Results for 'Reasoning about Actions'

972 found
Order:
  1.  80
    Reasoning about action and change.Helmut Prendinger & Gerhard Schurz - 1996 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 5 (2):209-245.
    Reasoning about change is a central issue in research on human and robot planning. We study an approach to reasoning about action and change in a dynamic logic setting and provide a solution to problems which are related to the Frame problem. Unlike most work on the frame problem the logic described in this paper is monotonic. It (implicitly) allows for the occurrence of actions of multiple agents by introducing non-stationary notions of waiting and test. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  2.  14
    Reasoning about action II.Matthew L. Ginsberg & David E. Smith - 1988 - Artificial Intelligence 35 (3):311-342.
  3.  18
    Reasoning about actions in dynamic linear time temporal logic.L. Giordano, A. Martelli & C. Schwind - 2001 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 9 (2):273-288.
    In this paper we present a theory for reasoning about actions which is based on Dynamic Linear Time Temporal Logic . DLTL is a simple extension of propositional temporal logic of linear time in which regular programs of propositional dynamic logic can be used for indexing temporal modalities. The action theory we define allows to reason with incomplete initial states, to do postdiction and to deal with ramifications and with nondeterministic actions, which are captured by possibly (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  15
    Reasoning about action I.Matthew L. Ginsberg & David E. Smith - 1988 - Artificial Intelligence 35 (2):165-195.
  5.  64
    Reasoning about actions and obligations in first-order logic.Gert -Jan C. Lokhorst - 1996 - Studia Logica 57 (1):221 - 237.
    We describe a new way in which theories about the deontic status of actions can be represented in terms of the standard two-sorted first-order extensional predicate calculus. Some of the resulting formal theories are easy to implement in Prolog; one prototype implementation—R. M. Lee's deontic expert shell DX—is briefly described.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  10
    Reasoning about action in polynomial time.Thomas Drakengren & Marcus Bjäreland - 1999 - Artificial Intelligence 115 (1):1-24.
  7.  49
    Reasoning about Actions and Obligations in First-Order Logic.Gert-Jan C. Lokhorst - 1996 - Studia Logica 57 (1):221 - 237.
    We describe a new way in which theories about the deontic status of actions can be represented in terms of the standard two-sorted extensional predicate calculus. Some of the resulting formal theories are easy to implement in Prolog; one prototype implementation--R. M. Lee's deontic expert shell DX--is briefly described.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  8.  7
    Reasoning about actions: steady versus stabilizing state constraints.Michael Thielscher - 1998 - Artificial Intelligence 104 (1-2):339-355.
  9.  42
    Reasoning about actions and change in argumentation.E. Hadjisoteriou & A. Kakas - 2015 - Argument and Computation 6 (3):265-291.
    Volume 6, Issue 3, September 2015, Page 265-291.
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10. A Decidable Multi-agent Logic for Reasoning About Actions, Instruments, and Norms.Kees van Berkel, Tim Lyon & Francesco Olivieri - 1996 - In Johan van Benthem (ed.), Logic and argumentation. New York: North-Holland. pp. 219 - 241.
    We formally introduce a novel, yet ubiquitous, category of norms: norms of instrumentality. Norms of this category describe which actions are obligatory, or prohibited, as instruments for certain purposes. We propose the Logic of Agency and Norms (LAN) that enables reasoning about actions, instrumentality, and normative principles in a multi-agent setting. Leveraging LAN , we formalize norms of instrumentality and compare them to two prevalent norm categories: norms to be and norms to do. Last, we pose (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  83
    Representation and Reasoning about Evolutions of the World in the Context of Reasoning about Actions.Chitta Baral & Nam Tran - 2005 - Studia Logica 79 (1):33-46.
    The first step in reasoning about actions and change involves reasoning about how the world would evolve if a certain action is executed in a certain state. Most research on this assumes the evolution to be only a single step and focus on formulating the transition function that defines changes between states due to actions. In this paper we consider cases where the evolution is more than just a single change between one state and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  12
    Probabilistic reasoning about epistemic action narratives.Fabio Aurelio D'Asaro, Antonis Bikakis, Luke Dickens & Rob Miller - 2020 - Artificial Intelligence 287 (C):103352.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  30
    Reasoning about Quantum Actions: A Logician's Perspective.Sonja Smets - 2013 - In Hanne Andersen, Dennis Dieks, Wenceslao J. Gonzalez, Thomas Uebel & Gregory Wheeler (eds.), New Challenges to Philosophy of Science. Springer Verlag. pp. 125--134.
