Results for 'Slaves of the Passions'

979 found
Order:
  1. Slaves of the passions * by mark Schroeder.Mark Schroeder - 2009 - Analysis 69 (3):574-576.
    Like much in this book, the title and dust jacket illustration are clever. The first evokes Hume's remark in the Treatise that ‘Reason is, and ought only to be the slave of the passions.’ The second, which represents a cross between a dance-step and a clinch, links up with the title and anticipates an example used throughout the book to support its central claims: that Ronnie, unlike Bradley, has a reason to go to a party – namely, that there (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   421 citations  
  2. Slaves of the passions.Mark Schroeder - 2007 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Long claimed to be the dominant conception of practical reason, the Humean theory that reasons for action are instrumental, or explained by desires, is the basis for a range of worries about the objective prescriptivity of morality. As a result, it has come under intense attack in recent decades. A wide variety of arguments have been advanced which purport to show that it is false, or surprisingly, even that it is incoherent. Slaves of the Passions aims to set (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   471 citations  
  3. Slaves of the Passions (review). [REVIEW]Melissa Barry - 2010 - Hume Studies 36 (2):225-228.
    In Slaves of the Passions, Mark Schroeder provides a systematic, rigorously argued defense of a Humean theory of reasons for action, taking pains to respond to influential objections to the view. While inspired by Hume, Schroeder makes it clear that he aims to develop a Humean theory, not necessarily one that Hume himself embraced, and for this reason little is said about Hume in the book. One respect in which Schroeder takes himself to be departing from Hume is (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  4.  71
    Reviews slaves of the passions . By mark Schroeder. Oxford university press, 2007, pp. IX + 224, £34.A. W. Price - 2009 - Philosophy 84 (2):291-295.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Précis of Slaves of the Passions[REVIEW]Mark Schroeder - 2012 - Philosophical Studies 157 (3):431-434.
    Précis of Slaves of the Passions Content Type Journal Article DOI 10.1007/s11098-010-9658-1 Authors Mark Schroeder, University of Southern California, Los Angeles, CA USA Journal Philosophical Studies Online ISSN 1573-0883 Print ISSN 0031-8116.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6. On Mark Schroeder's Hypotheticalism: A Critical Notice of Slaves of the Passions.David Enoch - 2011 - Philosophical Review 120 (3):423-446.
    In Slaves of the Passions Mark Schroeder puts forward Hypotheticalism, his version of a Humean theory of normative reasons that is capable, so he argues, to avoid many of the difficulties Humeanism is traditionally vulnerable to. In this critical notice, I first outline the main argument of the book, and then proceed to highlight some difficulties and challenges. I argue that these challenges show that Schroeder's improvements on traditional Humeanism – while they do succeed in making the view (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  7. Slaves of the passions? On Schroeder's new humeanism. [REVIEW]Alex Gregory - 2009 - Ratio 22 (2):250-257.
  8.  79
    Slaves of the Passions. By Mark Schroeder. (Oxford UP, 2007. Pp. 224. Price US$85.00.).James Lenman - 2013 - Philosophical Quarterly 63 (251):384-387.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9. Slaves of the passions * by mark Schroeder. [REVIEW]M. Alvarez - 2009 - Analysis 69 (3):574-576.
    Like much in this book, the title and dust jacket illustration are clever. The first evokes Hume's remark in the Treatise that ‘Reason is, and ought only to be the slave of the passions.’ The second, which represents a cross between a dance-step and a clinch, links up with the title and anticipates an example used throughout the book to support its central claims: that Ronnie, unlike Bradley, has a reason to go to a party – namely, that there (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10. Review of mark Schroeder, Slaves of the Passions[REVIEW]David Sobel - 2009 - Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2009 (4).
    I assess Schroeder's book Slaves of the Passions and isolate some grounds for concerns about the overall position.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Response to Mark Schroeder’s Slaves of the passions[REVIEW]Jonathan Dancy - 2012 - Philosophical Studies 157 (3):455-462.
