Results for 'Prohibition'

973 found
Order:
  1.  35
    From Prohibition to Permission: The Winding Road of Medical Assistance in Dying in Canada.Jocelyn Downie - 2022 - HEC Forum 34 (4):321-354.
    In this paper, I offer a personal and professional narrative of how Canada went from prohibition to permission for medical assistance in dying. I describe the legal developments to date and flag what might be coming in the near future. I also offer some personal observations and reflections on the role and impact of bioethics and bioethicists, on what it was like to be a participant in Canada's law reform process, and on lessons that readers in other jurisdictions might (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  2.  18
    The Prohibition Against Psychologizing.Robert L. Campbell - 2015 - Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 15 (1):53-66.
    The prohibition against psychologizing has been a source of confusion to many Randians. Psychologizing is the practice of incorrectly or improperly inferring motives in other people instead of rendering moral judgment. Rand thought that it could manifest in two ways: inquisitorial and excuse-making. However, Rand's concrete examples are preponderantly of the excuse-making type; her bright line between psychology and philosophy is unsuccessfully drawn; and in offering extended, strongly condemnatory analyses of the supposed motives behind psychologizing, she yields to the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  3.  29
    Prohibitive Voice as a Moral Act: The Role of Moral Identity, Leaders, and Workgroups.Salar Mesdaghinia, Debra L. Shapiro & Robert Eisenberger - 2021 - Journal of Business Ethics 180 (1):297-311.
    Employees’ may view prohibitive voice—that is, expressing concerns about harmful practices in the workplace—as a moral yet interpersonally risky behavior. We, thus, predict that prohibitive voice is likely to be influenced by variables associated with moral and relational qualities. Specifically, we hypothesize that employees’ moral identity internalization—i.e., the centrality of moral traits in their self-concept—is positively associated with their use of prohibitive voice. Furthermore, we hypothesize that this association is stronger when employees enjoy a higher quality relationship with their leader. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4. Crime, prohibition, and punishment.R. A. Duff - 2002 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 19 (2):97–108.
    Nigel Walker’s first principle of criminalization declares that ‘Prohibitions should not be included in the criminal law for the sole purpose of ensuring that breaches of them are visited with retributive punishment’. I argue that we should reject this principle, for ‘mala prohibita’ as well as for ‘mala in se’: conduct should be criminalized in order to ensure (as far as we reasonably can) that those who engage in it receive retributive punishment. In the course of the argument, I show (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  5.  87
    Prohibition or Coffee Shops: Regulation of Amphetamine and Methylphenidate for Enhancement Use by Healthy Adults.Veljko Dubljević - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (7):23-33.
    This article analyzes appropriate public policies for enhancement use of two most important stimulant drugs: Ritalin (methylphenidate) and Adderall (mixed amphetamine salts). The author argues that appropriate regulation of cognition enhancement drugs cannot be a result of a general discussion on cognitive enhancements as such, but has to be made on a case-by-case basis. Starting from the recently proposed taxation approach to cognition enhancement drugs, the author analyzes available, moderately permissive models of regulation. After a thorough analysis of relevant characteristics (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  6.  30
    Why Prohibiting Donor Compensation Can Prevent Plasma Donors from Giving Their Informed Consent to Donate.James Stacey Taylor - 2019 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 44 (1):10-32.
    In recent years, there has been a considerable increase in the degree of philosophical attention devoted to the question of the morality of offering financial compensation in an attempt to increase the medical supply of human body parts and products, such as plasma. This paper will argue not only that donor compensation is ethically acceptable, but that plasma donors should not be prohibited from being offered compensation if they are to give their informed consent to donate. Regulatory regimes that prohibit (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7.  6
    Prohibitions and Special Obligations.Brad Hooker - 2000 - In Ideal Code, Real World: A Rule-Consequentialist Theory of Morality. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    We typically think that morality prohibits certain kinds of behaviour, such as killing the innocent, stealing, breaking promises, etc. This chapter explores rule‐consequentialism's ability to underwrite these prohibitions, and, in particular, to underwrite our views about when such prohibitions should be amended or overridden. Argues against absolute prohibitions and explores the role of judgement in rule‐consequentialism. The final section explains how rule‐consequentialism can endorse rules giving agents special obligations towards family and friends.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Obligations and prohibitions in Talmudic deontic logic.M. Abraham, D. M. Gabbay & U. Schild - 2011 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 19 (2-3):117-148.
