Results for 'logical conventionalism'

926 found
Order:
See also
  1. Logical Conventionalism.Jared Warren - unknown - In Filippo Ferrari, Elke Brendel, Massimiliano Carrara, Ole Hjortland, Gil Sagi, Gila Sher & Florian Steinberger (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Logic. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
    Once upon a time, logical conventionalism was the most popular philosophical theory of logic. It was heavily favored by empiricists, logical positivists, and naturalists. According to logical conventionalism, linguistic conventions explain logical truth, validity, and modality. And conventions themselves are merely syntactic rules of language use, including inference rules. Logical conventionalism promised to eliminate mystery from the philosophy of logic by showing that both the metaphysics and epistemology of logic fit into a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  27
    Paraconsistent logics, conventionalism and ontology.Anna Pietryga - 1999 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 7:119.
    Paraconsistent logics may be viewed as one of the last elementsin a series of rapid developments in science in the 19th and early 20th c.,triggered by the appearance of non-Euclidean geometries. The philosophyof conventionalism, which gave a metatheoretical framework to the basicchanges involved, may also help in evaluating the truth import of logic and in determining its relation to ontology.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Logical Conventionalism and the Adoption Problem.Anandi Hattiangadi - 2023 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 97 (1):47-81.
    In this paper, I take issue with a core commitment of logical conventionalism: that we impose a logic on ourselves by adopting general linguistic conventions governing our use of logical terms, thereby determining the meanings of the logical constants and which of our inferences are valid. Drawing on Kripke’s ‘adoption problem’, I argue that general logical principles cannot be adopted, either explicitly or implicitly. I go on to argue that the meanings of our logical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4. An Empirical Route to Logical 'Conventionalism'.Eugene Chua - 2017 - In Baltag Alexandru, Seligman Jeremy & Yamada Tomoyuki (eds.), Logic, Rationality, and Interaction. LORI 2017. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol 10455. Springer. pp. 631-636.
    The laws of classical logic are taken to be logical truths, which in turn are taken to hold objectively. However, we might question our faith in these truths: why are they true? One general approach, proposed by Putnam [8] and more recently Dickson [3] or Maddy [5], is to adopt empiricism about logic. On this view, logical truths are true because they are true of the world alone – this gives logical truths an air of objectivity. Putnam (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. A Sketchy Logical Conventionalism.Jack Woods - 2023 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 97 (1):29-46.
    Anti-realism about the foundations of logic are curiously absent from the literature. This is especially striking given natural analogies with moral anti-realis.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6. Shadows of Syntax: Revitalizing Logical and Mathematical Conventionalism.Jared Warren - 2020 - New York, USA: Oxford University Press.
    What is the source of logical and mathematical truth? This book revitalizes conventionalism as an answer to this question. Conventionalism takes logical and mathematical truth to have their source in linguistic conventions. This was an extremely popular view in the early 20th century, but it was never worked out in detail and is now almost universally rejected in mainstream philosophical circles. Shadows of Syntax is the first book-length treatment and defense of a combined conventionalist theory of (...)
  7. Conventionalism about mathematics and logic.Hartry Field - 2022 - Noûs 57 (4):815-831.
    Conventionalism about mathematics has much in common with two other views: fictionalism and the multiverse view (aka plenitudinous platonism). The three views may differ over the existence of mathematical objects, but they agree in rejecting a certain kind of objectivity claim about mathematics, advocating instead an extreme pluralism. The early parts of the paper will try to elucidate this anti‐objectivist position, and question whether conventionalism really offers a third form of it distinct from fictionalism and the multiverse view. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8. Conventionalism and it's impact on logical empiricism.Rudolph Haller - 1998 - Philosophia Scientiae 3 (2):95-108.
  9. Poincaré's conventionalism and the logical positivists.Michael Friedman - 1995 - Foundations of Science 1 (2):299-314.
