Results for 'desire for good'

980 found
Order:
  1. The Desire for Good: Is the Meno Inconsistent with the Gorgias?Terry Penner & Rowe - 1994 - Phronesis 39 (1):1-25.
  2. Socrates on the Desire for Good and the Involuntariness of Wrongdoing: Gorgias 466a-468e.Kevin McTighe - 1992 - In Hugh H. Benson (ed.), Essays on the philosophy of Socrates. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 263--297.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  64
    Desire for good in meno 77b2–78b6.David Wolfsdorf - 2006 - Classical Quarterly 56 (01):77-.
  4. Desire for the Good in the Meno.M. Anagnostopoulos - 2003 - In Naomi Reshotko & Terry Penner (eds.), Desire, identity, and existence: essays in honor of T.M. Penner. Kelowna, B.C., Canada: Academic Print. &. pp. 171--91.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5.  41
    Plato's Moral Psychology: Intellectualism, the Divided Soul, and the Desire for Good.Rachana Kamtekar - 2017 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    Rachana Kamtekar offers a new understanding of Plato's account of the soul and its impact on our living well or badly, virtuously or viciously. She argues that throughout the dialogues Plato maintains that human beings have a natural desire for our own good, and that actions and conditions contrary to this desire are involuntary.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  6. The Forms, the Form of the Good, and the Desire for Good in Plato’s Republic.Terry Penner - 2003 - Modern Schoolman 80 (3):191-233.
  7.  19
    Plato’s Moral Psychology: Intellectualism, the Divided Soul, and the Desire for Good, written by Rachana Kamtekar.Sabrina Little - 2020 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 17 (3):363-366.
  8. The divided soul and desire for the good in Plato's republic.Mariana Anagnostopoulos - 2006 - In Gerasimos Santas (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Plato's "Republic". Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 166--188.
    This chapter contains section titled: Plato's Argument for the Tripartition of the Soul Psychic Justice and the Composite Soul The Problem of Unjust Souls Desire for the Good.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9. Socrates on Desire for the Good and the Involuntariness of Wrongdoing: Gorgias 466a-468e.Kevin Mctighe - 1984 - Phronesis 29 (3):193-236.
  10.  36
    Plato's Moral Psychology: Intellectualism, the Divided Soul, and the Desire for Good by Rachana Kamtekar.Emily Fletcher - 2020 - Philosophical Review 129 (4):643-646.
  11.  67
    The desire for health and the promises of medicine.Roberto Mordacci - 1998 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 1 (1):21-30.
    The varieties of meaning in which we use the terms illness and health requires that we develope a conceptualization allowing us to maintain a unity between the differences. In fact, the experiences of health and illness are complex ones and they need to be understood in their different levels so that the need for help of patients and their desire for health is adequately faced. At its roots, the experience of illness is that of a threat posed to the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12. Plato on the Desire for the Good.Rachel Barney - 2010 - In Sergio Tenenbaum (ed.), Desire, Practical Reason, and the Good. , US: Oxford University Press. pp. 34--64.
  13.  11
    Desire for Happiness and the Commandments in the First Chapter of Veritatis Splendor.Livio Melina & M. Harper Mccarthy - 1996 - The Thomist 60 (3):341-359.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:DESIRE FOR HAPPINESS AND THE COMMANDMENTS IN THE FIRST CHAPTER OF VER/TATIS SPLENDOR* LIVIO MELINA Pontijicio Istituto Giovanni Paolo II Rome, Italy ' ' THE DESIRE for happiness" and "the commandments " seem to constitute two irreducible alternatives, representing a contrariety that separates the classical conception of morality from the modern. The choice that Catholic post-Tridentine handbook theology made to remove the treatise on happiness from moral (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  17
    Why the Good? Appearance, Reality and the Desire for the Good in Republic, VI, 504B-506D.Dimitri El Murr - 2014 - Méthexis 27 (1):47-60.
    What arguments does Plato offer to explain the pre-eminence he confers to the idea of the Good in Republic, 6? Considering in detail the short but key section of the Republic (504b-506d) that precedes the analogy between the Good and the Sun, this paper argues that it is what Plato claims to be the universal recognition that the Good exists independently of any opinion that makes it so important for human thought. Nothing less than the concept that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  29
    Is the desire for a meaningful life a selfless desire?Joshua Lewis Thomas - 2019 - Human Affairs 29 (4):445-452.