    This paper examines the deontic logic of the Talmud. We shall find, by looking at examples, that at first approximation we need deontic logic with several connectives: O T A Talmudic obligation F T A Talmudic prohibition F D A Standard deontic prohibition O D A Standard deontic obligation. In classical logic one would have expected that deontic obligation O D is definable by $O_DA \equiv F_D\neg A$ and that O T and F T are connected by $O_TA (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  9.  27
    Prohibition-Era Aristotelianism: Parisian Theologians and the Four Causes.Spencer E. Young - 2011 - Bulletin de Philosophie Medievale 53:41 - 59.
    In this essay, I examine the reception and use of Aristotle’s four causes by twelfth- and thirteenth-century Latin Christian theologians, primarily at Paris. I pay special attention to the early thirteenth century, when Aristotle’s works on natural philosophy were officially prohibited in the French capital. By looking at a wide range of texts from both prominent and obscure theologians, I hope to contribute to an expanded view of the ways in which intellectuals in the Latin west received and appropriated Aristotle’s (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  28
    Prohibited Risks and Culpable Disregard or Inattentiveness: Challenge and Confusion in the Formulation of Risk-Creation Offenses.Paul H. Robinson - 2003 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 4 (1).
    Because they track the Model Penal Code, current criminal law formulations of risk offenses typically fail to distinguish the rule of conduct question—What risks does the criminal law prohibit?—from the adjudication question — When is a particular violator’s conscious disregard of, or his inattentiveness to, a risk in a particular situation sufficiently condemnable to deserve criminal liability? Instead, the formulations address only the second question — through their definition of reckless and negligent culpability — and fail to provide a rule (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  11. (1 other version)Against Prohibition (Or, When Using Ordinal Scales to Compare Groups Is OK).Cristian Larroulet Philippi - forthcoming - The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.
    There is a widely held view on measurement inferences, that goes back to Stevens’s ([1946]) theory of measurement scales and ‘permissible statistics’. This view defends the following prohibition: you should not make inferences from averages taken with ordinal scales (versus quantitative scales: interval or ratio). This prohibition is general—it applies to all ordinal scales—and it is sometimes endorsed without qualification. Adhering to it dramatically limits the research that the social and biomedical sciences can conduct. I provide a Bayesian (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  21
    Prohibition and Taste.Roger Burggraeve - 1994 - Ethical Perspectives 1 (3):130-144.
    John-Paul II’s encyclical Veritatis Splendor examines the commandments, in particular the Decalogue. In so far as it is the expression of ‘natural law’ applicable and reflexively accessible to all, it is a permanent charter not only of Christian inspired ethics but of every human ethic . Using the story of the rich young man, cited in the encyclical’s first chapter, we would like to elucidate in the first part, and in our own way, how prohibitions open the way for freedom (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. "A prohibition does not apply to a prohibition": A philosophical inquiry into the nature of halakhic laws.Israel J. Cohen - 2022 - Dine Israel 37:71-107.
    Halakha consists of a variety of laws that determine the halakhic status of various actions. Halakhic laws, by their very nature, have a general aspect in that they apply to all similar actions under similar conditions. In this paper, I examine, from a philosophical-analytical point of view, the relationship between the general aspect of the halakhic laws and the fact that these laws apply to particular actions. After the introduction, this paper is divided into three parts. First, I distinguish between (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  41
    Fear, Prohibition, and Liberty.Jeffrey Obler - 1981 - Political Theory 9 (1):65-80.