  14.  68
    Reasoning about Nature in Virtue, Action and Law: The Path from Principles to Practice.Eileen C. Sweeney - 2013 - Diametros 38:175-190.
    This paper argues that the role of nature in Aquinas’s account of virtue, action and law does not require the kind of adherence to Aristotle’s ‘metaphysical biology’ that is refuted by Darwin because of the way Aquinas transforms nature as applied to a rational being and as an analogy to elucidate virtue, habit and law. Aquinas’s grounding of ethics and law in the notion of nature is also not a kind of intuitionism designed to answer all moral questions and stop (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  44
    Reasoning about ‘irrational’ actions: When intentional movements cannot be explained, the movements themselves are seen as the goal.Adena Schachner & Susan Carey - 2013 - Cognition 129 (2):309-327.
  16. Reasoning about Sensing Actions in Domains with Multi-Valued Fluents.Tran Cao Son, Phan Huy Tu & Xin Zhang - 2005 - Studia Logica 79 (1):135-160.
    In this paper, we discuss the weakness of current action languages for sensing actions with respect to modeling domains with multi-valued fluents. To address this problem, we propose a language with sensing actions and multi-valued fluents, called AMK, provide a transition function based semantics for the language, and demonstrate its use through several examples from the literature. We then define the entailment relationship between action theories and queries in AMK, denoted by ⊧AMK, and discuss some properties about (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17. Reasoning about cooperation, actions and preferences.Lena Kurzen - 2009 - Synthese 169 (2):223 - 240.
    In this paper, a logic for reasoning about coalitional power is developed which explicitly represents agents’ preferences and the actions by which the agents can achieve certain results. A complete axiomatization is given and its satisfiability problem is shown to be decidable and EXPTIME -hard.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Reasons for action, acting for reasons, and rationality.Maria Alvarez - 2018 - Synthese 195 (8):3293-3310.
    What kind of thing is a reason for action? What is it to act for a reason? And what is the connection between acting for a reason and rationality? There is controversy about the many issues raised by these questions. In this paper I shall answer the first question with a conception of practical reasons that I call ‘Factualism’, which says that all reasons are facts. I defend this conception against its main rival, Psychologism, which says that practical reasons (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  19.  18
    Reasoning about types of action and agent capabilities.C. Hartonas - 2013 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 21 (5):703-742.
  20.  13
    A commonsense language for reasoning about causation and rational action.Charles L. Ortiz - 1999 - Artificial Intelligence 111 (1-2):73-130.
  21.  38
    Reasons for action: Wittgensteinian and Davidsonian perspectives in historical and meta-philosophical context.Hans Johann Glock - unknown
    My paper reflects on the debate about reasons for action and action explanations between Wittgensteinian teleological approaches and causalist theories inspired by Davidson. After a brief discussion of similarities and differences in the philosophy of language, I sketch the prehistory and history of the controversy. I show that the conflict between Wittgenstein and Davidson revolves neither around revisionism nor around naturalism. Even in the philosophy of mind and action, Davidson is not as remote from Wittgenstein and his followers as (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Reasons for action: Internal vs. external.Stephen Finlay & Mark Schroeder - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Often, when there is a reason for you to do something, it is the kind of thing to motivate you to do it. For example, if Max and Caroline are deciding whether to go to the Alcove for dinner, Caroline might mention as a reason in favor, the fact that the Alcove serves onion rings the size of doughnuts, and Max might mention as a reason against, the fact that it is so difficult to get parking there this time of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  23. Reasons for Action: Wittgensteinian and Davidsonian perspectives in historical, meta-philosophical and philosophical context.Hans-Johann Glock - 2014 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 3 (1):7-46.
    My paper reflects on the debate about reasons for action and action explanations between Wittgensteinian teleological approaches and causalist theories inspired by Davidson. After a brief discussion of similarities and differences in the philosophy of language, I sketch the prehistory and history of the controversy. I show that the conflict between Wittgenstein and Davidson revolves neither around revisionism nor around naturalism. Even in the philosophy of mind and action, Davidson is not as remote from Wittgenstein and his followers as (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  24. Reasons for Action and Psychological Capacities.Rosemary Lowry - 2012 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 15 (4):521 - 531.
