Results for 'formalization in philosophy'

958 found
Order:
  1. Formalization in philosophy.Sven Ove Hansson - 2000 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 6 (2):162-175.
    The advantages and disadvantages of formalization in philosophy are summarized. It is concluded that formalized philosophy is an endangered speciality that needs to be revitalized and to increase its interactions with non-formalized philosophy. The enigmatic style that is common in philosophical logic must give way to explicit discussions of the problematic relationship between formal models and the philosophical concepts and issues that motivated their development.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  2.  68
    The Emergence of Logical Formalization in the Philosophy of Religion: Genesis, Crisis, and Rehabilitation.Anders Kraal - 2013 - History and Philosophy of Logic 34 (4):351 - 366.
    The paper offers a historical survey of the emergence of logical formalization in twentieth-century analytically oriented philosophy of religion. This development is taken to have passed through three main ?stages?: a pioneering stage in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries (led by Frege and Russell), a stage of crisis in the 1920s and early 1930s (occasioned by Wittgenstein, logical positivists such as Carnap, and neo-Thomists such as Maritain), and a stage of rehabilitation in the 1930s, 1940s, and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3. Formal and Empirical Methods in Philosophy of Science.Vincenzo Crupi & Stephan Hartmann - 2009 - In Friedrich Stadler et al (ed.), The Present Situation in the Philosophy of Science. Springer. pp. 87--98.
    This essay addresses the methodology of philosophy of science and illustrates how formal and empirical methods can be fruitfully combined. Special emphasis is given to the application of experimental methods to confirmation theory and to recent work on the conjunction fallacy, a key topic in the rationality debate arising from research in cognitive psychology. Several other issue can be studied in this way. In the concluding section, a brief outline is provided of three further examples.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  89
    Formal and material theories in philosophy of science: a methodological interpretation.Alan Love - 2011 - In Henk W. De Regt, Stephan Hartmann & Samir Okasha (eds.), EPSA Philosophy of Science: Amsterdam 2009. Springer. pp. 175--185.
    John Norton’s argument that all formal theories of induction fail raises substantive questions about the philosophical analysis of scientific reasoning. What are the criteria of adequacy for philosophical theories of induction, explanation, or theory structure? Is more than one adequate theory possible? Using a generalized version of Norton’s argument, I demonstrate that the competition between formal and material theories in philosophy of science results from adhering to different criteria of adequacy. This situation encourages an interpretation of “formal” and “material” (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5.  5
    Challenging formalization in education and beyond: problems and solutions for traditional and online learning.Peter Serdyukov - 2022 - London: Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group.
    Challenging Formalization in Education and Beyond addresses the effects of today's attempts to organize knowledge, processes, and performance in education, particularly in its ever-growing digital environments. As on-site, blended, and fully online learning become deeply interdependent, secondary and higher education managers and instructors who seek to integrate, apply, and teach within these formats using standardized rules, assessments, algorithms, and accountability structures may be doing unintended harm to their students. Focusing on students' performance, health, cognition, behavior, and learning outcomes, this (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  32
    Formal and Informal Methods in Philosophy.Marcin Będkowski, Anna Brożek, Alicja Chybińska, Stepan Ivanyk & Dominik Traczykowski (eds.) - 2020 - Boston: Brill | Rodopi.
    The title of this book refers to the tension between formal and informal elements in the ways analytical philosophy is practiced. The authors examine questions of the scopes and limits of both kinds of research methods.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Argumentation and formal logic in philosophy.Henry Johnstone Jr - 1989 - Argumentation 3 (1).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  58
    Language Dependence in Philosophy of Science and Formal Epistemology.Branden Fitelson - unknown
    Suppose we have two false hypotheses H1 and H2. Sometimes, we would like to be able to say that H1 is closer to the truth than H2 (e.g., Newton’s hypothesis vs. Ptolemy’s).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  17
    Formal Ontology: Papers Presented at the International Summer School in Philosophy and Artificial Intelligence on "Formal Ontology", Bolzano, Italy, July 1-5, 1991, Central European Institute of Culture.Roberto Poli & Peter Simons (eds.) - 1996 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Kluwer.