    The logical positivists adopted Poincare's doctrine of the conventionality of geometry and made it a key part of their philosophical interpretation of relativity theory. I argue, however, that the positivists deeply misunderstood Poincare's doctrine. For Poincare's own conception was based on the group-theoretical picture of geometry expressed in the Helmholtz-Lie solution of the space problem, and also on a hierarchical picture of the sciences according to which geometry must be presupposed be any properly physical theory. But both of this (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  10.  29
    Carnap's conventionalism : logic, science, and tolerance.Noah Friedman-Biglin - 2014 - Dissertation, University of St Andrews
    In broadest terms, this thesis is concerned to answer the question of whether the view that arithmetic is analytic can be maintained consistently. Lest there be much suspense, I will conclude that it can. Those who disagree claim that accounts which defend the analyticity of arithmetic are either unable to give a satisfactory account of the foundations of mathematics due to the incompleteness theorems, or, if steps are taken to mitigate incompleteness, then the view loses the ability to account for (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  26
    Conventionalism in logic.Carlo Borromeo Giannoni - 1971 - The Hague,: Mouton.
    No detailed description available for "Conventionalism in logic".
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  12.  31
    Conventionalism about Logical Truth.David Johnson - 1995 - Philosophical Topics 23 (1):189-212.
  13.  30
    Conventionalist and contingency-oriented modal logics.R. Routley - 1971 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 12 (2):131-152.
  14.  25
    Shadows of Syntax: Revitalizing Logical and Mathematical Conventionalism, by Jared Warren.Fredrik Nyseth - 2021 - Mind 132 (527):880-890.
    This is a highly ambitious book, defending a long unpopular account of logic and mathematics—namely, conventionalism. Warren’s overall aim is to convince us tha.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  65
    Conventionalist Accounts of Personal Identity Over Time.David Mark Kovacs - 2024 - Philosophy Compass 19 (8):e13016.
    Conventionalism about personal identity over time is the view that personal identity is in some sense dependent on our beliefs, desires, social practices, or language use (collectively: on our “conventions”). This paper provides an opinionated survey of the state of the art about personal identity conventionalism. First, it offers a taxonomy of possible types of conventionalism along four different axes and discusses weak vs. strong, private vs. public, doxastic vs. non-doxastic, and realizer-relative vs. assessor-relative varieties of (...). Second, it reviews the main sources of motivation for conventionalism about personal identity: methodological, epistemological, and normative motivations. Third, it maps out the place of conventionalism in logical space and distinguishes it from related philosophical theses: personal identity pluralism, indeterminacy about personal identity, revisionism, and self-concern relativism. Finally, some potential avenues for future research are considered. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Inferentialism, Conventionalism, and A Posteriori Necessity.Jared Warren - 2022 - Journal of Philosophy 119 (10):517-541.
    In the mid twentieth century, logical positivists and many other philosophers endorsed a simple equation: something was necessary just in case it was analytic just in case it was a priori. Kripke’s examples of a posteriori necessary truths showed that the simple equation is false. But while positivist-style inferentialist approaches to logic and mathematics remain popular, there is no inferentialist account of necessity a posteriori. I give such an account. This sounds like an anti-Kripkean project, but it is not. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  17.  58
    Conventionalism, coordination, and mental models: from Poincaré to Simon.Rouslan Koumakhov - 2014 - Journal of Economic Methodology 21 (3):251-272.
    This article focuses on the conventions that sustain social interaction and argues that they are central to Simon's decision-making theory. Simon clearly identifies two kinds of coordination by convention: behavioral mores that shape human actions, and shared mental models that govern human perceptions. This article argues that Poincaré–Carnap's conventionalism provides powerful support for Simon's theory; it contends that this theory offers a more convincing account of decision and coordination than Lewis' concept of convention. Simon's approach to applying conventionalist logic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  97
    (1 other version)Shadows of Syntax: Revitalizing Logical and Mathematical Conventionalism.M. Rescorla - 2023 - History and Philosophy of Logic 45 (3):380-384.
    Volume 45, Issue 3, August 2024, Page 380-384.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  55
    The Methodological Roles of Tolerance and Conventionalism in the Philosophy of Mathematics: Reconsidering Carnap's Logic of Science.Emerson P. Doyle - 2014 - Dissertation, University of Western Ontario
    This dissertation makes two primary contributions. The first three chapters develop an interpretation of Carnap's Meta-Philosophical Program which places stress upon his methodological analysis of the sciences over and above the Principle of Tolerance. Most importantly, I suggest, is that Carnap sees philosophy as contiguous with science—as a part of the scientific enterprise—so utilizing the very same methods and subject to the same limitations. I argue that the methodological reforms he suggests for philosophy amount to philosophy as the explication of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Was Wittgenstein a radical conventionalist?Ásgeir Berg - 2024 - Synthese 203 (2):1-31.