    Response to Mark Schroeder’s Slaves of the passions Content Type Journal Article DOI 10.1007/s11098-010-9656-3 Authors Jonathan Dancy, The University of Reading, Reading, UK Journal Philosophical Studies Online ISSN 1573-0883 Print ISSN 0031-8116.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12.  86
    Slaves of the Passions (Mark Schroeder).Oxford: Oxford University Press. [REVIEW]Bradford Cokelet - 2009 - Ethics 119 (2):386-389.
  13. Can we be free if reason is the slave of the passions?Frank van Dun - unknown
    The writings of David Hume (1711–1776) are a treasure trove for those eager to find pithy, polished memorable quotes to bolster their arguments in favor of freedom, justice, and against the arrogance and follies of governments. It is difficult to resist the youthful élan of his major philosophical work, A Treatise of Human Nature (1739–1740), his provocative ironic style, witticisms, irreverence, and occasional sarcasm, which made him an international celebrity, the darling of Parisian salons, and, even now, a reader’s delight.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  19
    On Schroeder's chapter 10 in Slaves of the Passion.Toni Rønnow-Rasmussen - unknown
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. The Master of the Passions? An Examination of the Role of Reason in Action.Paul Griseri - 1988 - Dissertation, University of Kent at Canterbury (United Kingdom)
    Available from UMI in association with The British Library. ;Is reason the slave of the passions? In Part I it is argued that neither the humean nor the kantian answers to this question can be maintained simpliciter. Each side of the controversy has to make significant concessions to the other. One consequence of this is that humean and kantian approaches to action are less clearly distinguished than might initially be supposed. ;In Part II several central notions are examined. The (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  63
    Review of Mark Schroeder's 'Slaves of the Passions'. [REVIEW]Maria Alvarez - unknown
  17.  42
    Reason, Passion, and Action: The Third Condition of the Voluntary.T. D. J. Chappell - 1995 - Philosophy 70 (273):453 - 459.
    1. ‘Reason is and ought only to be the slave of the passions, and can pretend to no other office, but to serve and obey them.’ 2.3.3) Unfortunately, Hume uses ‘reason’ to mean ‘discovery of truth or falsehood‘ as well as discovery of logical relations. So suppose we avoid, as Hume I think does not, prejudging the question of how many ingredients are requisite for action, by separating these two claims out: A. Reason is and ought only to be (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  94
    Not passion's slave: Emotions and choice, by Robert C. Solomon and from passions to emotions: The creation of a secular psychological category, by Thomas Dixon.Peter Goldie - 2007 - European Journal of Philosophy 15 (1):106–110.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  13
    Schopenhauer's Philosophy of the Dark Origin.William Desmond - 2011 - In Bart Vandenabeele (ed.), A Companion to Schopenhauer. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 87–104.
    This chapter contains sections titled: 1 2 3 4 5 6 Notes References Further Reading.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  29
    Twilight of the Vampires: History and the Myth of the Undead.Matthew Kratter - 1998 - Contagion: Journal of Violence, Mimesis, and Culture 5 (1):30-45.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:TWILIGHT OF THE VAMPIRES: HISTORY AND THE MYTH OF THE UNDEAD Matthew Kratter University ofCalifornia Berkeley "Whoever fights monsters should see to it that in the process he does not become a monster." (Nietzsche, Beyond Good andEvil, IV, 146) One ofthe most satisfying parts ofan extended engagement with the mimetic theory is the bird's-eye view of history that it affords one—that magnificently coherent panorama which stretches from proto-hominids through (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. (1 other version)Prospects for a naturalization of practical reason: Humean instrumentalism and the normative authority of desire.Robert Audi - 2002 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 10 (3):235 – 263.