    Most moral philosophers agree that if a moral agent is incapable of performing some act ϕ because of a physical incapacity, then they do not have a reason to ϕ. Most also claim that if an agent is incapable of ϕ-ing due to a psychological incapacity, brought about by, for example, an obsession or phobia, then this does not preclude them from having a reason to ϕ. This is because the 'ought implies can' principle is usually interpreted as a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25. XV—Agents and Patients, or: What We Learn About Reasons for Action by Reflecting on Our Choices in Process‐of‐Thought Cases.Michael Smith - 2012 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 112 (3pt3):309-331.
    Can we draw substantive conclusions about the reasons for action agents have from premisses about the desires of their idealized counterparts? The answer is that we can. The argument for this conclusion is Rawlsian in spirit, focusing on the choices that our idealized counterparts must make simply in virtue of being ideal, and inferring from these choices the contents of the desires that they must have. It turns out that our idealized counterparts must have desires in which we (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  26.  42
    Representing and Reasoning about Game Strategies.Dongmo Zhang & Michael Thielscher - 2015 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 44 (2):203-236.
    As a contribution to the challenge of building game-playing AI systems, we develop and analyse a formal language for representing and reasoning about strategies. Our logical language builds on the existing general Game Description Language and extends it by a standard modality for linear time along with two dual connectives to express preferences when combining strategies. The semantics of the language is provided by a standard state-transition model. As such, problems that require reasoning about games can (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  26
    Internalism About Reasons for Action.Rachel Cohon - 1993 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 74 (4):265-288.
  28.  59
    Objectivism and Causalism About Reasons for Action.Eva Schmidt & Hans-Johann Glock - 2019 - In Gunnar Schumann (ed.), Explanation in Action Theory and Historiography: Causal and Teleological Approaches. New York: Routledge. pp. 124-145.
    This chapter explores whether a version of causalism about reasons for action can be saved by giving up Davidsonian psychologism and endorsing objectivism, so that the reasons for which we act are the normative reasons that cause our corresponding actions. We address two problems for ‘objecto-causalism’, actions for merely apparent normative reasons and actions performed in response to future normative reasons—in neither of these cases can the reason for which the agent acts cause her action. To (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29. Reason in action.John Gibbons - 2009 - In Lucy O'Brien & Matthew Soteriou (eds.), Mental actions. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 72.
    There is a problem with a very common theory of the nature of action. The problem stems from the fact that causation by practical reasons may be a necessary condition for being an intentional action, but it can’t be a sufficient condition. After all, desires and intentions are caused by practical reasons that rationalize them, but they’re clearly not actions. Even if all actions are events or changes and desires and intentions aren’t, the acquistion of a desire or (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  30. Reasons for Action.Pamela Hieronymi - 2011 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 111 (3pt3):407-427.
    Donald Davidson opens ‘Actions, Reasons, and Causes’ by asking, ‘What is the relation between a reason and an action when the reason explains the action by giving the agent's reason for doing what he did?’ His answer has generated some confusion about reasons for action and made for some difficulty in understanding the place for the agent's own reasons for acting, in the explanation of an action. I offer here a different account of the explanation of action, one (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  31.  36
    Reasoning about manipulation in multi-agent systems.Christopher Leturc & Grégory Bonnet - 2022 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 32 (2):89-155.
    Selfish, dishonest or malicious agents may find an interest in manipulating others. While many works deal with designing robust systems or manipulative strategies, few works are interested in defining in a broad sense what is a manipulation and how we can reason with such a notion. In this article, based on a social science literature, we give a general definition of manipulation for multi-agent systems. A manipulation is a deliberate effect of an agent – called manipulator – to instrumentalize another (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  22
    Reasons in Action: A Reductionist Account of Intentional Action.Ingmar Persson - 2019 - New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
    Ingmar Persson offers an original view of the processes of human action: deliberating on the basis of reasons for and against actions, making a decision about what to do, and implementing the decision in action in a way that makes the action intentional.
  33.  11
    Reasoning about nondeterministic and concurrent actions: A process algebra approach.Xiao Jun Chen & Giuseppe De Giacomo - 1999 - Artificial Intelligence 107 (1):63-98.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  31
    Thinking Like an Earthling: Children's Reasoning About Individual and Collective Action Related to Environmental Sustainability.Tina A. Grotzer & S. Lynneth Solis - 2023 - Topics in Cognitive Science 15 (3):433-451.