    This paper defends a reading of Wittgenstein’s philosophy of mathematics in the Lectures on the Foundation of Mathematics as a radical conventionalist one, whereby our agreement about the particular case is constitutive of our mathematical practice and ‘the logical necessity of any statement is a direct expression of a convention’ (Dummett 1959, p. 329). -/- On this view, mathematical truths are conceptual truths and our practices determine directly for each mathematical proposition individually whether it is true or false. Mathematical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  21. The origins of logical empiricism. The young Moritz Schlick and the conventionalism of Henri Poincare.Massimo Ferrari - 2012 - Giornale Critico Della Filosofia Italiana 8 (2):475-491.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. (1 other version)Conventionalism and the indeterminacy of translation.Barry Stroud - 1968 - Synthese 19 (1-2):82 - 96.
    Quine's arguments for the indeterminacy of translation demonstrate the existence and help to explain the rationale of restraints upon what we can say and understand. In particular they show that there are logical truths to which there are no intelligible alternatives. Thus the standard view that the truths of logic and mathematics differ from "synthetic" statements in being true solely by virtue of linguistic convention--Which requires for its plausibility the existence of intelligible alternatives to our present logical truth--Is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  23. What is Carnap's conventionalism after all?Norma Yunez-Naude - 2003 - Synthese 137 (1-2):261 - 272.
    As is well known, Carnap's conventionalism was a rejection to Kant's view ofmathematics and was fully developed in his Logische Syntax der Sprache.The purpose of this article is to step back to Der Logische Aufbau der Weltto show that the Logical Syntax of Language is an attempt to solve difficultiesfound in the earlier construction. I first clarify the notion of conventionalism, whichplays a central role in the application of mathematics to the reconstruction of empiricalknowledge. By not strictly (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  72
    Wittgenstein, Quine and Dummett on Conventionalism about Logic.Alexander Miller - 2014 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 3 (4):292-301.
  25. Geometric conventionalism and carnap's principle of tolerance.David De Vidi & Graham Solomon - 1993 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 25 (5):773-783.
    We discuss in this paper the question of the scope of the principle of tolerance about languages promoted in Carnap's The Logical Syntax of Language and the nature of the analogy between it and the rudimentary conventionalism purportedly exhibited in the work of Poincaré and Hilbert. We take it more or less for granted that Poincaré and Hilbert do argue for conventionalism. We begin by sketching Coffa's historical account, which suggests that tolerance be interpreted as a (...) that allows us complete freedom to select whatever language we wish—an interpretation that generalizes the conventionalism promoted by Poincaré and Hilbert which allows us complete freedom to select whatever axiom system we wish for geometry. We argue that such an interpretation saddles Carnap with a theory of meaning that has unhappy consequences, a theory we believe he did not hold. We suggest that the principle of linguistic tolerance in fact has a more limited scope; but within that scope the analogy between tolerance and geometric conventionalism is quite tight. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  39
    Conventionalism, scientific discovery and the sociology of knowledge.Angelo M. Petroni - 1993 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 7 (3):225-240.
    In this paper the basic aim of the so‐called ‘strong programme’ in the sociology of knowledge is examined. The ‘strong programme’ is considered (and rightly so) as an extreme version of the anti‐realist view of science. While the problem of scientific realism has normally been dealt with from the point of view of the ‘context of justification’ of theories, the paper focuses on the issues raised by law‐discovery. In this context Herbert Simon's views about the existence of a ‘logic of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27. Carnap's conventionalism: The problem with p-rules.Thomas Oberdan - 2005 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 68 (1):119-137.