    Formal ontology combines two ideas, one originating with Husserl, the other with Frege: that of ontology of the formal aspects of all objects, irrespective of their particular nature, and ontology pursued by employing the tools of modern formal disciplines, notably logic and semantics. These two traditions have converged in recent years and this is the first collection to encompass them as a whole in a single volume. It assembles essays from authors around the world already widely known for their work (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  10.  73
    Formalization in Philosophical Logic.Dale Jacquette - 1994 - The Monist 77 (3):358-375.
    The tools of logic are used properly or improperly relative to two interrelated purposes. Logic is both a symbolism for the expression of the formal structures of thought and an inference mechanism. Formalization in philosophical logic is justified to the extent that it contributes to our understanding of logical properties and the conceptual problems they may help to state, clarify, or resolve. This view of the value and limits of formalization in logic affords a pragmatic perspective that in (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11. Mathematical formalisms in scientific practice: From denotation to model-based representation.Axel Gelfert - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (2):272-286.
    The present paper argues that ‘mature mathematical formalisms’ play a central role in achieving representation via scientific models. A close discussion of two contemporary accounts of how mathematical models apply—the DDI account (according to which representation depends on the successful interplay of denotation, demonstration and interpretation) and the ‘matching model’ account—reveals shortcomings of each, which, it is argued, suggests that scientific representation may be ineliminably heterogeneous in character. In order to achieve a degree of unification that is compatible with successful (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  12.  50
    Formal Methods and Science in Philosophy: Introduction to the Special Issue.Patrick Blackburn, Srećko Kovač & Kordula Świętorzecka - 2020 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 49 (2):105-107.
    Introduction to the Special Issue containing selected contributions to the conference "Formal Methods and Science in Philosophy IV", Inter-University Center, Dubrovnik, April 11-13, 2019.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Changing use of formal methods in philosophy: late 2000s vs. late 2010s.Samuel C. Fletcher, Joshua Knobe, Gregory Wheeler & Brian Allan Woodcock - 2021 - Synthese 199 (5-6):14555-14576.
    Traditionally, logic has been the dominant formal method within philosophy. Are logical methods still dominant today, or have the types of formal methods used in philosophy changed in recent times? To address this question, we coded a sample of philosophy papers from the late 2000s and from the late 2010s for the formal methods they used. The results indicate that the proportion of papers using logical methods remained more or less constant over that time period but the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  14.  46
    Overcoming Instructor‐Originated Math Anxiety in Philosophy Students: A Consideration of Proven Techniques for Students Taking Formal Logic.Brian Macpherson - 2016 - Metaphilosophy 47 (1):122-146.
    Every university student has his or her nemesis. Biology and social science students anticipate with great apprehension their required statistics course, while many philosophy students live in fear of formal logic. Math anxiety is the common thread uniting all of them. This article argues that since formal logic is an algebra requiring similar kinds of symbol-manipulation skills needed to succeed in a basic mathematics course, then if logic students have math anxiety, this can impede their progress. Further, it argues (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  94
    The desirability of formalization in science.Patrick Suppes - 1968 - Journal of Philosophy 65 (20):651-664.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  16. (1 other version)Foundations of The Formal Sciences II. Applications of Mathematical Logic in Philosophy and Linguistics [Trends in Logic].Benedikt Löwe, Wolfgang Malzkorn & Thoralf Räsch (eds.) - 2003 - Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  17.  74
    The Geometry of Knowledge: Lewis, Becker, Carnap and the Formalization of Philosophy in the 1920s.Alan Richardson - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (1):165-182.
    On an ordinary view of the relation of philosophy of science to science, science serves only as a topic for philosophical reflection, reflection that proceeds by its own methods and according to its own standards. This ordinary view suggests a way of writing a global history of philosophy of science that finds substantially the same philosophical projects being pursued across widely divergent scientific eras. While not denying that this view is of some use regarding certain themes of and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  18. Formal Indication, Philosophy, and Theology.Brian Gregor - 2007 - Faith and Philosophy 24 (2):185-202.