    This is an age of naturalization projects. Much epistemological work has been done toward naturalizing theoretical reason. One might view Hume as seeking to naturalize reason in both the theoretical (roughly, epistemological) and the practical realms. I suggest that whatever else underlies the vitality of Hume's instrumentalism - encapsulated in his view that 'reason is and ought only to be the slave of the passions' - one incentive is the hope of naturalizing practical reason. This paper explores some broadly (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  22. “Yes, the theory is abstemious, but...”: A Critique of Yehezkel.Regan Lance Reitsma - 2017 - European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 13 (1):59-79.
    This article is a critique of Gal Yehezkel’s attempt to refute subjectivism about normative practical reasons, a school of thought inspired by Hume. Yehezkel believes reason, far from being, as Hume puts it, “the slave of the passions,” has the normative authority to be a critic of basic desires and argues that subjectivism lacks the theoretical resources both to acknowledge this alleged truth and to analyze the distinction between wanting an outcome and intending to pursue it. I contend his (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  27
    Not Passion’s Slave.Nico H. Frijda - 2010 - Emotion Review 2 (1):68-75.
    Bob Solomon claimed that we are not passion’s slaves. I examine whether or not we are, considering universal determinism. I argue that we indeed are free, or at least that we can be, and try to understand this. Free will resides in the presence of alternative action options, in our ability to freely search for, detect, or create them, in our ability to use them, and in our ability to, in some measure, free ourselves from the automatic impact of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24. Not Passion’s Slave: Emotions and Choice.Robert C. Solomon - 2003 - New York, US: Oup Usa.
    This volume collects thirty years worth of articles on the emotions written by the distinguished philosopher Robert Solomon. Solomon's thesis is that we are significantly responsible for our emotions, which are evaluative judgments that in effect we choose. This is the first of several volumes that document work in the emotions.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  25.  9
    Cartesian Imaginations: The Method and Passions of Imagining.Dennis L. Sepper - 2005 - In Alan Jean Nelson (ed.), A Companion to Rationalism. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 156–176.
    This chapter contains sections titled: The Status of the Rationalist Image The Deeper Background Descartes: The Directed Imagination of Mathematics, and Passions as Nascent Images Malebranche Conclusion.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  28
    The Monstrosity of Vice: Sin and Slavery in Campanella’s Political Thought.Brian Garcia - 2020 - Aither: Journal for the Study of Greek and Latin Philosophical Traditions 12 (2):232–248.
    This paper opens by reviewing Aristotle’s conception of the natural slave and then familiar treatments of the internal conflict between the ruling and subject parts of the soul in Aristotle and Plato; I highlight especially the figurative uses of slavery and servitude when discussing such problems pertaining to incontinence and vice—viz., being a ‘slave’ to the passions. Turning to Campanella, features of the City of the Sun pertaining to slavery are examined: in sketching his ideal city, Campanella both rejects (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  25
    Reading Hume on the Principles of Morals ed. by Taylor Jacqueline.Philip A. Reed - 2021 - Hume Studies 44 (2):278-280.
    Readers of this journal know that Hume regarded an Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals as his finest work. It was, Hume said, "incomparably the best." Yet, most of the scholarly work on Hume's moral philosophy in recent decades focuses on the Treatise, which Hume wrote some three decades prior to the Enquiry.There are good reasons to focus on the older work. It is much longer, so there is more to sink our scholarly teeth into. Many discussions and discursions appear (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Hypotheticalism and the objectivity of morality.Kelly Heuer - manuscript
    Mark Schroeder’s Slaves of the Passions defends a version of the Humean Theory of Reasons he calls “Hypotheticalism,” according to which all reasons an agent has for action are explained by desires that are in turn explained by reference to her psychology. This paper disputes Schroeder’s claim that his theory has the potential to allay long-standing worries about moral objectivity and normativity within a Humean framework because it fails to attain the requisite level of agent-neutrality for moral reasons. (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. In Defence of Proportionalism.Daan Evers - 2014 - European Journal of Philosophy 22 (2):313-320.