    Rudolf Carnap's 'Principle of Tolerance' was undoubtedly one of the most infl uential precepts in 20th Century philosophy. Introduced in The Logical Syntax of Language, Carnap's Principle suffered from ambiguities which aroused important philosophical questions from Moritz Schlick and Alberto Coffa. Specifi cally, their questions arise from the application of the Principle to the matter of including extra-logical transformation rules in the defi nition of a language, which Carnap regarded as an important difference between his own conventionalist philosophy (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Conventionalism.Iris Einheuser - 2003 - Dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology
    Certain fundamental philosophical disputes, in contrast to disputes in the empirical sciences, are characterized by the persistence of disagreement. This has led some to endorse conventionalism, the view that the 'facts of the matter' partly depend on our conventions and that disagreements persist because both sides to the dispute employ different conventions. What does it mean to say that the facts of the matter partly depend on conventions? My thesis is concerned with this question. It has four parts. ;Part (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29. Conventionalism in Carnap's Early Philosophy.Edmund Runggaldier - 1976
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  51
    Moderate Conventionalism and Cultural Appropriation.Juha Räikkä & Mikko Puumala - 2019 - Etikk I Praksis - Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics 1:81-88.
    Cultural appropriation, also called cultural borrowing, has been the topic of much discussion in recent years. Roughly speaking, cultural appropriation happens when someone outside of a cultural or ethnic group takes or uses some object that is characteristic or in some way important to the group without the group’s permission. Individuals who find cultural appropriation unproblematic have often argued that if we express moral criticism of the use of traditional Sami outfits by non-Sami, then we are logically committed to criticize (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  66
    Conventionalism in Early Analytic Philosophy and the Principle of Relativity.Ori Belkind - 2020 - Erkenntnis 87 (2):827-852.
    In this paper I argue that the positivist–conventionalist interpretation of the Restricted Principle of Relativity is flawed, due to the positivists’ own understanding of conventions and their origins. I claim in the paper that, to understand the conventionalist thesis, one has to diambiguate between three types of convention; the linguistic conventions stemming from the fundamental role of mathematical axioms, the conventions stemming from the coordination betweeh theoretical statements and physical, observable facts or entities, and conventions that are made possible by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  15
    An invitation to conventionalism: a philosophy for modern (space-)times.Patrick Dürr & James Read - 2024 - Synthese 204 (1):1-55.
    Geometric underdetermination (i.e., the underdetermination of the geometric properties of space and time) is a live possibility in light of some of our best theories of physics. In response to this, geometric conventionalism offers a selective anti-realism, refusing to assign truth values to variant geometric propositions. Although often regarded as being dead in the water by modern philosophers, in this article we propose to revitalise the programme of geometric conventionalism both on its own terms, and as an attractive (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33. On Logical Relativity.Achille C. Varzi - 2002 - Philosophical Issues 12 (1):197-219.
    One logic or many? I say—many. Or rather, I say there is one logic for each way of specifying the class of all possible circumstances, or models, i.e., all ways of interpreting a given language. But because there is no unique way of doing this, I say there is no unique logic except in a relative sense. Indeed, given any two competing logical theories T1 and T2 (in the same language) one could always consider their common core, T, and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  34.  69
    (1 other version)Conventionalism in geometry and the interpretation of necessary statements.Max Black - 1942 - Philosophy of Science 9 (4):335-349.
    The statements traditionally labelled “necessary,” among them the valid theorems of mathematics and logic, are identified as “those whose truth is independent of experience.” The “truth” of a necessary statement has to be independent of the truth or falsity of experiential statements; a necessary statement can be neither confirmed nor refuted by empirical tests.The admission of genuinely necessary statements presents the empiricist with a troublesome problem. For an empiricist may be defined, in terms of the current idiom, as one who (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  35.  58
    Lessons from the logic of demonstratives: what indexicality teaches us about logic and vice versa.G. Russell - 2012 - In Greg Restall & Gillian Kay Russell (eds.), New waves in philosophical logic. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    This paper looks at what David Kaplan's work on indexicals can teach us about logic and the philosophy of logic, and also what Kaplan's logic (i.e. the Logic of Demonstratives) can teach us about indexicals. The lessons are i) that logical consequence is not necessary truth-preservation, ii) that that the linguistic doctrine of necessary truth (also called conventionalism about modality) fails, and iii) that there is a kind of barrier to entailment between non-context-sensitive and context-sensitive claims.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  36.  83
    A Conventionalist Theory of Obligation.Govert Den Hartogh - 1998 - Law and Philosophy 17 (4):351 - 376.
    This DOI is not currently attached to any metadata records. DOIs can’t actually ever be deleted (they’re persistent), but sometimes our members create DOIs in error. We do have a process to approximate deletion which we follow only in rare cases where the DOI has been genuinely created in error, and most crucially, if the DOI has never been published anywhere online or in print and never otherwise distributed to or communicated with anyone (authors, readers, reviewers, etc.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  37.  70
    Infinite inference and mathematical conventionalism.Douglas Blue - 2025 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 109 (3):897-912.