    Susan Wolf defines a meaningful life as one that is somewhat successfully engaged in promoting positive value. I grant this claim; however, I disagree with Wolf’s theory about why we desire meaningfulness, so understood. She suggests that the human desire for meaningfulness is derived from an awareness of ourselves as equally insignificant in the universe and a resulting anti-solipsistic concern for promoting goodness outside the boundaries of our own lives. I accept that this may succeed in explaining why (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  30
    The Desire for Knowledge in Early Scotist Debate: William of Alnwick and John of Reading.Francesco Fiorentino - 2015 - Quaestio 15:675-687.
    Alnwick distances himself from Scotus, as he appears in Lectura Oxoniensis and the commentary on Metaphysics, though the natural propensity of the will is affirmed in q. 9 d. 49 of Book Four of Reportata Parisiensia. However, this question could be spurious, or else more susceptible to the Parisian influence of teaching of Henry of Ghent, with whom Alnwick aligns himself when he sanctions without any doubt the fact that man desires to pass from a lesser good, guaranteed by (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  42
    Is the desire for life rational?Christophe de Ray - forthcoming - Religious Studies:1-19.
    The question of the meaning of life has long been thought to be closely intertwined with that of the existence of God. I offer a new theistic, anti-naturalist argument from the meaning of life. It is argued that the desire for life is irrational on naturalism, since there would be no good reason to believe that life is worthwhile on the whole if naturalism were true. As I show, the same cannot be argued of theism. Since it is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Desire and Goodness.Allan Hazlett - 2021 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 105 (1):160-180.
    Hume argued that passions, unlike judgments of the understanding, cannot be reasonable or unreasonable. Crucial for his argument was the premise that passions cannot be correct or incorrect. As he put it: “[a] passion is an original existence … and contains not any representative quality” and “passions are not susceptible of any … agreement or disagreement either to the real relations of ideas, or to real existence and matter of fact … being original facts and realities, compleat in themselves.” In (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  49
    Plato’s Moral Psychology: Intellectualism, the Divided Soul, and the Desire for Good by Rachana Kamtekar. [REVIEW]Ravi Sharma - 2019 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 57 (1):160-161.
  20.  28
    Plato’s Moral Psychology: Intellectualism, the Divided Soul, and the Desire for Good, by Rachana Kamtekar. [REVIEW]G. S. Bowe - 2019 - Ancient Philosophy 39 (2):477-481.
  21.  25
    "To make a difference...": Narrative Desire in Global Medicine.Byron J. Good & Mary-Jo DelVecchio Good - 2012 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 2 (2):121-124.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:"To make a difference...":Narrative Desire in Global MedicineByron J. Good and Mary-Jo DelVecchio GoodIf, as Arthur Frank (2002) writes, "moral life, for better and worse, takes place in storytelling," this collection of narratives written by physicians working in field settings in global medicine gives us a glimpse of some aspects of moral experience, practice, and dilemmas in settings of poverty and low health care resources. These essays (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  74
    Friendship in education and the desire for the good: An interpretation of Plato's phaedrus.D. P. E. Muir - 2000 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 32 (2):233–247.
  23.  28
    Rachana Kamtekar, Plato’s Moral Psychology: Intellectualism, the Divided Soul, and the Desire for the Good (review).Nicholas D. Smith - 2018 - Ethics 129 (2):404-408.
  24.  82
    Educating for Good Questioning: a Tool for Intellectual Virtues Education.Lani Watson - 2018 - Acta Analytica 33 (3):353-370.
    Questioning is a familiar, everyday practice which we use, often unreflectively, in order to gather information, communicate with each other, and advance our inquiries. Yet, not all questions are equally effective and not all questioners are equally adept. Being a good questioner requires a degree of proficiency and judgment, both in determining what to ask and in deciding who, where, when, and how to ask. Good questioning is an intellectual skill. Given its ubiquity and significance, it is an (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  25.  69
    Aristotle on the Good Man’s Desire for Pleasant Friends.Andreas Vakirtzis - 2018 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 12 (2):74-88.