    This paper examines Heidegger’s account of the proper relation between philosophy and theology, and Dietrich Bonhoeffer’s critique thereof. Part I outlines Heidegger’s proposal for this relationship in his lecture “Phenomenology and Theology,” where he suggests that philosophy might aid theology by means of ‘formal indication.’ In that context Heidegger never articulates what formal indication is, so Part II exposits this obscure notion by looking at its treatment in Heidegger’s early lecture courses, as well as its roots in Husserl. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  26
    Natural language at a crossroads: Formal and probabilistic approaches in philosophy and computer science.Paulo Pirozelli & Igor Câmara - 2022 - Manuscrito 45 (2):50-81.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  81
    Model‐Building in Philosophy.Timothy Williamson - 2017 - In Russell Blackford & Damien Broderick (eds.), Philosophy's Future. Hoboken: Wiley. pp. 159–171.
    The chapter argues that a model‐building methodology like that widespread in contemporary natural and social science already plays a significant role in philosophy. One neglected form of progress in philosophy over the past fifty years has been the development of better and better formal models of significant phenomena. Examples are given from both philosophy of language and epistemology. Philosophy can do still better in the future by applying model‐building methods more systematically and self‐consciously, with consequent readjustments (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  21.  2
    Between Logic and Intuition: David Lewis and the Future of Formal Methods in Philosophy.Johan van Benthem, Vincent F. Hendricks, John Symons & Stig Andur Pedersen (eds.) - 2008 - Springer.
  22.  18
    Foundations of the Formal Sciences Ii: Applications of Mathematical Logic in Philosophy and Linguistics, Papers of a Conference Held in Bonn, November 10–13, 2000.Benedikt Löwe, Wolfgang Malzkom & Thoralf Räsch (eds.) - 2003 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    "Foundations of the Formal Sciences" is a series of interdisciplinary conferences in mathematics, philosophy, computer science and linguistics. The main goal is to reestablish the traditionally strong links between these areas of research that have been lost in the past decades. The second conference in the series had the subtitle "Applications of Mathematical Logic in Philosophy and Linguistics" and brought speakers from all parts of the Formal Sciences together to give a holistic view of how mathematical methods can (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  68
    Teaching Formal Logic as Logic Programming in Philosophy Departments.Richard Tieszen - 1992 - Teaching Philosophy 15 (4):337-347.
  24. Formal Methods in the Philosophy of Science.Leon Horsten & Igor Douven - 2008 - Studia Logica 89 (2):151-162.
    In this article, we reflect on the use of formal methods in the philosophy of science. These are taken to comprise not just methods from logic broadly conceived, but also from other formal disciplines such as probability theory, game theory, and graph theory. We explain how formal modelling in the philosophy of science can shed light on difficult problems in this domain.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  25. Logic in Philosophy.Johan van Benthem - 2002 - In Dale Jacquette (ed.), Philosophy of Logic. Malden, Mass.: North Holland. pp. 65-99.
    1 Logic in philosophy The century that was Logic has played an important role in modern philosophy, especially, in alliances with philosophical schools such as the Vienna Circle, neopositivism, or formal language variants of analytical philosophy. The original impact was via the work of Frege, Russell, and other pioneers, backed up by the prestige of research into the foundations of mathematics, which was fast bringing to light those amazing insights that still impress us to-day. The Golden Age (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  26. Identity and discernibility in philosophy and logic.James Ladyman, Øystein Linnebo & Richard Pettigrew - 2012 - Review of Symbolic Logic 5 (1):162-186.
