the normative validity (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  45
    Self‐defence and Forcing the Choice between Lives.Seumas Miller - 2008 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 9 (2):239-243.
    ABSTRACT In the standard case of justifiable killing in self‐defence one agent without provocation tries to kill a second agent and the second agent's only way to avoid death is to kill his attacker. It is widely accepted that such killings in self‐defence are morally justifiable, but it has proved difficult to show why this is so. Recently, Montague has put forward an account in terms of forcing a choice between lives, and Teichman has propounded a quasi‐Hobbesian rights‐based (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7.  41
    (1 other version)Self-Defence Against Multiple Threats.Kerah Gordon-Solmon - 2015 - New Content is Available for Journal of Moral Philosophy 14 (2):125-133.
    _ Source: _Page Count 9 If a threat is liable to be defensively killed, there is a defeasible justification for killing her. On certain prevailing assumptions about liability, which I accept, there are liability justifications for killing _any number_ of minimally responsible threats, each of whom would otherwise kill a single non-responsible victim. Absent harms to third parties, these justifications appear, counter-intuitively, to be undefeated. I argue that this counter-intuitive appearance is deceptive.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8. Self-Defence and Innocence: Aggressors and Active Threats: Phillip Montague.Phillip Montague - 2000 - Utilitas 12 (1):62-78.
    Although people generally agree that innocent targets of culpable aggression are justified in harming the aggressors in self-defence, there is considerable disagreement regarding whether innocents are justified in defending themselves when their doing so would harm other innocent people. I argue in this essay that harming innocent aggressors and active innocent threats in self-defence is indeed justified under certain conditions, but that defensive actions in such cases are justified as permissions rather than as claim rights. This justification therefore (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  9.  42
    Permissible Killing: The Self-Defence Justification of Homicide.Suzanne Uniacke - 1994 - Cambridge University Press.
    Do individuals have a positive right of self-defence? And if so, what are the limits of this right? Under what conditions does this use of force extend to the defence of others? These are some of the issues explored by Dr Uniacke in this comprehensive 1994 philosophical discussion of the principles relevant to self-defence as a moral and legal justification of homicide. She establishes a unitary right of self-defence and the defence of others, one which grounds the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  10. A practical account of self-defence.Helen Frowe - 2010 - Law and Philosophy 29 (3):245-272.
    I argue that any successful account of permissible self- defence must be action-guiding, or practical . It must be able to inform people’s deliberation about what they are permitted to do when faced with an apparent threat to their lives. I argue that this forces us to accept that a person can be permitted to use self-defence against Apparent Threats: characters whom a person reasonably, but mistakenly, believes threaten her life. I defend a hybrid account of self-defence (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  11.  23
    Defending Self-Defence.Fiona Leverick - 2007 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 27 (3):563-579.
  12. Public Shaming as Moral Self-Defence.James Edgar Lim - forthcoming - Social Theory and Practice.
    What, if anything, can justify public shaming? Philosophers who have written on this topic have pointed out the role of public shaming in enforcing valuable social norms. In this paper, I defend an alternate, supplementary justification for public shaming: as a form of moral self-defence. Moral self-defence is the defence of one’s moral standing – being recognized as an equal in the eyes of oneself and others – rather than the defence of one’s physical body or rights. Agents (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  86
    Child soldiers and killing in self-defence: Challenging the 'moral view' on killing in war.Milla Emilia Vaha - 2011 - Journal of Military Ethics 10 (1):36-51.
    (2011). CHILD SOLDIERS AND KILLING IN SELF-DEFENCE: CHALLENGING THE ‘MORAL VIEW’ ON KILLING IN WAR. Journal of Military Ethics: Vol. 10, No. 1, pp. 36-51. doi: 10.1080/15027570.2011.561639.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14. Self-Defence among Innocent People.Gerhard Øverland - 2005 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 2 (2):127-146.
    I explain the asymmetry between innocent aggressors and their victims, and attempt to separate justified and unjustified defensive force when both parties are innocent. I propose the principle of initiating behaviour, which states that: ‘In order for one person to be justified in using defensive force the other party must initiate the apparently threatening behaviour, but the defendant’s interpretation of that behaviour, as being threatening, would have to be reasonable.’ We can thereby maintain the view that there is a significant (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15. Contagious disease and self-defence.T. M. Wilkinson - 2007 - Res Publica 13 (4):339-359.