  26. Reflective commentary (2): appearance, reality and the desire for the good.Dimitri El Murr - 2013 - In G. Boys-Stones, C. Gill & D. El-Murr (eds.), The Platonic Art of philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  46
    The Self-Justifying Desire for Happiness.Raffaele Rodogno - 2004 - South African Journal of Philosophy 23 (4):343-352.
    In Happiness, Tabensky equates the notion of happiness to Aristotelian eudaimonia. I shall claim that doing so amounts to equating two concepts that moderns cannot conceptually equate, namely, the good for a person and the good person or good life. In §2 I examine the way in which Tabensky deals with this issue and claim that his idea of happiness is as problematic for us moderns as is any translation of the notion of eudaimonia in terms of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  31
    Psychological eudaimonism and the natural desire for the good: Comments on Rachana Kamtekar's Plato's Moral Psychology.Iakovos Vasiliou - 2021 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 103 (1):234-239.
  29.  33
    Slow Tech: a quest for good, clean and fair ICT.Norberto Patrignani & Diane Whitehouse - 2014 - Journal of Information, Communication and Ethics in Society 12 (2):78-92.
    Purpose– The purpose of this paper is to introduce the term Slow Tech as a way of describing information and communication technology that is good, clean and fair. These are technologies that are human centred, environmentally sustainable and socially desirable.Design/methodology/approach– The paper's approach is based on a qualitative discourse that justifies the introduction of Slow Tech as a new design paradigm.Findings– The limits of the human body, and the need to take into account human wellbeing, the limits of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  30.  91
    What are desires good for? Towards a coherent endorsement theory.Krister Bykvist - 2006 - Ratio 19 (3):286–304.
    Desire-based theories of well-being are often said to accept (G), x is good for a person just in case he wants it, and (B), x is better for a person than y just in case he prefers x to y. I shall argue that (G) and (B) are inconsistent, and this inconsistency resists any plausible refinement of these principles. The inconsistency is brought out by cases in which our wants and preferences for certain life-options are contingent on which (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  31.  17
    Towards a Theory of Schooling for Good Life in Postcolonial Societies.Vikas Maniar - 2019 - Journal of Human Values 25 (3):166-176.
    Schools often aim at creating opportunities for good life and at promoting a good society. Liberal theorization on schooling is premised on a functioning liberal democracy with a capitalist economy. However, postcolonial societies are characterized by poverty and inequality, cultural diversity, and an ongoing project of state and nation building. This challenges some of the foundational assumptions of liberal conceptions of schooling aimed at promoting good life and good society in postcolonial societies. Realization of good (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32. The morality of the desire for esteem: Gassendi and the Augustinian challenge.Andreas Blank - 2021 - History of European Ideas 47 (8):1228-1242.
    ABSTRACT Pierre Gassendi (1592–1655) has not been perceived as one of the early modern philosophers who had something interesting to say about the role of the desire for esteem in social life and the moral duties connected with this desire. Nevertheless, in his Animadversiones in decimum librum Diogenis Laertii (1649) there are some scattered, but interrelated remarks about how the desire for esteem could be supportive of civic virtue. These remarks were written during the years when Jansenism (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. The Recovery of the Natural Desire for Salvation.Jorge Martín Montoya Camacho & José Manuel Giménez Amaya - 2024 - Scientia et Fides 12 (1):119-141.
    Dynamic Theodicy (DT) is a broad concept we bring up to designate some modern Philosophical Theology attempts to reconcile the necessary and perfect existence of God with the contingent characteristics of human life. In this paper we analyze such approaches and discuss how they have become incomprehensible because the metaphysical assumptions implicit in these explanations have lost their intrinsic relation to the natural human desire for salvation. In the first part we show Charles Hartshorne's DT-model, arising from the modal (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Desire-Based Theories of Reasons and the Guise of the Good.Kael McCormack - 2023 - Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 9 (47):1288-1321.
    I propose an account of desire that reconciles two apparently conflicting intuitions about practical agency. I do so by exploring a certain intuitive datum. The intuitive datum is that often when an agent desires P she will seem to immediately and conclusively know that there is a reason to bring P about. Desire-based theories of reasons seem uniquely placed to explain this intuitive datum. On this view, desires are the source of an agent’s practical reasons. A desire (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35.  84
    Desire and the Good: in search of the right fit.Graham Oddie - 2017 - In Federico Lauria & Julien Deonna (eds.), The Nature of Desire. New York, USA: Oxford University Press.