    We argue that (1) a purported example of an infinite inference we humans can actually perform admits a faithful, finitary description, and (2) infinite inference contravenes any view which does not grant our minds uncomputable powers. These arguments block the strategy, dating back to Carnap's Logical Syntax of Language, of using infinitary inference rules to secure the determinacy of arithmetical truth on conventionalist grounds.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  9
    Carnap's Early Conventionalism: An Inquiry Into the Historical Background of the Vienna Circle.Edmund Runggaldier - 1984 - Rodopi.
    Revision of the author's thesis--Oxford University, 1977. Bibliography: p.[142]-144.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  39.  40
    (1 other version)The scientific world-perspective and other essays, 1931–1963, by Ajdukiewicz Kazimierz. Edited and with an introduction by Giedymin Jerzy. Synthese library, vol. 108. D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht and Boston 1978, LIII + 378 pp.Giedymin Jerzy. Editor's preface. Pp. IX–XII.Giedymin Jerzy. Ajdukiewicz's life and personality. Pp. XIII–XVI.Giedymin Jerzy. Radical conventionalism, its background and evolution: Poincaré, LeRoy, Ajdukiewicz. Pp. XIX–LIII.Ajdukiewicz Kazimierz. On the meaning of expressions. Pp. 1–34. English translation by Jerzy Giedymin of XXXVIII 536.Ajdukiewicz Kazimierz. Language and meaning. Pp. 35–66. English translation by John Wilkinson of 2259.Ajdukiewicz Kazimierz. The world-picture and the conceptual apparatus. Pp. 67–89. English translation by John Wilkinson of XXXVIII 537.Ajdukiewicz Kazimierz. On the applicability of pure logic to philosophical problems. Pp. 90–94. English translation by Jerzy Giedymin of XXXVIII 536.Ajdukiewicz Kazimierz. On the probl.C. Lejewski - 1978 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (2):457-463.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. (1 other version)Carnap's metrical conventionalism versus differential topology.Thomas Mormann - 2004 - Proc. 2004 Biennial Meeting of the PSA, vol. I, Contributed Papers 72 (5):814 - 825.
    Geometry was a main source of inspiration for Carnap’s conventionalism. Taking Poincaré as his witness Carnap asserted in his dissertation Der Raum (Carnap 1922) that the metrical structure of space is conventional while the underlying topological structure describes "objective" facts. With only minor modifications he stuck to this account throughout his life. The aim of this paper is to disprove Carnap's contention by invoking some classical theorems of differential topology. By this means his metrical conventionalism turns out to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41. A Defence of Conventionalism.Paul Horwich - 1986 - In Graham Macdonald & Crispin Wright (eds.), Fact, Science and Morality: Essays on A. J. Ayer's Language, Truth and Logic. Blackwell.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42.  30
    Objectivity and Consistency in Mathematics: A Critical Analysis of Two Objections to Wittgenstein's Pragmatic Conventionalism.Pieranna Garavaso - 1985 - Dissertation, The University of Nebraska - Lincoln
    Wittgenstein's views on mathematics are radically original. He criticizes most of the traditional philosophies of mathematics. His views have been subject to harsh criticisms. In this dissertation, I attempt to defend Wittgenstein's philosophy of mathematics from two objections: the objectivity objection and the consistency objection. The first claims that Wittgenstein's account of mathematics is not sufficient for the objectivity of mathematics; the second claims that it is only a partial account of mathematics because it cannot explain the semantic properties of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. An Argument from Proof Theory against Implicit Conventionalism.Rea Golan - 2023 - Philosophical Quarterly 74 (1):273-290.
    Conventionalism about logic is the view that logical principles hold in virtue of some linguistic conventions. According to explicit conventionalism, these conventions have to be stipulated explicitly. Explicit conventionalism is subject to a famous criticism by Quine, who accused it of leading to an infinite regress. In response to the criticism, several authors have suggested reconstructing conventionalism as implicit in our linguistic behaviour. In this paper, drawing on a distinction from proof theory between derivable and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  82
    Soames on the logical empiricists on truth, meaning, convention, and logical truth.Mario Gómez-Torrente - 2019 - Philosophical Studies 176 (5):1357-1365.