    This paper gives a self-defence account of the scope and limits of the justified use of compulsion to control contagious disease. It applies an individualistic model of self-defence for state action and uses it to illuminate the constraints on public health compulsion of proportionality and using the least restrictive alternative. It next shows how a self-defence account should not be rejected on the basis of past abuses. The paper then considers two possible limits to a self-defence (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  16.  38
    Defending Self-Defence.Garrett Barden - 1984 - Irish Philosophical Journal 1 (2):25-35.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. National Defence, Self Defence, and the Problem of Political Aggression.Seth Lazar - 2014 - In Cécile Fabre & Seth Lazar, The Morality of Defensive War. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press. pp. 10-38.
    Wars are large-scale conflicts between organized groups of belligerents, which involve suffering, devastation, and brutality unlike almost anything else in human experience. Whatever one’s other beliefs about morality, all should agree that the horrors of war are all but unconscionable, and that warfare can be justified only if we have some compel- ling account of what is worth fighting for, which can justify contributing, as individu- als and as groups, to this calamitous endeavour. Although this question should obviously be central (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  18. Killing the Innocent in Self-Defence.Helen Frowe - unknown
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Self-Defence and Just War.Suzanne Uniacke - 2002 - In Janssen Dieter & Quante Michael, Gerechte Kriege. Mentis-Verlag. pp. 64-78.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  68
    “The complete guide to self defence”.Douglas N. Husak - 1996 - Law and Philosophy 15 (4):399 - 406.
  21.  35
    Forced Choices and Self‐Defence.Phillip Montague - 2008 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 12 (1):89-93.
    ABSTRACT This paper is a reply to three objections raised by Seumas Miller against a ‘forced‐choice’account of the morality of self‐defence. It is argued that Miller's first objection rests on a misconception of how the forced‐choice account is supposed to work; that his second objection is simply mistaken; and that his third objection overlooks how the forced‐choice account explicitly accommodates the moral difference between self‐defence and ‘other‐defence.’Finally, it is suggested that Miller's entire approach is defective in its failure (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  62
    Thomas Aquinas and Antonio de Córdoba on self-defence: saving yourself as a private end.Daniel Schwartz - 2018 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 26 (6):1045-1063.
    ABSTRACTRevisionists about Aquinas’ teaching on private self-defence take the standard reading to hold that Aquinas applies a version of the Doctrine of Double Effect according to which the intentional killing of a wrongful attacker by a private person is morally prohibited while the non-intentional but foreseeable killing of the attacker is permitted. Revisionists dispute this reading and argue that Aquinas permits the intentional killing of wrongful attackers. I argue that revisionists mischaracterize the standard reading of Aquinas. I consider one (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. State Legitimacy and Self-defence.Massimo Renzo - 2011 - Law and Philosophy 30 (5):575-601.
    In this paper I outline a theory of legitimacy that grounds the state’s right to rule on a natural duty not to harm others. I argue that by refusing to enter the state, anarchists expose those living next to them to the dangers of the state of nature, thereby posing an unjust threat. Since we have a duty not to pose unjust threats to others, anarchists have a duty to leave the state of nature and enter the state. This duty (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  24.  85
    Digital Self-Defence: Why you Ought to Preserve Your Privacy for the Sake of Wrongdoers.Lauritz Aastrup Munch - 2022 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 25 (2):233-248.
    Most studies on the ethics of privacy focus on what others ought to do to accommodate our interest in privacy. I focus on a related but distinct question that has attracted less attention in the literature: When, if ever, does morality require us to safeguard our own privacy? While we often have prudential reasons for safeguarding our privacy, we are also, at least sometimes, morally required to do so. I argue that we, sometimes, ought to safeguard our privacy for the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  65
    Provocateurs and Their Rights to Self-Defence.Lisa Hecht - 2019 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 13 (1):165-185.
    A provocateur does not pose a threat of harm. Hence, a forceful response to provocation is generally considered wrongful. And yet, a provocateur is often denied recourse to a self-defence justification if she defends herself against such a violent response. In recent work, Kimberly Ferzan argues that a provocateur forfeits defensive rights but this forfeiture cannot be explained in the same way as an aggressor’s rights forfeiture. Ordinarily, one forfeits the right not to be harmed and to self-defend (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  26.  59
    Self‐defence Against the Innocent.Michael Clark - 2000 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 17 (2):145–155.
    Do we have the right to defend ourselves against innocent aggressors? If I amattacked in a lift by a knife‐wielding lunatic, may I kill or maim him to protect my own life? On one view the insane man’s plight is his bad luck and I am under no obligation to let it be transferred to me. On the opposing view it is my bad luck to be under attack and I have no right to transfer it to an innocent man (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  27.  40
    Self‐Defence and the Right to Resist.Christopher J. Finlay - 2008 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 16 (1):85 – 100.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  10
    Self-defence and War.David Rodin - 1998
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Implicit Bias, Self-Defence, and the Reasonable Person.Jules Holroyd & Federico Picinali - 2022 - In Matt Matravers & Claes Lernestedt, The Criminal Law's Person. Hart Publishing.
