Results for 'Kroon Frederick'

950 found
Order:
  1.  61
    Phenomenal Intentionality and the Role of Intentional Objects.Frederick Kroon - 2013 - In Uriah Kriegel (ed.), Phenomenal Intentionality. , US: Oxford University Press. pp. 137.
  2. Descriptivism, Pretense, and the Frege-Russell Problems.Frederick Kroon - 2004 - Philosophical Review 113 (1):1-30.
    Contrary to frequent declarations that descriptivism as a theory of how names refer is dead and gone, such a descriptivism is, to all appearances, alive and well. Or rather, a descendent of that doctrine is alive and well. This new version—neo-descriptivism, for short—is supposedly immune from the usual arguments against descriptivism, in large part because it avoids classical descriptivism’s emphasis on salient, first-come-to-mind properties and holds instead that a name’s reference-fixing content is typically given by egocentric properties specified in terms (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  3.  29
    Why Realisms about Fiction Must (and Can) Accommodate Fictional Properties.Frederick Kroon & Paul Oppenheimer - 2023 - Philosophies 8 (5):82.
    The topic of fictional objects is a familiar one, the topic of fictional properties less so. But it deserves its own place in the philosophy of fiction, if only because fictional properties have such a prominent role to play in science fiction and fantasy. What, then, are fictional properties and how does their apparent unreality relate to the unreality of fictional objects? The present paper explores these questions in the light of familiar debates about the nature of fictional objects.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4. A-intensions and communication.Frederick Kroon - 2004 - Philosophical Studies 118 (1-2):279-298.
    In his 'Why We Need A-Intensions', Frank Jackson argues that "representational content [is] how things are represented to be by a sentence in the communicative role it possesses in virtue of what it means," a type of content Jackson takes to be broadly descriptive. I think Jackson overstates his case. Even if we agree that such representational properties play a crucial reference-fixing role, it is much harder to argue the case for a crucial communicative role. I articulate my doubts about (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  5. The Fiction of Creationism.Frederick Kroon - 2010 - In Franck Lihoreau (ed.), Truth in Fiction. Ontos Verlag. pp. 38--203.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  6. Belief about Nothing in Particular.Frederick Kroon - 2005 - In Mark Eli Kalderon (ed.), Fictionalism in Metaphysics. New York: Oxford University Press UK. pp. 178.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  7. Causal descriptivism.Frederick W. Kroon - 1987 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 65 (1):1 – 17.
  8. Intending and Imagining.Frederick Kroon - 2006 - In Henrik Lagerlund, Sten Lindström & Rysiek Sliwinski (eds.), Modality Matters: Twenty-Five Essays in Honour of Krister Segerberg. Uppsala Philosophical Studies 53. pp. 53--247.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Imagination, Philosophy, and the Arts.Frederick Kroon - 2004 - Mind 113 (451):559-562.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10. Existence in the Theory of Definite Descriptions.Frederick Kroon - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy 106 (7):365-389.
  11. Beyond Belief? A Critical Study of Graham Priest's Beyond the Limits of Thought'.Frederick Kroon - 2001 - Theoria 67 (2):140-53.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12. Quantified negative existentials.Frederick Kroon - 2003 - Dialectica 57 (2):149–164.
    This paper suggests that quantified negative existentials about fiction—statements of the form “There are some / many / etc. Fs in work W who don't exist”—offer a serious challenge to the theorist of fiction: more serious, in a number of ways, that singular negative existentials. I argue that the temptation to think that only a realist semantics of such statements is plausible should be resisted. There are numerous quantified negative existentials found in other areas that seem equally “true” but where (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  13. Theoretical terms and the causal view of reference.Frederick W. Kroon - 1985 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 63 (2):143 – 166.
  14. Millian descriptivism.Frederick Kroon - 2004 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82 (4):553 – 576.
    Mill is a detractor of the view that proper names have meanings, defending in its place the view that names are nothing more than (meaningless) marks. Because of this, Mill is often regarded as someone who anticipated the theory of direct reference for names: the view that the only contribution a name makes to propositions expressed through its use is the name's referent. In this paper I argue that the association is unfair. With some gentle interpretation, Mill can be portrayed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  15. Rationality and epistemic paradox.Frederick Kroon - 1993 - Synthese 94 (3):377 - 408.
