Results for 'Popper’s criticism of induction'

950 found
Order:
  1.  77
    On a recent objection to Popper and Miller's "disproof" of probabilistic induction.Colin Howson - 1989 - Philosophy of Science 56 (4):675-680.
    Dunn and Hellman's objection to Popper and Miller's alleged disproof of inductive probability is considered and rejected. Dunn and Hellman base their objection on a decomposition of the incremental support P(h/e)-P(h) of h by e dual to that of Popper and Miller, and argue, dually to Popper and Miller, to a conclusion contrary to the latters' that all support is deductive in character. I contend that Dunn and Hellman's dualizing argument fails because the elements of their decomposition are not supports (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  2.  17
    Edward A. Milne’s Philosophy of Science: Between Aristotelianism and Popperism.Dariusz Dąbek - 2019 - Roczniki Filozoficzne 67 (3):5-23.
    This article seeks to show that E.A. Milne’s philosophy of science has its roots in the philosophy of Aristotle and it could be an inspiration for Popper’s philosophy. The similarities with Aristotle’s concept are as follows: 1) the aim of science is to explain phenomena by discovering general principles; 2) the mind is responsible for discovering them, although experience guides the search; 3) deducing detailed statements from general assumptions is the most important element of research. On the other hand, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  22
    The Distinctive Character of Popper’s Critical Rationalism.Jeremy Shearmur - 2021 - In Oseni Taiwo Afisi (ed.), Karl Popper and Africa: Knowledge, Politics and Development. Springer. pp. 69-81.
    Popper was also a critic of the idea that it was possible – or necessary – to give a positive response to the problem of induction. He was also a critic of many probabilistic theories of induction. He suggested that instead of seeking for a positive way of resolving the problem of induction – or, more generally, of trying to justify our claims that our ideas were true – we should, instead be concerned to make our claims (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Falsificationism Unfalsified: a Reply to Callahan’s “Why Popper is Wrong on Induction”.J. C. Lester - manuscript
    Epistemology is often a problem for libertarianism. Many libertarian texts assume that they need to do more than explain and defend the libertarian conjecture. Instead, they try to offer epistemological support for it (whether empirically or morally); which falsificationism and, more broadly, critical rationalism explains is not possible. Moreover, they often mistake this attempt at support for an explanation of libertarianism (which ought to include an abstract theory of liberty and how it relates to liberty in practice). Therefore, when a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  42
    Popper's criticism of methodology of social sciences.Nenad Cekić - 1993 - Theoria 36 (2):21-48.
  6.  1
    Challenging historicist utopianism: Karl Popper’s criticism of Karl Mannheim.Martyn Hammersley - forthcoming - History of European Ideas.
    In his critique of historicism and utopian social engineering, Karl Popper treats various writers – notably, Plato, Hegel, and Marx – as expounding these mistaken ideas, and as illustrating the threat they pose to ‘the open society’. Among contemporaries, one of those he singles out for criticism is the sociologist Karl Mannheim. While he spends relatively little time discussing Mannheim’s work compared to that of Plato and Marx, I argue that Ideology and Utopia and Man and Society in an (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  45
    Popper's Analysis of the Problems of Induction and Demarcation and Mises' Justification of the Theoretical Social Sciences.Natsuka Tokumaru - 2009 - In Zuzana Parusniková & Robert S. Cohen (eds.), Rethinking Popper. London: Springer. pp. 161--174.
  8.  28
    Lakatos's criticism of Carnapian inductive logic was mistaken.Teddy Groves - 2016 - Journal of Applied Logic 14:3-21.
  9. Suppes's Criticism of the Propensity Interpretation of Probability and Quantum Mechanics.Karl Popper - 1974 - In P. A. Schlipp (ed.), The Philosophy of Karl Popper (Book Ii). Open Court. pp. 1125-1139.
  10. Improve Popper and procure a perfect simulacrum of verification indistinguishable from the real thing.Nicholas Maxwell - 2021 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science.