    The reasonable person standard is used in adjudicating claims of self-defence. In US law, an individual may use defensive force if her beliefs that a threat is imminent and that force is required are beliefs that a reasonable person would have. In English law, it is sufficient that beliefs in imminence and necessity are genuinely held; but the reasonableness of so believing is given an evidential role in establishing the genuineness of the beliefs. There is, of course, much contention (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Assassination and targeted killing: Law enforcement, execution or self-defence?Michael L. Gross - 2006 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 23 (3):323–335.
    abstract During the current round of fighting in the Middle East, Israel has provoked considerable controversy as it turned to targeted killings or assassination to battle militants. While assassination has met with disfavour among traditional observers, commentators have, more recently, sought to justify targeted killings with an appeal to both self‐defence and law enforcement. While each paradigm allows the use of lethal force, they are fundamentally incompatible, the former stipulating moral innocence and the latter demanding the presumption of criminal (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  31.  59
    Deterrence and Self-Defence.Nadine Elzein - 2021 - The Monist 104 (4):526-539.
    Measures aimed at general deterrence are often thought to be problematic on the basis that they violate the Kantian prohibition against sacrificing the interests of some as a means of securing a greater good. But even if this looks like a weak objection because deterrence can be justified as a form of societal self-defence, such measures may be regarded as problematic for another reason: Harming in self-defence is only justified when it’s necessary, i.e., when there are no relatively (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  33
    Luxorius on the Art of Self-Defence.R. Renehan - 1981 - Classical Quarterly 31 (02):472-.
    ‘pedibus makes no better sense than metre.’ Shackleton Bailey, who suspects an allusion to the exclusus amator theme and accordingly suggests unctis…postibus . But iunctis pedibus is idiomatic Latin for an all-out fight and has an authentic look to it; Ovid, Met. 9. 42–4 illustrates the usage: rursusque ad bella coimus inque gradu stetimus certi non cedere, eratque cum pede pes iunctus. See further Verg. A. 10. 361 haeret pede pes densusque viro vir; Liv. 38. 21. 13 pede collato pugnandum (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  36
    A moral justification for killing in self-defence.K. Dowling - 1998 - South African Journal of Philosophy 17 (3):262-274.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  92
    Domestic Violence and the Gendered Law of Self-Defence in France: The Case of Jacqueline Sauvage.Kate Fitz-Gibbon & Marion Vannier - 2017 - Feminist Legal Studies 25 (3):313-335.
    Legal responses to battered women who kill have long animated scholarly debate and law reform activity. In September 2012 after 47 years of alleged abuse, Frenchwoman Jacqueline Sauvage fatally shot her abusive husband three times in the back. The subsequent contested trial, conviction for murder, unsuccessful appeal and later presidential pardon of Sauvage thrust the French law of self-defence into the spotlight. The Sauvage case raises important questions surrounding the adequacy of the French criminal law in this area, the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35. (1 other version)Geoengineering as self-defence.Stephen M. Gardiner & Alicia R. Intriago - 2013 - The Philosophers' Magazine 60:17-18.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Border Coercion and Democratic Legitimacy: Freedom of Association, Territorial Dominion, and Self-Defence.Arash Abizadeh - manuscript
  37. Suzanne Uniacke, Permissible Killing: The Self-Defence Justification of Homicide Reviewed by.Wayne N. Renke - 1996 - Philosophy in Review 16 (1):69-71.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  32
    What factors influenced Japan's decision to dispatch its Self-Defence Forces (SDF) to Iraq in 2004?Jack Edward Holden - 2011 - Polis (Misc) 6:2012.
  39. John Stuart Mill on the Suez Canal and the Limits of Self-Defence.Tim Beaumont - 2024 - International Theory.
    Michael Walzer’s use of John Stuart Mill’s A Few Words on Non-Intervention (1859) helped to inaugurate it as a canonical text of international theory. However, Walzer’s use of the text was highly selective because he viewed the first half as a historically parochial discussion of British foreign policy, and his interest in the second was restricted to the passages in which Mill proposes principles of international morality to govern foreign military interventions to protect third parties. As a result, theorists tend (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. A glimpse of the self: Defence of subjectivity in Beckett and his later theatre.Matthijs Engelberts - 2000 - In Willem van Reijen & Willem G. Weststeijn, Subjectivity. Atlanta, GA: Rodopi.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  50
    A Case for Feminist Self-Defence.Thomas Nadelhoffer - 2018 - The Philosophers' Magazine 81:26-32.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Book Review:Permissible Killing: The Self-Defence Justification of Homicide. Suzanne Uniacke. [REVIEW]Jeff McMahan - 1996 - Ethics 106 (3):641-.