    In his book Slaves of the Passions, Mark Schroeder defends a Humean theory of reasons. Humeanism is the view that you have a reason to X only if X‐ing promotes at least one of your desires. But Schroeder rejects a natural companion theory of the weight of reasons, which he calls proportionalism. According to it, the weight of a reason is proportionate to the strength of the desire that grounds it and the extent to which the act promotes (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  30.  70
    “The Monstrous Centaur”? Joseph de Maistre on Reason, Passion and Violence.Douglas Hedley - 2011 - Faith and Philosophy 28 (1):71-81.
    This essay remarks upon a seeming paradox in the philosophical anthropology of Joseph de Maistre (1753–1821). He presents a traditional Platonic asymmetry of reason and the passions. This is put to the service of an Origenistic-universalistic theology that revolves around questions of guilt, punishment and redemption and a theory of sacrifice. Maistre is far from being the irrationalist that many political theorists observe, even if he presents an antagonistic relationship between reason and passions, the rational self and its (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Desire: Its Role in Practical Reason and the Explanation of Action.G. F. Schueler - 1995 - MIT Press.
    Does action always arise out of desire? G. F. Schueler examines this hotly debated topic in philosophy of action and moral philosophy, arguing that once two senses of "desire" are distinguished - roughly, genuine desires and pro attitudes - apparently plausible explanations of action in terms of the agent's desires can be seen to be mistaken. Desire probes a fundamental issue in philosophy of mind, the nature of desires and how, if at all, they motivate and justify our actions. At (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  32.  18
    Eminence of the Mind over the Body.Belko Ouologueme & Yacouba Coulibaly - 2019 - Open Journal of Philosophy 9 (3):281-294.
    The mind-body problem is far to be an old issue because it keeps rising new understanding and perception without ceasing. In the contemporary philosophy of mind, the essence of the question should not be any more whether there is a distinction between mind and body. Rather philosophers should be more focused on the interaction between mind and body. The new interest is how does it happen? This article argues the eminence of the mind over the body. Mind-body interaction is not (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  52
    Aquinas on the Role of Emotion in Moral Judgment and Activity.Judith Barad - 1991 - The Thomist 55 (3):397-413.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:AQUINAS ON THE ROLE OF EMOTION IN MORAL JUDGMENT AND ACTIVITY JUDITH BARAD Indiana State University Terre Haute, Indiana MONG PHILOSOPHERS who have discussed the role of emotion in morality there is much disagreement. At one extreme there is a tradition of ethical thinkers, represented by David Hume, who juxtapose reason and emotion and hoM that the choice of ultimate va:1ues is always made by the emotional side of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34.  15
    Vita passibilis, imperturbatio (apatheia), vita passiva: The Passive Condition of Man in the Theological Thought of Maximus the Confessor.Picu Ocoleanu - 2023 - Diakrisis Yearbook of Theology and Philosophy 6:67-77.
    Maximus the Confessor distinguishes three stages in the spiritual becoming of man: vita passibilis i.e. the way of life in that man is living under the reign of the bodily passions, apatheia as state of liberation from the reign of the lower passions, and vita passiva as modus vivendi in which the human makes the personal experience of the revelation and the presence of God. Thereby being man means according to Maximus suffering under the rule of someone - (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  6
    “And so with the moderns”: The Role of the Revolutionary Writer and the Mythicization of History in J. Leslie Mitchell’s Spartacus.Scott Lyall - 2022 - Clotho 4 (2):127-152.
    The focus of this article is J. Leslie Mitchell’s Spartacus (1933), his fictional representation of the slave rebellion in ancient Rome led by the eponymous gladiator. The article begins by examining Mitchell’s contribution to debates over the role of the revolutionary writer in Left Review in the mid-1930s and his place in the British Left in this era, before going on to survey the ways in which the figure of Spartacus and the German Spartacists are represented across Mitchell’s oeuvre. It (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Not Passion’s Slave: Emotions and Choice. [REVIEW]Kevin E. O'Reilly - 2006 - Review of Metaphysics 59 (4):903-904.