    According to Karl Popper, science cannot verify its theories empirically, but it can falsify them, and that suffices to account for scientific progress. For Popper, a law or theory remains a pure conjecture, probability equal to zero, however massively corroborated empirically it may be. But it does just seem to be the case that science does verify empirically laws and theories. We trust our lives to such verifications when we fly in aeroplanes, cross bridges and take modern medicines. We can (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  11
    Popper and His Popular Critics: Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos.Joseph Agassi - 2014 - Cham: Imprint: Springer.
    This volume examines Popper's philosophy by analyzing the criticism of his most popular critics: Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos. They all followed his rejection of the traditional view of science as inductive. Starting from the assumption that Hume's criticism of induction is valid, the book explores the central criticism and objections that these three critics have raised. Their objections have met with great success, are significant and deserve paraphrase. One also may consider them reasonable (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12. Conjectural knowledge: Popper's solution of the problem of induction.David Miller - 1982 - In Karl R. Popper & Paul Levinson (eds.), In pursuit of truth: essays on the philosophy of Karl Popper on the occasion of his 80th birthday. Sussex, England: Harvester Press. pp. 17--49.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13.  43
    Popper’s Critical Rationalism as a Response to the Problem of Induction: Predictive Reasoning in the Early Stages of the Covid-19 Epidemic.Tuomo Peltonen - 2023 - Philosophy of Management 22 (1):7-23.
    The extent of harm and suffering caused by the coronavirus pandemic has prompted a debate about whether the epidemic could have been contained, had the gravity of the crisis been predicted earlier. In this paper, the philosophical debate on predictive reasoning is framed by Hume’s problem of induction. Hume argued that it is rationally unjustified to move from the finite observations of past incidences to the predictions of future events. Philosophy has offered two major responses to the problem of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  77
    Popper and His Popular Critics: Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos: Appendix.Joseph Agassi - 2022 - Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 59 (4):181-188.
    Popper’s popular critics – Kuhn, Feyerabend, and Lakatos – replace his older, Wittgenstein-style critics, now defunct. His new critics played with the idea of criticism as beneficial, in vain search of variants of these that could better appeal to the public. Some of their criticism of Popper is valid but marginal for the dispute about rationality. He was Fallibilist; they hedged about it. He viewed learning from experience as learning from error; they were unclear about it. His (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  88
    Karl Popper: Critical Appraisals.Philip Catton & Graham Macdonald (eds.) - 2004 - New York: Routledge.
    One of the most original thinkers of the century, Karl Popper has inspired generations of philosophers, historians, and politicians. This collection of papers, specially written for this volume, offers fresh philosophical examination of key themes in Popper's philosophy, including philosophy of knowledge, science and political philosophy. Drawing from some of Popper's most important works, contributors address his solution to the problem of induction, his views on conventionalism and criticism in an open society, and his unique position in 20th (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  16.  66
    Popper's account of acceptability.R. G. Swinburne - 1971 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 49 (2):167 – 176.
    ACCORDING TO POPPER, SCIENTIFIC THEORIES ARE TO BE ACCEPTED IN SO FAR AS THEY ARE FALSIFIABLE AND IN SO FAR AS THEY HAVE BEEN CORROBORATED. THE CONCEPTS OF FALSIFIABILITY AND CORROBORATION ARE SUBMITTED TO DETAILED ANALYSIS. THE POINT OF ACCEPTING THEORIES, ACCORDING TO POPPER, IS TO OBTAIN THEORIES OF HIGH VERISIMILITUDE. HOWEVER THE BEST WE CAN DO IS TO OBTAIN THEORIES OF HIGH PROBABLE VERISIMILITUDE. POPPER’S CRITERIA FOR ACCEPTING THEORIES WILL ONLY LEAD TO THEORIES OF HIGH PROBABLE VERISIMILITUDE ON (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  17.  87
    Popper and nursing theory.Peter Allmark - 2003 - Nursing Philosophy 4 (1):4-16.
    Science seems to develop by inducing new knowledge from observation. However, it is hard to find a rational justification for induction. Popper offers one attempt to resolve this problem. Nursing theorists have tended to ignore or reject Popper, often on the false belief that he is a logical positivist (and hence hostile to qualitative research). Logical positivism claims that meaningful sentences containing any empirical content should ultimately be reducible to simple, observation statements. Popper refutes positivism by showing that there (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18. A criticism of Popper's theory of simplicity.H. R. Post - 1961 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 12 (48):328-331.