    Learning to accept and understand our identity as inhabitants of planet Earth is an essential aspect of living sustainably in a global community with others. What is involved in learning, that despite what divides us, we are first and foremost Earthlings and that the well-being of our planetary home is in our collective hands? What are the cognitive features of concepts that are inherent to thinking like an Earthling? This article considers themes that arise from research that inform what is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Pleasure as a reason for action.Alisdair Mac Intyre - 1965 - The Monist 49 (2):215-233.
    It is often said nowadays that to understand pleasure we must understand it as affording us a reason for or an explanation of action. It is only from the standpoint of the agent that we can avoid being misled. Both Professor Nowell-Smith and Mr. Manser have argued along these lines; and Dr. Kenny has written that “pleasure is always a reason for action” and has elucidated what he means by a footnote: “I do not mean that a thing’s being pleasant (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Entitlement to Reasons for Action.Abraham Roth - 2017 - In David Shoemaker (ed.), Oxford Studies in Agency and Responsibility Volume 4. Oxford University Press. pp. 75-92.
    The reasons for which I act are normally my reasons; I represent goal states and the means to attaining them, and these guide me in action. Can your reason ever be the reason why I act? If I haven’t yet taken up your reason and made it mine by representing it for myself, then it may seem mysterious how this could be possible. Nevertheless, the paper argues that sometimes one is entitled to another’s reason and that what one does is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  37. Consequentialism and Reasons for Action.Christopher Woodard - 2020 - In Douglas W. Portmore (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Consequentialism. New York, USA: Oup Usa. pp. 179–196.
    Consequentialist theories often neglect reasons for action. They offer theories of the rightness or the goodness of actions, or of virtue, but they typically do not include theories of reasons. However, consequentialists can give plausible accounts of reasons. This chapter examines some different ways in which such accounts might be developed, focusing on Act Consequentialism and Rule Consequentialism and on the relationship between reasons and rightness. It notes that adding claims about reasons to consequentialist theories may introduce a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  58
    How people think “if only …” about reasons for actions.Clare R. Walsh & Ruth M. J. Byrne - 2007 - Thinking and Reasoning 13 (4):461 – 483.
    When people think about how a situation might have turned out differently, they tend to imagine counterfactual alternatives to their actions. We report the results of three experiments which show that people imagine alternatives to actions differently when they know about a reason for the action. The first experiment ( n = 36) compared reason - action sequences to cause - effect sequences. It showed that people do not imagine alternatives to reasons in the way they (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  39. Group-based reasons for action.Christopher Woodard - 2003 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 6 (2):215-229.
    This article endorses a familiar, albeit controversial, argument for the existence of group-based reasons for action, but then rejects two doctrines which other advocates of such reasons usually accept. One such doctrine is the willingness requirement, which says that a group-based reason exists only if (sufficient) other members of the group in question are willing to cooperate. Thus the paper argues that there is sometimes a reason, which derives from the rationality of some group action, to play one's part unilaterally (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  40.  29
    A Unified Logical Framework for Reasoning about Deontic Properties of Actions and States.Piotr Kulicki, Robert Trypuz, Robert Craven & Marek J. Sergot - forthcoming - Logic and Logical Philosophy:1-35.
    This paper studies some normative relations that hold between actions, their preconditions and their effects, with particular attention to connecting what are often called ‘ought to be’ norms with ‘ought to do’ norms. We use a formal model based on a form of transition system called a ‘coloured labelled transition system’ (coloured LTS) introduced in a series of papers by Sergot and Craven. Those works have variously presented a formalism (an ‘action language’) nC+ for defining and computing with a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  25
    Consistency and Variation in Reasoning About Physical Assembly.William P. McCarthy, David Kirsh & Judith E. Fan - 2023 - Cognitive Science 47 (12):e13397.
    The ability to reason about how things were made is a pervasive aspect of how humans make sense of physical objects. Such reasoning is useful for a range of everyday tasks, from assembling a piece of furniture to making a sandwich and knitting a sweater. What enables people to reason in this way even about novel objects, and how do people draw upon prior experience with an object to continually refine their understanding of how to create it? (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  53
    Reasoning About Permitted Announcements.P. Balbiani & P. Seban - 2011 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 40 (4):445-472.