    Questions about the relation between identity and discernibility are important both in philosophy and in model theory. We show how a philosophical question about identity and dis- cernibility can be ‘factorized’ into a philosophical question about the adequacy of a formal language to the description of the world, and a mathematical question about discernibility in this language. We provide formal definitions of various notions of discernibility and offer a complete classification of their logical relations. Some new and surprising facts (...)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  27.  53
    Open-mindedness in Philosophy of Religion.Gregory E. Trickett & John R. Gilhooly (eds.) - 2019 - Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars.
    In a free society, it is common to hear the request that one â ~keep an open mind.â Just what exactly is it, however, to keep an open-mind? How does open-mindedness function? How does it square with important personal commitments? These issues are particularly acute when it comes to matters of religious belief in which open-mindedness can sound to the pious a bit too much like doubt. Certainly, in a discipline whose discourse remains rational dialogue, effort should be spent discerning (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  6
    Il trascendere formale in Karl Jaspers: strumenti ed esiti di una metafisica non-oggettiva.Paolo Cattorini - 1986 - Milano: Vita e pensiero.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. What is formal in Husserl's logical investigations?Gianfranco Soldati - 1999 - European Journal of Philosophy 7 (3):330–338.
    It is sometimes said that questions of form are questions of logic or language. In his "Logical Investigations" Husserl, however, clearly distinguished formal ontology from formal grammar and formal logic. The article attempts to explain Husserl's notion of formal ontology. It investigates the relation between formal and material ontology as well as the relation between epistemic and metaphysical necessity. The article provides an interpretation of Husserl's claim that there are metaphysical necessities which are necessarily recognized by the human mind on (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  7
    Il trascendere formale in Karl Jaspers: strumenti ed esiti di una metafisica non-oggettiva.Franco Riva - 1971 - Milano: Vita e Pensiero.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. The Logic in Philosophy of Science.Hans Halvorson - 2019 - Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Major figures of twentieth-century philosophy were enthralled by the revolution in formal logic, and many of their arguments are based on novel mathematical discoveries. Hilary Putnam claimed that the Löwenheim-Skølem theorem refutes the existence of an objective, observer-independent world; Bas van Fraassen claimed that arguments against empiricism in philosophy of science are ineffective against a semantic approach to scientific theories; W. V. O. Quine claimed that the distinction between analytic and synthetic truths is trivialized by the fact that (...)
  32.  51
    Linguistics in Philosophy[REVIEW]John Kleinig - 1969 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 18 (3):262-264.
    J L Austin has left a firm imprint on much contemporary philosophy. Not surprisingly, however, his published papers and lectures have provoked strongly contrasting responses, some seeing in them the refinement of certain philosophical techniques and the introduction of new standards of care, others the final degeneration of linguistic philosophy into verbal hair-splitting. Whatever the response, his writings were bound to attract the attention of formal linguists, and the last decade has seen a significant number of contributions by (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  19
    (1 other version)The Concept of Formality in Mathematics.Hiroshi Nagai - 1960 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 1 (5):289-312.
  34. The beginnings of formalization in theology.E. Niezńanski - 1991 - In Georg Schurz (ed.), Advances in Scientific Philosophy. pp. 551--9.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  18
    Understanding in philosophy of language.Ekaterina V. Vostrikova & Petr S. Kusliy - 2017 - Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 54 (4):62-67.
    This paper addresses the question of understanding of language expressions. We argue that understanding of language expressions can be successfully studied within a general approach of formal semantics and pragmatics. We show how three types of meanings of expressions (truth conditional meaning, presuppositional component and implicatures) contribute to our general understanding of what was said and how those meanings can be studied within the formal approach.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. The following classification is pragmatic and is intended merely to facilitate reference. No claim to exhaustive categorization is made by the parenthetical additions in small capitals.Psycholinguistics Semantics & Formal Properties Of Languages - 1974 - Foundations of Language: International Journal of Language and Philosophy 12:149.