  19.  15
    The Cambridge Companion to Popper.Jeremy Shearmur & Geoffrey Stokes (eds.) - 2016 - Cambridge University Press.
    Karl Popper was one of the most influential philosophers of the twentieth century. His criticism of induction and his falsifiability criterion of demarcation between science and non-science were major contributions to the philosophy of science. Popper's broader philosophy of critical rationalism comprised a distinctive philosophy of social science and political theory. His critique of historicism and advocacy of the open society marked him out as a significant philosopher of freedom and reason. This book sets out the historical and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  20.  31
    Karl R. Popper's Critique of Historicism.Rıza Bakiş & Eyüp Alsancak - 2016 - Cumhuriyet İlahiyat Dergisi 20 (1):89-116.
    Karl R. Popper is an important philosopher of science of 20th Century and is known in this field through his theory of falsification. But the critical theory of rationality is indeed his basic theory and it can be seen in his whole idea. Critique of historicism also contains his views on the social and political philosophy in a systematic context in relation to them. Popper embodied his views about the historicism through human-centered thoughts of philosophers such as Plato, Aristotle, Marx (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Stumbling-blocks and limitations of Popper criticism of induction.Z. Parusnikova - 1985 - Filosoficky Casopis 33 (5):721-734.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  49
    The rationalist tradition and the problem of induction: Karl Popper's rejection of epistemological optimism.Phil Parvin - 2011 - History of European Ideas 37 (3):257-266.
    This article evaluates Karl Popper's contribution to analytic philosophy, and outlines some of the contradictions in his work which make it difficult to locate in any particular tradition. In particular, the article investigates Popper's own claims to be a member of the rationalist tradition. Although Popper described himself as a member of this tradition, his definition of it diverged quite radically from that offered by other supporters of rationalism, like, for example, Mach, Carnap, and the logical positivists of the Vienna (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Popper's Falsificationism and the Problem of Induction.Nader Chokr - 1986 - Epistemologia 9 (1):105.
  24. Popper's solution to the problem of induction.Colin Howson - 1984 - Philosophical Quarterly 34 (135):143-147.
  25.  67
    Traditional rationality vs. a tradition of criticism: A criticism of Popper's theory of the objectivity of science. [REVIEW]JohnR Wettersten - 1978 - Erkenntnis 12 (3):329 - 338.
    This essay points out that Popper's theory of the objectivity of science is ambiguous: it is not clear whether it provides a guarantee of correct evaluations of theories or only a means of uncovering errors in such evaluations. The latter approach seems to be a more natural extension of Popper's fallibilist theory and is needed if his learning theory is adopted. But this leads to serious problems for a fallibilist theory of science.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  26.  14
    Criticism and Survival. An Interpretation of Popper's Theory of Evolution.Godfrey B. Tangwa - 1991 - Quest - and African Journal of Philosophy 5 (2):32-47.
  27.  51
    Levels of criticism: Handling Popperian problems in a Popperian way. [REVIEW]Ivor Grattan-Guinness - 2008 - Axiomathes 18 (1):37-48.
    Popper emphasised both the problem-solving nature of human knowledge, and the need to criticise a scientific theory as strongly as possible. These aims seem to contradict each other, in that the former stresses the problems that motivate scientific theories while the one ignores the character of the problems that led to the formation of the theories against which the criticism is directed. A resolution is proposed in which problems as such are taken as prime in the search for knowledge, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  54
    (1 other version)Pigden Revisited, or In Defence of Popper’s Critique of the Conspiracy Theory of Society.Deane Galbraith - 2022 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 52 (4):235-257.
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences, Volume 52, Issue 4, Page 235-257, July 2022. Charles Pigden’s 1995 article “Popper Revisited, or What is Wrong with Conspiracy Theories?” stimulated what is today a fertile sub-field of philosophical enquiry into conspiracy theories. In his article, Pigden identifies Karl Popper as the originator of the philosophical argument that it is naïve to believe in any conspiracy theory. But Popper was not criticizing belief in conspiracy theories at all, as Pigden defined them or as they (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  64
    Karl Popper's Philosophy of Science.Paul M. Churchland - 1975 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 5 (1):145 - 156.