    Do individuals have a positive right of self-defence? And if so, what are the limits of this right? Under what conditions does this use of force extend to the defence of others? These are some of the issues explored by Dr Uniacke in this comprehensive 1994 philosophical discussion of the principles relevant to self-defence as a moral and legal justification of homicide. She establishes a unitary right of self-defence and the defence of others, one which grounds the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  43.  23
    Risky Business: A Model of Sufficient Risk for Anticipatory Self-Defence.Jamal Nabulsi - 2020 - Journal of Military Ethics 19 (4):292-311.
    Drawing on the historical insight of Emer de Vattel to build on the contemporary arguments of Michael Walzer and David Luban, this article develops a model of sufficient risk as a necessary condition for anticipatory war to be deemed self-defence. This model holds that an anticipatory war may constitute legitimate self-defence (as opposed to aggression) when it aims to forestall a threat that poses a sufficient risk to the anticipating state. This is the point where a threat is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Putative Self-defense And Rules Of Imputation. In Defense Of The Battered Woman.B. Byrd - 1994 - Jahrbuch für Recht Und Ethik 2.
    This article attemps to provide a good defense for battered women who kill their sleeping husbands, particularly in cases where it is judged that she was mistaken in her assumption of the need to exercise self-defense. Proceeding from the distinction between the imputation of an act to an actor and the imputation of blame to an actor for criminally prohibited conduct , the article moves on to a discussion of the relevance of mistakes as to justifying circumstances (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Self-Defense, Punishment and Forfeiture.David Alm - 2013 - Criminal Justice Ethics 32 (2):91-107.
    According to the self-defense view, the moral justification of punishment is derived from the moral justification of an earlier threat of punishment for an offense. According to the forfeiture view, criminals can justly be punished because they have forfeited certain rights in virtue of their crimes. The paper defends three theses about these two views. (1) The self-defense view is false because the right to threaten retaliation is not independent of the right to carry out that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  84
    Self-Defense and Giving Rise to Cost: On Innocent Bystanders, Threats, Obstructors, and Obstacles, and the Permissibility to Harm Them.Gerhard Øverland - 2016 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 10 (4):831-847.
    Philosophers have had trouble defending the common sense view that it is permissible to impose significant cost on an innocent person who is about to harm you to prevent the harm from occurring. In this paper, I argue that such harm can be justified if one pays attention to the moral significance of imposing a cost on others. The constraint against harming people who give rise to cost by their presence or movements is weaker than the constraint against harming bystanders. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  67
    Self-Defense, Forfeiture and Necessity.David Alm - 2019 - Philosophical Papers 48 (3):335-358.
    The thesis of this paper is that it is possible to explain why a culpable aggressor forfeits his right not to suffer the harm necessary to prevent his aggression if a killer forfeits his right to life. I argue that this strategy accounts also for the necessity restriction on self-defense. I respond to several objections, including the worry that it makes no sense to attempt a derivation of the relatively uncontroversial from the highly controversial.
    No categories
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Self-Defense, Punishing Unjust Combatants and Justice in War.Steve Viner - 2010 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 4 (3):297-319.
    Some contemporary Just War theorists, like Jeff McMahan, have recently built upon an individual right of self-defense to articulate moral rules of war that are at odds with commonly accepted views. For instance, they argue that in principle combatants who fight on the unjust side ought to be liable to punishment on that basis alone. Also, they reject the conclusion that combatants fighting on both sides are morally equal. In this paper, I argue that these theorists overextend their (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49. Simple truths, hard problems: Some thoughts on terror, justice, and self-defence.Noam Chomsky - 2005 - Philosophy 80 (1):5-28.
    Among the most elementary of moral truisms is the principle of universality: we apply to ourselves the same standards we do to others, more stringent ones if we are serious. A near-universal principle of intellectual culture is the rejection of this truism, sometimes explicitly. Rejection of this and similar moral truisms has severe human consequences, and yields what are regarded as “hard problems”—hard in no small measure because truisms are rejected. Illustrations range from establishment of “norms” for international behavior to (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  50.  43
    Against Self-Defense.Blake Hereth - 2017 - Social Theory and Practice 43 (3):613-635.
    The ethics of self-defense is dominated by the Orthodox View, which claims that at least some cases of self-defensive assault are permissible. I defend the radical view that there are no permissible instances of self-defensive assault. My argument proceeds as follows: Every permissible act of self-defensive assault could, in principle, have its permissibility be massively overdetermined. Such ‘super-permissible’ acts of assault are ones in which agents are objectively permitted to perform those acts in morally trivializing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 970