    Since the appearance of his earliest works on the subject of the emotions, namely, his article “Emotions and Choice” in 1973 and his book The Passions in 1976, Robert C. Solomon has never ceased to develop the idea that we are in some significant sense and to some significant degree responsible for our emotions. His presentation of this thesis in these two works was, on his own admission, somewhat polemical and stood in need of considerable revision. This present volume, (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  32
    Not Passion’s Slave. [REVIEW]Kevin E. O’Reilly - 2006 - Review of Metaphysics 59 (4):903-904.
    Since the appearance of his earliest works on the subject of the emotions, namely, his article “Emotions and Choice” in 1973 and his book The Passions in 1976, Robert C. Solomon has never ceased to develop the idea that we are in some significant sense and to some significant degree responsible for our emotions. His presentation of this thesis in these two works was, on his own admission, somewhat polemical and stood in need of considerable revision. This present volume, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  18
    Why Why Liberalism Failed Fails as an Account of the American Order.Paul R. DeHart - 2019 - Catholic Social Science Review 24:19-31.
    In Why Liberalism Failed, Patrick Deneen contends that the American founding is fundamentally Hobbesian and that the Constitution is the application of the Hobbesian revolution concerning liberty and anthropology. I contend that Deneen fundamentally mischaracterizes the American founding. The founders and framers affirmed the necessity of consent for political authority and obligation. But they also situated the necessity of consent in the context of a morally and metaphysically realist natural law, maintained that an objective good of the whole constitutes the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Reason in Hume’s Passions.Nathan Brett & Katharina Paxman - 2008 - Hume Studies 34 (1):43-59.
    Hume is famous for the view that “reason is, and ought only to be, the slave of the passions.” His claim that “we are no sooner acquainted with the impossibility of satisfying any desire, than the desire itself vanishes” is less well known. Each seems, in opposite ways, shocking to common sense. This paper explores the latter claim, looking for its source in Hume’s account of the passions and exploring its compatibility with his associationist psychology. We are led (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40. David Hume on Reason, Passions and Morals.A. T. Nuyen - 1984 - Hume Studies 10 (1):26-45.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:26. DAVID HUME ON REASON, PASSIONS AND MORALS Perhaps the most notorious passage in Hume's Treatise is the one that concerns the relative roles of reason and passions, where he says: Reason is, and ought only to be the slave of the passions (T 415). This psychology of action is the foundation of Hume's moral theory, wherein we find his two other notorious dicta, one being!.¡oral (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  89
    Reason Over Passion: The Social Basis of Evaluation and Appraisal.Evan Simpson - 1979 - Waterloo, Ont.: Wilfrid Laurier Press.
    "Reason is not passion's slave." Rather, the author argues, reason appraises the cultural appropriateness of passion, thus directing our attitudinal behaviour. He refutes those theories of value which correspond philosophically to societies described by Jean-Jacques Rousseau: societies of "honour without virtue, reason without wisdom, pleasure without happiness." His argument, which takes into account traditional philosophic positions, is divided into five parts: Attitudes, Evaluation, Characterization, Culture, Morality.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Direction of Fit.G. F. Schueler - 2013 - In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Hoboken, NJ: Blackwell.
    The difference between cognitive and conative mental states, such as beliefs and desires, has sometimes been held to be that they have different “directions of fit” between the mind and the world – mind-to-world for beliefs and world-to-mind for desires (see Desire). Some philosophers have pursued the idea that if this thought can be given a plausible explanation it can be used to ground Hume's claim that “reason is the slave of the passions,” i.e., that no moral or other (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  11
    The nature and tendency of free institutions.Frederick Grimké - 1848 - Cambridge,: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. Edited by John William Ward.