    In the first part of this paper, I express doubts that Tarski and Carnap were guilty of some confusions about the relations between truth and meaning, attributed to them by Soames. In the second part, I consider Quine's Carrollian argument against conventionalism about logical truth, discussed only briefly and approvingly by Soames, and I explore the question whether some not obviously incorrect forms of conventionalism about logical truth, such as what I call "finitary conventionalism", are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  21
    Political Philosophy of Science in Nineteenth-Century France: From Comte’s Positivism to Renouvier’s Conventionalism.Warren Schmaus - 2017 - In Marcus P. Adams, Zvi Biener, Uljana Feest & Jacqueline Anne Sullivan (eds.), Eppur Si Muove: Doing History and Philosophy of Science with Peter Machamer: A Collection of Essays in Honor of Peter Machamer. Dordrecht: Springer.
    Recent controversy over whether the Vienna Circle can provide a model for today’s political turn in the philosophy of science indicates the need to clarify just what is meant by the term political philosophy of science. This paper finds fourteen different meanings of the term, including both descriptive and normative usages, having to do with the roles of political values in the sciences, the political consequences and significance of the sciences and scientific modes of thought, and political processes within the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Necessity and language: In defence of conventionalism.Hans-Johann Glock - 2007 - Philosophical Investigations 31 (1):24–47.
    Kalhat has forcefully criticised Wittgenstein's linguistic or conventionalist account of logical necessity, drawing partly on Waismann and Quine. I defend conventionalism against the charge that it cannot do justice to the truth of necessary propositions, renders them unacceptably arbitrary or reduces them to metalingustic statements. At the same time, I try to reconcile Wittgenstein's claim that necessary propositions are constitutive of meaning with the logical positivists’ claim that they are true by virtue of meaning. Explaining necessary propositions (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  47.  47
    Is logic just last in line for the execution? Logic, holism, and the constitutive a priori.Oran Magal - unknown
    I argue that Quine’s early critique of Carnap’s conventionalism is in serious tension with the holism of "Two Dogmas of Empiricism", since his critique of convention- alism makes a compelling case for a privileged status either for logic, or for some other principle by means of which to derive consequences. Based on this, I call for a modification of Quinean holism, on grounds internal to Quine’s views. The result motivates a rehabilitation of Carnap’s notion of framework principles, and a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  5
    The Logical Perspective in Pragma-dialectics.Hubert Marraud - 2024 - Topoi 43 (4):1247-1258.
    I argue that the logical perspective—the study of arguments as products—is not well integrated into pragma-dialectics. I show that the Validity Rule and the Argumentation Scheme Rule, despite being procedural rules, are, in a certain sense, “logical” rules. Subsequently, I distinguish and review three successive periods in the development of the logical dimension of pragma-dialectics: conventionalist, inferentialist and dualist, to reveal that none of them is completely satisfactory. I contend that, given the assumptions and conceptual apparatus of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  95
    Necessity and language: in defence of conventionalism.Hans Johann Https://Orcidorg909X Glock - 2008 - .
    Kalhat has forcefully criticised Wittgenstein's linguistic or conventionalist account of logical necessity, drawing partly on Waismann and Quine. I defend conventionalism against the charge that it cannot do justice to the truth of necessary propositions, renders them unacceptably arbitrary or reduces them to metalingustic statements. At the same time, I try to reconcile Wittgenstein's claim that necessary propositions are constitutive of meaning with the logical positivists' claim that they are true by virtue of meaning. Explaining necessary propositions (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  50.  24
    Language, logic, and causation: philosophical writings of Douglas Gasking.Tim Oakley & L. J. O'Neill (eds.) - 1996 - Melbourne, Australia: Melbourne University Press.
    This volume is a collection of ten essays by Douglas Gasking (1911–1994), a significant figure in Australian philosophy. There are three previously published papers, “Mathematics and the World” (proposing a form of conventionalism), “Causation and Recipes” (expounding a manipulation account of causation), and “Clusters”, (an account of certain varieties of class-membership). The seven previously unpublished papers include further work on causation, some epistemological issues, subjective probability, a carefully worked out account of the sense in which observable behaviour can be (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 926