  15.  34
    Reexamining the Prohibition of Gestational Surrogacy in Sunni Islam.Ruaim A. Muaygil - 2016 - Developing World Bioethics 17 (2):112-120.
    Advances in reproductive medicine have provided new, and much needed, hope for millions of people struggling with infertility. Gestational surrogacy is one such development that has been gaining popularity with infertile couples, especially those unable to benefit from other reproductive procedures such as In Vitro Fertilization. For many Muslim couples, however, surrogacy remains a nonviable option. Islamic scholars have deemed the procedure incompatible with Islam and have prohibited its use. This paper examines the arguments presented for proscribing surrogacy arrangements in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16.  37
    More Prohibitions in Greek.H. Darnley Naylor - 1906 - The Classical Review 20 (07):348-.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  16
    The Prohibition of Torture in Exceptional Circumstances.Michelle Farrell - 2013 - Cambridge University Press.
    Can torture be justified in exceptional circumstances? In this timely work, Michelle Farrell asks how and why this question has become such a central debate. She argues that the ticking bomb scenario is a fiction which blinds us to the reality of torture and investigates what it is that that scenario fails to represent. Farrell aims to reframe how we think about torture, and critically reflects on the historical and contemporary approaches to its use in exceptional situations. She demonstrates how (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  89
    Can patents prohibit research? On the social epistemology of patenting and licensing in science.Justin B. Biddle - 2014 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 45:14-23.
    A topic of growing importance within philosophy of science is the epistemic implications of the organization of research. This paper identifies a promising approach to social epistemology—nonideal systems design—and uses it to examine one important aspect of the organization of research, namely the system of patenting and licensing and its role in structuring the production and dissemination of knowledge. The primary justification of patenting in science and technology is consequentialist in nature. Patenting should incentivize research and thereby promote the development (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  19.  47
    Identifying prohibition norms in agent societies.Bastin Tony Roy Savarimuthu, Stephen Cranefield, Maryam A. Purvis & Martin K. Purvis - 2013 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 21 (1):1 - 46.
    In normative multi-agent systems, the question of “how an agent identifies norms in an open agent society” has not received much attention. This paper aims at addressing this question. To this end, this paper proposes an architecture for norm identification for an agent. The architecture is based on observation of interactions between agents. This architecture enables an autonomous agent to identify prohibition norms in a society using the prohibition norm identification (PNI) algorithm. The PNI algorithm uses association rule (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  9
    Prohibition on the Obligation to Disclose One’s Worldview, Religious Beliefs, or Religion in the Light of Article 53(7) of the Constitution of The Republic of Poland of April 2, 1997. [REVIEW]Michał Ożóg - 2021 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 66 (2):243-265.
    The aim of this article is to present the normative content of article 53 clause 7 of the Constitution of the Republic of Poland of 2nd April 1997. The paper presents the subjective scope of the regulation, including the scope of subjects who enjoy the guarantee of the “right to silence” as well as the list of addressees of the prohibition. The analysis also presents the subjective scope of article 53 paragraph 7 of the Constitution, together with an indication (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  26
    A Prohibition Without a Purpose? Laws That Are Not Norms?: A Rejoinder to Professor Boyle.John T. Noonan - 1982 - American Journal of Jurisprudence 27 (1):14-16.
    Consider a familiar case. A sign reads, “No vehicles in the park.” A man in the park has a heart attack. An ambulance is needed. Does its entry violate the rule? Most people would say that the rule was not meant to apply to needed ambulances. It would not make any difference if the rule read, “No vehicles whatsoever in the park.” The purpose of any rule against vehicles would not be served by a flat prohibition of ambulances. Consider (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  30
    Prohibition in Greek.R. C. Seaton - 1906 - The Classical Review 20 (09):438-.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  37
    Criminal Prohibition of Wrongful Re‑identification: Legal Solution or Minefield for Big Data?Mark Phillips, Edward S. Dove & Bartha M. Knoppers - 2017 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 14 (4):527-539.