    First published in 1848, Frederick Grimke's book, in the words of the editor, "deserves comparison with Tocqueville's justly famous work, Democracy in America, and is in certain ways superior. It is the single best book written by an American in the nineteenth century on the meaning of our political way of life." A second edition of Grimke's work was published in 1856, and a third edition appeared posthumously in 1871, but since then this classic in American thought has been almost (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  8
    Diderot and the art of thinking freely.Andrew S. Curran - 2019 - New York: Other Press.
    A vivacious biography of the prophetic and sympathetic philosopher who along with Voltaire and Rousseau built the foundations of the modern world, and travelled as far as Russia to enlighten the Tsarina Catherine the Great. Denis Diderot is often associated with the decades-long battle to bring the world's first comprehensive Encyclopédie into existence. But his most compelling and personal writing took place in the shadows. Thrown into prison for his atheism in 1749, Diderot decided to reserve his most daring books (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  22
    The Concept of Benevolence. [REVIEW]G. M. - 1974 - Review of Metaphysics 28 (2):355-355.
    The views of three prominent eighteenth-century moral philosophers, Francis Hutcheson, Bishop Butler, and David Hume, are critically examined in this book. Professor Roberts believes that a careful analysis of these empiricist philosophers’ views can serve as a prolegomenon to an adequate understanding of benevolence. The nature of benevolence and its role in motivating moral actions was a crucial issue in eighteenth-century moral philosophy. Some philosophers who preceded Hutcheson denied that only feelings motivated actions; and others, who defended the efficacy of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Humean agent-neutral reasons?Daan Evers - 2009 - Philosophical Explorations 12 (1):55 – 67.
    In his recent book Slaves of the Passions , Mark Schroeder defends a Humean account of practical reasons ( hypotheticalism ). He argues that it is compatible with 'genuinely agent-neutral reasons'. These are reasons that any agent whatsoever has. According to Schroeder, they may well include moral reasons. Furthermore, he proposes a novel account of a reason's weight, which is supposed to vindicate the claim that agent-neutral reasons ( if they exist), would be weighty irrespective of anyone's desires. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  47.  56
    The Pyrrhus Perplex: A Superficial View of Mimesis.Andrew J. McKenna - 1994 - Contagion: Journal of Violence, Mimesis, and Culture 1 (1):31-46.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Pyrrhus Perplex: A Superficial View of Mimesis Andrew J. McKenna Loyola University Chicago In the interest of knowledge conveyed as experience, a teacher of literature likes to begin with a story: A man sets out to discover a treasure he believes is hidden under a stone; he turns over stone after stone but finds nothing. He grows tired of such futile undertaking but the treasure is too precious (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  16
    Therapy of the Passions in Spinoza’s Ethics.현영종 ) - 2019 - Modern Philosophy 13:99-118.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Does Hume Have an Instrumental Conception of Practical Reason?Jean Hampton - 1995 - Hume Studies 21 (1):57-74.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume Studies Volume XXI, Number 1, April 1995, pp. 57-74 Does Hume Have an Instrumental Conception of Practical Reason? JEAN HAMPTON Many philosophers and social scientists regard the instrumental theory of practical reason as highly plausible, and standardly credit David Hume as the first philosopher to formulate this conception of reason clearly. Yet I will argue in this paper that Hume does not advocate the instrumental conception of practical (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  50.  47
    The Secret History of Emotion: From Aristotle's 'Rhetoric' to Modern Brain Science (review).Michael J. Hyde - 2007 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 40 (3):326-329.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:The Secret History of Emotion: From Aristotle's ‘Rhetoric’ to Modern Brain ScienceMichael J. HydeThe Secret History of Emotion: From Aristotle's ‘Rhetoric’ to Modern Brain Science. Daniel M. Gross. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2006. Pp. x + 194. $35.00, Hardcover.The twofold goal of this book is clearly stated by its author: "to reconstitute by way of critical intellectual history a deeply nuanced, rhetorical understanding of emotion that prevailed (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 979