    I argue for an evaluative theory of desire—specifically, that to desire something is for it to appear, in some way or other, good. If a desire is a non-doxastic appearance of value then it is no mystery how it can rationalize as well as cause action. The theory is metaphysically neutral—it is compatible with value idealism (that value reduces to desire), with value realism (that it is not so reducible), and with value nihilism (all appearances (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  36. Desire, Practical Reason, and the Good.Sergio Tenenbaum (ed.) - 2010 - , US: Oxford University Press.
    Most philosophers working in moral psychology and practical reason think that either the notion of "good" or the notion of "desire" have central roles to play in our understanding of intentional explanations and practical reasoning. However, philosophers disagree sharply over how we are supposed to understand the notions of "desire" and "good", how these notions relate, and whether both play a significant and independent role in practical reason. In particular, the "Guise of the Good" thesis (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  37.  59
    What Motivates Software Crackers?Sigi Goode & Sam Cruise - 2006 - Journal of Business Ethics 65 (2):173-201.
    Software piracy is a serious problem in the software industry. Software authors and publishing companies lose revenue when pirated software rather than legally purchased software is used. Policy developers are forced to invest time and money into restricting software piracy. Much of the published research literature focuses on software piracy by end-users. However, end-users are only able to copy software once the copy protection has been removed by a ‘cracker’. This research aims to explore why, if copy protection is so (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  67
    Perceptual differences of sales practitioners and students concerning ethical behavior.J. B. DeConinck & D. J. Good - 1989 - Journal of Business Ethics 8 (9):667 - 676.
    This study investigates specific behavioral perceptual differences of ethics between practitioners and students enrolled in sales classes. Respondents were asked to indicate their beliefs to issues related to ethics in sales. A highly significant difference was found between mean responses of students and sales personnel. Managers indicated a greater concern for ethical behavior and less attention to sales than did the students. Students indicated a strong desire for success regardless of ethical constraints violated.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  39.  17
    Spinoza: Desire and Supreme Good, from Philosophizing to Wise.Alla Marcellin Konin & N’Dré Sam Beugre - 2023 - International Journal of Philosophy 11 (3):56-62.
    If Spinoza is a thinker very present in the Faculties of Philosophy, on the other hand, he is presented as one of the great forgotten of the humanist programs of secondary education. Contrary to what happened with other philosophers, who had more chance of spreading in non-specialized contexts (we can cite Nietzsche, Pascal, Plato or Schopenhauer as obvious examples), Spinoza is generally considered a excessively systematic author, and complex, whose works would have been written for a small group of scholars. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  57
    Good design as design for good: exploring how design can be ethically and environmentally sustainable by co-designing an eco-hostel within a Mayan community.Claudia Garduño García - 2015 - Journal of Global Ethics 11 (1):110-125.
    Designers acknowledge that their skills can assist the visualization and materialization of a desirable future and have gone as far as proposing that design can achieve societal change. Designing for a better world is associated with decreasing environmental depletion impacts while making good for both people and the environment, if possible. Evidently, this is a space where design deals with ethical matters, defining what is good or questioning if good has a universal meaning. This paper discusses the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  25
    Kant on Love for Oneself: Why Respect for the Moral Law, but Not the Desire for Happiness, is a Moral Incentive.Lawrence Masek - 2002 - Dissertation, Marquette University
    After reading Kant's claim that only the moral law and respect for the moral law can motivate moral actions, readers sometimes caricature Kant's moral theory as a bizarre form of rule-fetishism that provides no good explanation of why people should act morally. My dissertation challenges this caricature by defending the thesis that Kant correctly maintains that moral actions always benefit the agent. ;This thesis seems to contradict Kant's claim that self-love cannot motivate moral actions and his distinction between acting (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  54
    Globalization and the Good Corporation: A Need for Proactive Co-existence.S. Prakash Sethi - 2003 - Journal of Business Ethics 43 (1-2):21-31.