    Proper recognition came belatedly to the work of Karl Popper. The novelty and power of his comprehensive philosophy went largely unnoticed for decades, his views being misapprehended, to the extent they were apprehended at all, as an uncompelling variation on the dominant Positivist theme. In the past two decades, however, recognition has become widespread. He can lay claim to being the initial figure in a vital and flourishing tradition in the contemporary literature; his views find expression even in undergraduate curricula; (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  33
    A Paradox of Information.A Comment on Miller's New Paradox of Information.A Paradox of Zero Information.Miller's So-called Paradox: A Reply to Professor J. L. Mackie.Miller's paradox of Information.The Straight and Narrow Rule of Induction: A Reply to Dr Bub and Mr Radner.New Mysteries for Old: The Transfiguration of Miller's Paradox.David Miller, Karl R. Popper, Jeffrey Bub & Michael Radner - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (1):124-127.
  31. Keynes's weight of argument and Popper's paradox of ideal evidence.Rod O'Donnell - 1992 - Philosophy of Science 59 (1):44-52.
    Popper's paradox of ideal evidence has long been viewed as a telling criticism of Keynes's logical theory of probability and its associated concept of the weight of argument. This paper shows that a simple addition to Keynes's definitions of irrelevance enables his theory to elude the paradox with ease. The modified definition draws on ideas already present in Keynes's Treatise on Probability (1973). As a consequence, relevant evidence and the weight of argument may increase, even when new evidence leaves (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  26
    Marx's view of history and Popper's criticism.Shigeru Shojaku - 1971 - Kagaku Tetsugaku 4:77-89.
  33.  43
    Between autobiography and reality: Popper's inductive years.Michel ter Hark - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 33 (1):79-103.
    On the basis of his unpublished thesis ‘Gewohnheit und Gesetzerlebnis in der Erziehung’ a historical reconstruction is given of the genesis of Popper's ideas on induction and demarcation which differs radically from his own account in Unended quest. It is shown not only that he wholeheartedly endorses inductive epistemology and psychology but also that his ‘demarcation’ criterion is inductivistic. Moreover it is shown that his later demarcation thesis arises not from his worries about, on the one hand, Marxism and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  34.  13
    The Backbone of a Straw Man.Artur Koterski - 2018 - Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy 62:75-79.
    In his monograph on the Vienna Circle Kraft writes that “one of the earliest and most fundamental insights of the Vienna Circle” was “that no deductive or logical justification of induction is at all possible”. In Logik der Forschung Popper developed his philosophical conception starting from a very emphatic critique of logical positivism and its alleged essential feature inductivism. Although Kraft’s assessment is essentially correct, as the present paper intends to show, Popper’s opinion prevailed and came to dominate (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Reid's Criticism of Hume's Theory of Personal Identity.Harry Lesser - 1978 - Hume Studies 4 (2):41-63.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:REID' S CRITICISM OF HUME'S THEORY OF PERSONAL IDENTITY One of the most interesting philosophical controversies is that between Reid and Hume, considered as representatives of two different sorts of empiricism. Hume, for these purposes, represents 'radical' empiricism, and the attempt to base knowledge solely on experience and what can be validly inferred from it, regardless of how far this leads one from everyday notions and beliefs. Reid, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36. Inductive Support.Georg J. W. Dorn - 1991 - In Gerhard Schurz & Georg Dorn (eds.), Advances in Scientific Philosophy. Essays in Honour of Paul Weingartner on the Occasion of the 60th Anniversary of his Birthday. Rodopi. pp. 345.