    We formalize what it means to have permission to say something. We adapt the dynamic logic of permission by van der Meyden (J Log Comput 6(3):465–479, 1996 ) to the case where atomic actions are public truthful announcements. We also add a notion of obligation. Our logic is an extension of the logic of public announcements introduced by Plaza ( 1989 ) with dynamic modal operators for permission and for obligation. We axiomatize the logic and show that it is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  43. Reasons in Action.Michael Pendlebury - 2013 - Philosophical Papers 42 (3):341 - 368.
    When an agent performs an action because she takes something as a reason to do so, does she take it as a normative reason for the action or as an explanatory reason? In Reasons Without Rationalism, Setiya criticizes the normative view and advances a version of the explanatory view. This paper advances a version of the normative view and shows that it is not subject to Setiya's criticisms. It also shows that Setiya's explanatory account is subject to two fatal flaws, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  15
    IV. Two Problems about Reasons for Actions.D. F. Pears - 1973 - In Roger Trigg (ed.), Agent, Action, and Reason. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 128-166.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45.  19
    Brief notes on reasons for action in Hume's Inquiries.Lucas Taufer - 2023 - Kínesis - Revista de Estudos Dos Pós-Graduandos Em Filosofia 15 (39):255-275.
    Our aim in this essay is to present some David Hume’s contributions on reasons for action’s debate. We tried to do this mainly from the discussions presented in the chapters “Of liberty and necessity”, from his An enquiry concerning human understanding, and “Of the general principles of morals” and “Concerning moral sentiment”, both from his An enquiry concerning the principles of morals. Starting from Bernard Williams' provocation in his description of what would be a “sub-Humean” model about reasons for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  13
    Brief notes on reasons for action in John Stuart Mill's utilitarian ethics.Lucas Taufer - 2022 - Pólemos - Revista de Estudantes de Filosofia da Universidade de Brasília 11 (23):141-157.
    Our aim in this essay is to make some reflections on John Stuart Mill’s utilitarian ethics’ possible contributions about the discussion on reasons for action. We tried to do this mainly exposing the arguments from the chapters “What utilitarianism is” and “Of the ultimate sanction of the principle of Utility” from his “Utilitarianism”. Our efforts for this attempt are spent at three different ways: in the first two, we tried to reconstruct the argument put forward by the Victorian philosopher (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  16
    Emotion, reason, and action in Kant.Maria Borges - 2019 - New York: Bloomsbury Academic.
    Action, reason, and causes in Kant -- Can we act without feelings? Respect, sympathy and other forms of love -- A place for affects and passion in the Kantian system -- What can Kant teach us about emotions? -- Physiology and the controlling of affects in Kant's philosophy -- Virtue as a cure for affects and passions -- The beautiful and the good: refinement as an introduction to morality -- Women and emotion -- Evil and passion -- An emotional (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  44
    Practical reasoning about knowledge states for open world planning with sensing.Tamara Babaian & James G. Schmolze - 2009 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 19 (1):7-41.
    We present a representation for reasoning and planning with an incomplete state description (open-world) called PSIPLAN-S. The presented formalism has several properties critical for application domains with a large degree of incompleteness in the state description, particularly, in domains with a large or unknown set of all objects. The formalism offers (1) considerably expressive state and goal description language, that includes limited universal quantification, (2) representation of sensing actions and knowledge goals, (3) a correct and complete state update (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  33
    Reasoning About Preference Dynamics.Fenrong Liu - 2011 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer Verlag.
    Our preferences determine how we act and think, but exactly what the mechanics are and how they work is a central cause of concern in many disciplines. This book uses techniques from modern logics of information flow and action to develop a unified new theory of what preference is and how it changes. The theory emphasizes reasons for preference, as well as its entanglement with our beliefs. Moreover, the book provides dynamic logical systems which describe the explicit triggers driving preference (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  50.  25
    O ne main topic in practical philosophy is the question of when someone has a reason for a certain action. Most philosophers agree on the necessity of a motivational and a justificatory condition, but they still disagree about how these conditions can be fulfilled. Though these conditions are important in forming convincing concepts of practical. [REVIEW]Kirsten B. Endres & Practical Reasons - 2003 - In Peter Schaber & Rafael Hüntelmann (eds.), Grundlagen der Ethik. De Gruyter. pp. 1--67.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 972