    This paper provides a new solution to the epistemic paradox of belief-instability, a problem of rational choice which has recently received considerable attention (versions of the problem have been discussed by — among others — Tyler Burge, Earl Conee, and Roy Sorensen). The problem involves an ideally rational agent who has good reason to believe the truth of something of the form:[Ap] p if and only if it is not the case that I accept or believe p.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  16.  99
    The problem of 'Jonah': How not to argue for the causal theory of reference.Frederick W. Kroon - 1983 - Philosophical Studies 43 (2):281 - 299.
  17.  11
    Mill's Philosophy of Language.Frederick Kroon - 2016 - In Christopher Macleod & Dale E. Miller (eds.), A Companion to Mill. Hoboken: John Wiley & Sons, Inc.. pp. 207–221.
    The present chapter describes Mill's account of language and the wider goals that he sets for his account, such as its relation to logic and reasoning. While the main purpose of the chapter is expository, it also engages with the common perception among philosophers of language that Mill's views of language are outdated, apart, possibly, from his purely denotative account of proper names. By focusing on Mill's view of names as well as propositions, including his conflation of predication and assertion, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  63
    Pushing the Boundaries of Pretence.Frederick Kroon - 2018 - Analysis 78 (4):703-712.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  19.  47
    Non-directed postmortem sperm donation: some questions.Frederick Kroon & Ben Kroon - 2021 - Journal of Medical Ethics 47 (4):261-262.
    In their recent ‘The ethical case for non-directed postmortem sperm donation’, Hodson and Parker outline and defend the concept of voluntary non-directed postmortem sperm donation, the idea that men should be able to register their desire to donate their sperm after death for use by strangers since this would offer a potential means of increasing the quantity and heterogeneity of donor sperm. In this response, we raise some concerns about their proposal, focusing in particular on the fact that current methodologies (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20. On Pretending that Things Do Not Exist: Evans, Existence, and Existentials.Frederick Kroon - 2003 - Dialogue 42 (2):235-.
    Attempts to analyze negative existential statements face the following familiar problem. If a negative existential statement—say, “Hamlet does not exist” or “the golden mountain does not exist”—is true, its subject term must lack an object of reference. But, absent such an object, it seems that nothing true or false can be said about “it.” In particular, if there is no Hamlet to talk about, we surely cannot truthfully say that “he” does not exist. Hence, the truth of true negative existentials—and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Was meinong only pretending?Frederick W. Kroon - 1992 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (3):499-527.
    In this paper I argue against the usual interpretation of\nMeinong's argument for nonexistent objects, an\ninterpretation according to which Meinong imported\nnonexistent objects like "the golden mountain" to account\ndirectly for the truth of statements like the golden\nmountain is golden'. I claim instead (using evidence from\nMeinong's "On Assumptions") that his argument really\ninvolves an ineliminable appeal to the notion of pretense.\nThis appeal nearly convinced Meinong at one stage that he\ncould do without nonexistent objects. The reason, I argue,\nwhy he nonetheless embraced an ontology of nonexistents (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  22.  85
    Parts and Pretense.Frederick W. Kroon - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (3):543-560.
    This paper begins with a puzzle about certain temporal expressions: phrases like ‘Jones as he was ten years ago’ and ‘the Jones of ten years ago’. There are reasons to take these as substantival, to be interpreted as terms for temporal parts. But it seems that the same reifying strategy would also force us to countenance a host of less attractive posits, among them fictional counterparts of real things (to correspond to such phrases as ‘Garrison as he was in the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  82
    Characterizing Non-existents.Frederick Kroon - 1996 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 51 (1):163-193.
    Consider predicates like 'is a fictional character' and 'is a mythical object'. Since their ascription entails a corresponding Negative Existential claim, call these 'NE-characterizing predicates'. Objectualists such as Parsons, Sylvan, van Inwagen, and Zalta think that NE-characterizing properties are genuine properties of genuinely non-existent objects. But how, then, to make room for statements like 'Vulcan is a failed posit' and 'that little green man is a trick of the light'? The predicates involved seem equally NE-characterizing yet on the surface fail (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  24. Imaginative motivation.Frederick Kroon - 2009 - Utilitas 21 (2):181-196.