    Large corporations are coming under intense pressure to act in a socially responsible manner. Corporations have accepted this notion provided that it is exercised voluntarily. It has also been argued that corporations can do well by doing good, and that good ethics is good business. This paper presents an alternative viewpoint by demonstrating that while voluntary socially responsible conduct is desirable, it plays a rather small role in inspiring good corporate conduct. Instead, (a) it is the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  43.  22
    Striving for Contemplation. True Politicians Vs Good Politicians in Aristotle's Philosophy.Elena Irrera - 2010 - Elenchos 31 (1):77-110.
    In this paper I will argue that, in Aristotle’s thought, the political commitment of authentically wise men is ultimately motivated by an intellectual rather than by a merely practical interest. Through analysis of Eudemian Ethics A 4. 1216 a 23-7 and Q 3. 1248 b 8-37 I shall contend that the socalled “true politician” is to be identified with a kalos kai agathos man, i.e. with an individual who – rather than being driven by mere desire for the promotion (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Duty, Desire and the Good Person: Towards a Non‐Aristotelian Account of Virtue.Nomy Arpaly - 2014 - Philosophical Perspectives 28 (1):59-74.
    This paper presents an account of the virtuous person, which I take to be the same as the good person. I argue that goodness in a person is based on her desires. Contra Aristotelians, I argue that one does not need practical wisdom to be good. There can be a perfectly good person with mental retardation or autism, for example, whether or not such conditions are compatible with the Aristotelian kind of wisdom. Contra Kantians, I argue that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  45. Moral Fetishism and a Third Desire for What’s Right.Nathan Howard - 2021 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 20 (3).
    A major point of debate about morally good motives concerns an ambiguity in the truism that good and strong-willed people desire to do what is right. This debate is shaped by the assumption that “what’s right” combines in only two ways with “desire,” leading to distinct de dicto and de re readings of the truism. However, a third reading of such expressions is possible, first identified by Janet Fodor, which has gone wholly unappreciated by philosophers in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46. Desire Formation and Human Good.Richard Arneson - 2006 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 59:9-32.
    In Wuthering Heights a man and a woman fall in love and their passion for each other wreaks havoc on several lives, theirs included. Long after his beloved is dead, Heathcliff’s life revolves entirely around his love for her. Frustrated by events, his grand romantic passion expresses itself in destructive spasms of antisocial behavior. Catherine, the object of this passion, marries another man on a whim, but describes her feelings for him as like superficial foliage, whereas ‘her love for Heathcliff (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  47.  98
    Ill-Being for Desire Satisfactionists.Chris Heathwood - 2022 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 46:33-54.
    Shelly Kagan notices in a recent, influential paper how philosophers of well-being tend to neglect ill-being—the part of the theory of well-being that tells us what is bad in itself for subjects—and explains why we need to give it more attention. This paper does its part by addressing the question, If desire satisfaction is good, what is the corresponding bad? The two most discussed ill-being options for theories on which desire satisfaction is a basic good are (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48. Locke, suspension of desire, and the remote good.Tito Magri - 2000 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 8 (1):55 – 70.
    The chapter 'Of power' of Locke's Essay Concerning Human Understanding is a very fine discussion of agency and a very complex piece of philosophy. It is the result of the superimposition of at least three layers of text (those of the first, second and fifth editions of the Essay), expressive of widely differing views of the same matters. The argument concerning agency and free will that it puts forward (as it now stands, reporting Locke's last word on the subject) is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  49.  25
    Good Reasons for Acting: Towards Human Flourishing.Giulia Codognato - forthcoming - Argumenta.
    The aim of this paper is to show that if and only if agents are motivated to act by good reasons for acting, they flourish, since, in so doing, they consciously act in accordance with their nature through virtuous actions. I offer an account of what good reasons for acting consist of reconsidering Aquinas’ natural inclinations. Based on a critical analysis of Anjum and Mumford’s work on dispositions in analytic metaphysics, I argue, contra Hume’s law, that Aquinas’ natural (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  35
    Respect for autonomy: deciding what is good for oneself.Brent Michael Kious - 2016 - Journal of Medical Ethics 42 (12):769-775.
    Paternalistic interference in autonomous decisions is typically impermissible. This has several explanations, among which is a view I call theagent-constitution of the good: that the autonomous agent not onlyknowswhat is best for herself, butdetermineswhat is best for herself through her desires, goals and so on (heraims). For instance, it might seem that if an autonomous person does choose not to take insulin for her diabetes, then not only is it inappropriate to force treatment upon her, it is also not (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 980