    I set up two axiomatic theories of inductive support within the framework of Kolmogorovian probability theory. I call these theories ‘Popperian theories of inductive support’ because I think that their specific axioms express the core meaning of the word ‘inductive support’ as used by Popper (and, presumably, by many others, including some inductivists). As is to be expected from Popperian theories of inductive support, the main theorem of each of them is an anti-induction theorem, the stronger one of them (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37. What is Dialectic? Some remarks on Popper’s criticism.Berry Groisman - unknown
    Karl Popper famously opposed Marxism in general and its philosophical core – the Marxist dialectic – in particular. As a progressive thinker, Popper saw in dialectic a source of dogmatism damaging to philosophy and political theory. Popper had summarized his views on dialectic in an article that was first delivered in 1937 and subsequently republished as a chapter of his book (2002, pp. 419-451), where he accuses Marxist dialecticians of not tolerating criticism. Ironically, Popper’s view that all Marxist (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  91
    Karl R. Popper. The demarcation between science and metaphysics. A reprint of XXXVI 533. The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, The library of living philosophers, vol. 11, Open Court, La Salle, Ill., and Cambridge University Press, London, 1963, pp. 183–226. - John G. Kemeny. Carnap's theory of probability and induction. The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, The library of living philosophers, vol. 11, Open Court, La Salle, Ill., and Cambridge University Press, London, 1963, pp. 711–738. - Arthur W. Burks. On the significance of Carnap's system of inductive logic for the philosophy of induction. The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, The library of living philosophers, vol. 11, Open Court, La Salle, Ill., and Cambridge University Press, London, 1963, pp. 739–759. - Hilary Putnam. “Degree of confirmation” and inductive logic. The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, The library of living. [REVIEW]Richard C. Jeffrey - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (3):631-633.
  39.  24
    Objective Knowledge and the not Dispensability of Epistemic Subjects. Some remarks on Popper's notion of objective knowledge.Shahid Rahman, Juan Redmond & Nicolas Clerbout - unknown
    While discussing his notion of objective knowledge Popper introduces the idea of dispensability of knowing subjects, the autonomy of knowledge and the argumentative function of language. The main claim of our paper is that, on our view, objective knowledge produced by argumentative interaction is not achieved by dispensing knowing subjects but by differentiating between the play and the strategic levels of argumentation, where a distinction should be drawn between a particular concrete knowing subject engaged in that interaction, say Karl, and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  38
    On Popper-Miller's proof of the impossibility of inductive probability.Andr�Srivadulla Rodr�Guez - 1987 - Erkenntnis 27 (3):353-357.
  41.  24
    Between autobiography and reality: Popper's inductive years.M. Hark - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 33 (1):75-100.
    On the basis of his unpublished thesis 'Gewohnheit und Gesetzerlebnis in der Erziehung' (1926-7) a historical reconstruction is given of the genesis of Popper's ideas on induction and demarcation which differs radically from his own account in Unended quest. It is shown not only that he wholeheartedly endorses inductive epistemology and psychology but also that his 'demarcation' criterion is inductivistic. Moreover it is shown that his later demarcation thesis arises not from his worries about, on the one hand, Marxism (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  29
    The Devaluation of the Subject in Popper’s Theory of World 3.Zuzana Parusniková - 2016 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 46 (3):304-317.
    Popper proposed his theory of objective knowledge to eliminate subjectivist epistemologies. Popper’s objectivism culminated in the theory of the autonomous World 3 characterized by its independence from the subjective factors belonging to World 2. I argue that Popper did not succeed in unifying his idea of the autonomy of knowledge with the requirement of the creative role of the critical subject in cognition. Moreover, his effort to desubjectivize knowledge undermined the vital importance of the critical activity that ensures the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43. Thoughts on Political Sources of Karl Popper’s Philosophy of Science.Struan Jacobs - 1999 - Journal of Philosophical Research 24:445-457.
    How did Karl Popper arrive at his theory of science? Popper believed that Einstein’s general theory of relativity and his attitudes of modesty and self-criticism were all important.This paper challenges details in Popper’s account and suggests an alternative interpretation of the formation of his theory. It is held that his disillusionment with Marxism predated and conditioned his understanding of Einstein, and that the liberalism of J. S. Mill may have exercised an influence. Political ideas and practice paved the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Popper's paradoxical pursuit of natural philosophy.Nicholas Maxwell - 2016 - In Jeremy Shearmur & Geoffrey Stokes (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Popper. Cambridge University Press. pp. 170-207.