    The collapse of confidence in anonymization as a robust approach for preserving the privacy of personal data has incited an outpouring of new approaches that aim to fill the resulting trifecta of technical, organizational, and regulatory privacy gaps left in its wake. In the latter category, and in large part due to the growth of Big Data–driven biomedical research, falls a growing chorus of calls for criminal and penal offences to sanction wrongful re-identification of “anonymized” data. This chorus cuts across (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24. Prohibition and transgression.George Kateb - 2008 - In David Campbell & Morton Schoolman (eds.), The New Pluralism: William Connolly and the Contemporary Global Condition. Durham: Duke University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Transgression and prohibition (Bataille's version).J. Bystricky - 2004 - Filozofia 59 (5):343-355.
    Bataille's version of transgression and prohibition is based on two presuppositions: the first one is coupling of death and ecstasy on the level of energetic principle, which makes the combination of personally grounded experience of transcendence with the dispositions of the subject possible. The second one concerns making use of two existential forces: the will to survival and the will to transcendence. The counterbalance of life and its negation is the basis for understanding and identification of the social function (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  31
    Tobacco: Prohibition, Coffee Shops, or Discouragement?Yvette van der Eijk - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (7):51-53.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  7
    Prohibition de la drogue : Diagnostic et solutions.Bertrand Lemennicier - 1992 - Journal des Economistes Et des Etudes Humaines 3 (4):493-522.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  51
    Abortion: Prohibitions and Exceptions.Sheelagh McGuinness - 2009 - American Journal of Bioethics 9 (8):70-72.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  22
    The Prohibition of Meat and Milk Mixing in the Same Meal: A Brief Theological and Medical Approach to a Jewish Dietary Law.Elias E. Mazokopakis - 2023 - European Journal of Theology and Philosophy 3 (1):19-21.
    According to Jewish dietary laws, known as Kashrut, the meat and milk mixing in the same meal is prohibited. This article examines this prohibition from a theological and modern medical viewpoint.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  23
    Kidney Donors' Interests and the Prohibition on Sales.Luke Semrau - 2023 - Bioethics 37 (9):831-837.
    I shall argue, first, that potential kidney donors may be subject to harmful pressure to donate. This pressure may take almost any form; people have diverse interests, and anything that could set them back may qualify as pressure. Given features of the context—the high stakes, the involvement of family, and the social meaning of donation—such pressure may be especially harmful. This problem is less tractable than the more familiar worry that pressure may compromise consent. Screening may ensure donors validly consent, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31. Drug Prohibition: A Public-Health Perspective.Bonnie Steinbock - 1994 - In S. Luper-Foy C. Brown (ed.), Drugs, Morality, and the Law. Garland. pp. 217--40.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Prohibition Dilemmas and Deontic Logic.Peter Vallentyne - 1987 - Logique Et Analyse 18 (17):113-22.
  33. Drug prohibition is both wrong and unworkable.Tibor R. Machan - 2012 - Think 11 (30):85-92.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Sports : prohibiting drugs in sports : an enhanced proposal.Thomas Petersen & Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen - 2007 - In Jesper Ryberg, Thomas S. Petersen & Clark Wolf (eds.), New waves in applied ethics. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 237--60.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  35.  36
    The Prohibition of Marriage against Canons in the Early Twelfth Century.Terence Patrick McLaughlin - 1941 - Mediaeval Studies 3 (1):94-100.
  36. From prohibition to affirmation : on challenges and possibilities of a Badiouian philosophy of art.Ali Alizadeh - 2018 - In A. J. Bartlett, Justin Clemens & Alain Badiou (eds.), Badiou and his interlocutors: lectures, interviews and responses. London: Bloomsbury Academic, an imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  42
    The Prohibition on Eugenics and Reproductive Liberty.Jacqueline A. Laing - 2006 - University of New South Wales Law Journal 29:261-266.