  37.  55
    Hermann Dishkant. The first order predicate calculus based on the logic of quantum mechanics. Reports on mathematical logic, no. 3 , pp. 9–17. - G. N. Georgacarakos. Orthomodularity and relevance. Journal of philosophical logic, vol. 8 , pp. 415–432. - G. N. Georgacarakos. Equationally definable implication algebras for orthomodular lattices. Studia logica, vol. 39 , pp. 5–18. - R. J. Greechie and S. P. Gudder. Is a quantum logic a logic?Helvetica physica acta, vol. 44 , pp. 238–240. - Gary M. Hardegree. The conditional in abstract and concrete quantum logic. The logico-algehraic approach to quantum mechanics, volume II, Contemporary consolidation, edited by C. A. Hooker, The University of Western Ontario series in philosophy of science, vol. 5, D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Boston, and London, 1979, pp. 49–108. - Gary M. Hardegree. Material implication in orthomodular lattices. Notre Dame journal of formal logic, vol. 22 , pp. 163–182. - J. M. Jauch and C. Piron. What is “q. [REVIEW]Alasdair Urquhart - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (1):206-208.
  38.  43
    Studies in Philosophy and the History of Philosophy, Vol. III: John Duns Scotus, 1265-1965. [REVIEW]A. R. E. - 1968 - Review of Metaphysics 21 (3):567-567.
    This is an outstanding contribution to Scotistic scholarship in English. A distinguished array of Scotus and medieval philosophy scholars have served up polished essays to mark this the seventh centenary of the birth of the "Subtle Doctor." Allan Wolter writes on "The Formal Distinction," Timotheus A. Barth on "Being, Univocity, and Analogy According to Duns Scotus," Heiko Oberman on "Duns Scotus, Nominalism, and the Council of Trent," Efrem Bettoni on "The Originality of the Scotistic Synthesis," Bonansea on "Duns Scotus' (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  21
    The Meaning and Value of Formalization in Logic.A. L. Subbotin - 1963 - Russian Studies in Philosophy 2 (1):85-95.
    1. One sometimes finds, in popular literature, the statement that formal logic is called formal because it studies the forms of thought: concepts, judgments, inferences. To confine the definition in this way would, to say the least, be an inaccuracy. Study of concepts and other forms of thought is generally assumed to be a task of philosophy; and it attains its highest development in dialectical philosophy. The fact is that statements such as the one we have cited are (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  32
    Grammar in Philosophy[REVIEW]B. J. - 1980 - Review of Metaphysics 34 (2):399-400.
    Although Ordinary Language Philosophy is widely believed to have disappeared leaving scarcely a trace in this era of formal semantics, it is very much the formal semantics of ordinary language that dominates the scene. More common ground than one might have supposed proves thus to be available for the unreconstructed ordinary language philosopher, in the present volume, to enter into the thick of current discussion. The prevailing tone of the work is certainly much more formal than anything one recalls (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Thought Experiments in Philosophy.Soren Haggqvist - 1998 - Philosophical Review 107 (3):480.
    Philosophy and science employ abstract hypothetical scenarios- thought experiments - to illustrate, defend, and dispute theoretical claims. Since thought experiments furnish no new empirical observations, the method prompts two epistemological questions: whether anything may be learnt from the merely hypothetical, and, if so, how. Various sceptical arguments against the use of thought experiments in philosophy are discussed and criticized. The thesis that thought experiments in science provide a priori knowledge through non-sensory grasping of abstract entities is discussed and (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  42.  13
    What can we do in Philosophy using Frege’s and Kripke’s logics?Lourdes Valdivia Dounce - 2024 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 28 (1):119-133.
    In this article I issue a challenge to philosophers engaged in constructing logical languages. Formal languages that have had a great influence on various areas of philosophy have ineffable statements that arise from metaphysical assumptions, thus limiting what we can do with them. I deal with two cases. The case of Frege known as “The paradox of the concept horse”, and that of Kripke that is not as famous as the Fregean problem, which I call “The necessary bearing of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  11
    (1 other version)Bayesian networks in philosophy.Luc Bovens & Stephan Hartmann - 2003 - In Benedikt Löwe, Wolfgang Malzkorn & Thoralf Räsch (eds.), Foundations of the Formal Sciences Ii: Applications of Mathematical Logic in Philosophy and Linguistics. Springer Verlag. pp. 39-46.