    Philosophy of science is seen by most as a meta-discipline – one that takes science as its subject matter, and seeks to acquire knowledge and understanding about science without in any way affecting, or contributing to, science itself. Karl Popper’s approach is very different. His first love is natural philosophy or, as he would put it, cosmology. This intermingles cosmology and the rest of natural science with epistemology, methodology and metaphysics. Paradoxically, however, one of his best known contributions, his (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  45.  12
    Popper¿s Approach to Education: A Cornerstone of Teaching and Learning.Stephanie Chitpin - 2016 - New York, NY: Routledge.
    Challenging the theory of induction in teacher education, this book proposes a knowledge-building framework based on the critical rationalism of philosopher of science, Karl Popper. The Objective Knowledge Growth Framework developed in this book is designed to be an effective critical analysis framework for empowering teachers and schools to build and share professional knowledge. This book is essential reading for educational scholars, researchers, professionals, policymakers, and all those interested in exploring the application of Popperian philosophy to the field of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46. Popper’s Argument against Spengler’s “Historicism”.Richard Michael McDonough - forthcoming - Oswald Spengler Society Journal.
    § I presents a detailed version of “Popper’s Basic Argument.” § 2 shows why Marx’s theory of historical development is a paradigm case of the kind of “historicism” that is refuted by Popper’s argument. § 3 explains the crucial difference between Marx’s and Spengler’s respective theories that makes the former but not the latter fall to Popper’s criticism. § 4 argues that the inapplicability of Popper’s argument to Spengler’s type of theory is obvious from the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  15
    More on popper and biology: the utility of induction.John R. S. Fincham - 2000 - Bioessays 22 (7):684-684.
  48.  16
    Induktive Exemplifikation in realen und gedanklichen Experimenten.Marco Buzzoni - 2023 - Distinctio 2 (2):17-43.
    Der Neue Experimentalismus musste sich angesichts seines Gegensatzes zwischen experimentellen Praktiken und grundlegenden Theorien mit dem Problem der Beziehung zwischen der Einmaligkeit der ersteren und der Allgemeinheit der letzteren auseinandersetzen. Andere Autoren (von Charles A. Baylis und Nelson Goodman bis Catherine Elgin) haben das Konzept der Exemplifikation verwendet, um die Beziehung zwischen partikulären und universellen/allgemeinen Begriffen oder Gesetzen zu klären. Es stellt sich jedoch die Frage, ob sie zwar einen Gesichtspunkt andeuten, der neue Aspekte des Problems beleuchten kann, das Problem (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  8
    Considerations on the Non-Materiality of the Consciousness - Focusing on Popper’s Theory of Three Worlds. 김소형 - 2024 - Journal of the Daedong Philosophical Association 106:45-68.
    본 논문의 목적은 포퍼의 ‘3세계 이론(Theory of Three World)’을 두뇌와 같은 “생물학 적 조건은 의식의 필요조건이지만 충분조건이 아니다”라는 주장으로 이해하고 분석적으로 논하는 것이다. 3세계 이론은 물리계인 1세계 이외에, 정신계인 2세계와 객관적 지식의 세계인 3세계를 상정하는 다원론적 주장이다. 포퍼가 3세계를 요구하는 이유는, 첫째 물 리적·생물학적 조건만으로는 과학적 지식들의 객관성을 담보할 수 없으며, 둘째 의식이 나 관점의 누락하고는 어떤 과학적 지식도 물리계에 적용될 수 없다고 생각했기 때문이다. 그는 과학철학자로서 날로 발전하는 과학지식들의 객관성과 합리성에 탄복했으나, 이것들 의 정당성에 의문을 제기하는 흄의 귀납의 문제에는 (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  99
    Why There Can't Be a Logic of Induction.Stuart S. Glennan - 1994 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1994:78 - 86.
    In this paper I offer a criticism of Carnap's inductive logic which also applies to other formal methods of inductive inference. Criticisms of Carnap's views have typically centered upon the justification of his particular choice of inductive method. I argue that the real problem is not that there is an agreed upon method for which no justification can be found, but that different methods are justified in different circumstances.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 950