    John Harris criticises the European Parliament’s ‘waft in the direction of human rights and human dignity’ and rejects its suggestion that ‘human cloning violates the principle of equality since “it permits a eugenic and racist selection of the human race”’. He argues that, by parity of reasoning, so too do ‘pre-natal and pre-implantation screening, not to mention egg donation, sperm donation, surrogacy, abortion and human preference in choice of partner’. Conflating the techniques mentioned (ie, human cloning, egg donation, etc) with (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  30
    Prohibitives in Terence.Willard K. Clement - 1901 - The Classical Review 15 (03):157-159.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  25
    Permissions, Prohibitions and Two Legalising.Three Contributions to Logical Philosophy - 2006 - In J. Jadacki & J. Pasniczek (eds.), The Lvov-Warsaw School: The New Generation. Reidel. pp. 195.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  2
    Misreading Medicine: Statutory Prohibitions of Abortion for Disability.Megan Glasmann - forthcoming - Journal of Medical Humanities:1-13.
    Abortion prohibitions in some states include carve-outs based on the medical condition of either the mother or the fetus. These carve-outs, however, may be couched in limiting language structured by legislators rather than in language understandable in the context of medical care. In circumstances where legislative bodies fail to adequately incorporate medical professionals in the drafting of medical laws, the resulting vagueness or ambiguity may lead to a lack of utility or viability. This paper considers the consequences of such legislative (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  29
    Moral Prohibitions and Consent.Dan W. Brock - 1980 - Bowling Green Studies in Applied Philosophy 2:111-121.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  29
    Prohibitions in Greek.Henry Jackson - 1904 - The Classical Review 18 (05):262-263.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  13
    Prohibition and Legalization: Beyond the False Dichotomy.David Boyum - 2001 - Social Research: An International Quarterly 68:865-867.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44. Nozick, prohibition, and no-fault motor insurance.Toby Handfield - 2003 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 20 (2):201–208.
    Is a Nozickian theory of rights compatible with a no-fault motor insurance scheme? I say, Yes. The argument turns on an explication of the basis on which a Nozickian justifies the prohibition of merely risky activities.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  38
    Protecting Research Subjects from Prohibited Multi-Participation in Clinical Trials.Hans-Peter Graf - 2011 - Research Ethics 7 (4):136-147.
    The protection of human research subjects in clinical studies is regulated by international guidelines and national laws. Research Ethics Committees play an important role here, as they review the documentation for clinical studies under consideration of ethical aspects. This documentation includes an exclusion or wash-out period which designates when study subjects may not have participated in another study or be allowed to take part in a future one within a specified time period. However not all research subjects comply with their (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Are prohibitions of superluminal causation by stochastic Einstein locality and by absence of Lewisian probabilistic counterfactual causality equivalent?Miklós Rédei - 1993 - Philosophy of Science 60 (4):608-618.
    Butterfield's (1992a,b,c) claim of the equivalence of absence of Lewisian probabilistic counterfactual causality (LC) to Hellman's stochastic Einstein locality (SEL) is questioned. Butterfield's assumption on which the proof of his claim is based would suffice to prove that SEL implies absence of LC also for appropriately given versions of these notions in algebraic quantum field theory, but the assumption is not an admissible one. The conclusion must be that the relation of SEL and absence of LC is open, and that (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  62
    Prohibition and preemption.Arthur Ripstein - 1999 - Legal Theory 5 (3):235-263.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Prohibiting Attempts and Preparations.Barbara Levenbook - 1980 - University of Missouri-Kansas City Law Review 49:41-63.
  49.  26
    Antitrust prohibitions of anti-abortion protests.Clifton B. Perry - 1995 - Journal of Social Philosophy 26 (2):73-80.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  15
    « Prohibition, psychoanalysis, and the heterosexual matrix » in Gender Trouble par Judith Butler : genres du récit et inflexions imaginaires.Chantal Delourme - 2019 - Rue Descartes 95 (1):108-125.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 973