    There is a long philosophical tradition of addressing questions in philosophy of science and epistemology by means of the tools of Bayesian probability theory (see Earman (1992) and Howson and Urbach (1993)). In the late '70s, an axiomatic approach to conditional independence was developed within a Bayesian framework. This approach in conjunction with developments in graph theory are the two pillars of the theory of Bayesian Networks, which is a theory of probabilistic reasoning in artificial intelligence. The theory has (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  55
    Caught in the Middle: Philosophy of Science between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of “Kuhn Sneedified”.Christian Damböck - 2014 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 4 (1):62-82.
    This article is concerned with the development of philosophy of science in the 1970s. The explanatory framework is the picture of two fundamental split-offs: the controversial establishment of history and sociology of science and of formal philosophy of science as independent disciplines, against the background of more traditional “conceptual” varieties of philosophy of science. I illustrate these developments, which finally led to somewhat “purified” versions of the respective accounts, by examining a case study, namely, that of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45.  38
    Formal Methods in the Philosophy of Natural Science.Thomas Müller - 2010 - In Thomas Uebel, Stephan Hartmann, Wenceslao Gonzalez, Marcel Weber, Dennis Dieks & Friedrich Stadler (eds.), The Present Situation in the Philosophy of Science. Springer. pp. 111--123.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  46.  63
    Formal Identity as Isomorphism in Thomistic Philosophy of Mind.Stephen Pimentel - 2006 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 80:115-126.
    A central problem within an influential strand of recent philosophy of mind has been to explain the “conformity of mind to thing” that characterizes knowledge. John Haldane has argued that this problem can be best addressed by a development of Thomas Aquinas’s account of the “formal identity” of the knowing subject with the object known. However, such a development is difficult to present in a manner perspicuous to a contemporary audience. This paper seeks to present a persuasive account of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  11
    Other Logics: Alternatives to Formal Logic in the History of Thought and Contemporary Philosophy.Admir Skodo (ed.) - 2014 - Boston: Brill.
    In Other Logics: Alternatives to Formal Logic in the History of Thought and Contemporary Philosophy , edited by Admir Skodo, an array of historical and philosophical chapters decenter the idea of formal logic as the most accurate, timeless, and abstract description of all thought and reasoning.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Proof, Logic and Formalization.Michael Detlefsen (ed.) - 1992 - London, England: Routledge.
    The mathematical proof is the most important form of justification in mathematics. It is not, however, the only kind of justification for mathematical propositions. The existence of other forms, some of very significant strength, places a question mark over the prominence given to proof within mathematics. This collection of essays, by leading figures working within the philosophy of mathematics, is a response to the challenge of understanding the nature and role of the proof.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  49.  30
    Naturauffassungen in Philosophie, Wissenschaft, Technik, vol. 4. [REVIEW]Riccardo Pozzo - 1998 - Review of Metaphysics 52 (2):480-481.
    This volume concludes a series dedicated to the understanding of nature by philosophers, scientists, and technicians from antiquity to today. This understanding is an issue largely debated today by philosophers as well as nonphilosophers. Being the fourth and the last, this volume includes also an index rerum of the items dealt with in this as well as in the preceding three volumes. The seven essays it presents are primarily concerned with the positions of Newton, Kant, and Einstein. In fact, the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Formal semantics in modern type theories with coercive subtyping.Zhaohui Luo - 2012 - Linguistics and Philosophy 35 (6):491-513.
    In the formal semantics based on modern type theories, common nouns are interpreted as types, rather than as predicates of entities as in Montague’s semantics. This brings about important advantages in linguistic interpretations but also leads to a limitation of expressive power because there are fewer operations on types as compared with those on predicates. The theory of coercive subtyping adequately extends the modern type theories and, as shown in this paper, plays a very useful role in making type theories (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
1 — 50 / 958