    This article argues for a certain picture of the rational formation of conditional intentions, in particular deterrent intentions, that stands in sharp contrast to accounts on which rational agents are often not able to form such intentions because of what these enjoin should their conditions be realized. By considering the case of worthwhile but hard-to-form deterrent intentions (the threat to leave a cheating partner, say), the article argues that rational agents may be able to form such intentions by first simulating (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  93
    A problem about make-believe.Frederick William Kroon - 1994 - Philosophical Studies 75 (3):201 - 229.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  26.  5
    Fictional Properties.Frederick Kroon & Paul E. Oppenheimer - 2024 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 100 (4):447-466.
    The topic of fictional objects and their nature is a familiar one, the topic of fictional properties less so. This article focuses on the way artefactualism – now arguably the most popular form of realism about fictional objects – might be extended to give an account of fictional properties. After describing what seems the most developed such extension, the article articulates a serious problem it faces, before showing how artefactualism about fictional properties would benefit from certain insights contained in an (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  47
    Realism and the Progress of Science.Frederick William Kroon - 1986 - Philosophical Studies 31:346-349.
  28.  63
    Against ontological reduction.Frederick W. Kroon - 1992 - Erkenntnis 36 (1):53 - 81.
  29.  1
    Real Emotions for Unreal Fictional Objects: A Brentanean Perspective.Frederick William Kroon - forthcoming - Philosophia:1-24.
    The best-known arguments for the reality of emotions to fictional characters are (on their own) unable to show that appreciators of fiction have genuine emotional attitudes to fictional characters. At best, they point to the need to distinguish fictional emotions as states from fictional emotions as (relational) attitudes. I argue for this position by using an argumentative strategy that parallels one found in Brentano’s reist account of intentional states involving non-existent objects. The conception of emotional states that emerges yields a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  30
    Robert Nola (25 June 1940 – 23 October 2022).Frederick Kroon - 2024 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 102 (1):251-252.
    Robert Nola was born in Auckland, his father a Croatian fisherman who emigrated to New Zealand. Robert was the first in his New Zealand family to go to University, and after completing an undergrad...
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Fictionalism in Metaphysics.Frederick Kroon - 2011 - Philosophy Compass 6 (11):786-803.
    This is a survey of contemporary work on ‘fictionalism in metaphysics’, a term that is taken to signify both the place of fictionalism as a distinctive anti‐realist metaphysics in which usefulness rather than truth is the norm of acceptance, and the fact that philosophers have given fictionalist treatments of a range of specifically metaphysical notions.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  32.  60
    Deterrence and the fragility of rationality.Frederick Kroon - 1996 - Ethics 106 (2):350-377.
  33.  41
    Fictionalism in Philosophy.Bradley Armour-Garb & Frederick Kroon (eds.) - 2019 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    There are things we routinely say that may strike us as literally false but that we are nonetheless reluctant to give up. This might be something mundane, like the way we talk about the sun setting in the west, or it could be something much deeper, like engaging in talk that is ostensibly about numbers despite believing that numbers do not literally exist. Rather than regard such behaviour as self-defeating, a "fictionalist" is someone who thinks that this kind of discourse (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34. Circles and Fixed Points in Description Theories of Reference.Frederick Kroon - 1989 - Noûs 23 (3):373 - 382.
  35. Make-believe and fictional reference.Frederick Kroon - 1994 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 52 (2):207-214.
  36.  76
    Intentional Objects, Pretence, and the Quasi-Relational Nature of Mental Phenomena: A New Look at Brentano on Intentionality.Frederick Kroon - 2013 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 21 (3):377-393.
    Brentano famously changed his mind about intentionality between the 1874 and 1911 editions of Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint (PES). The 1911 edition repudiates the 1874 view that to think about something is to stand in a relation to something that is within in the mind, and holds instead that intentionality is only like a relation (it is ‘quasi-relational’). Despite this, Brentano still insists that mental activity involves ‘the reference to something as an object’, much as he did in the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  37. Is the brain a quantum computer?Abninder Litt, Chris Eliasmith, Frederick W. Kroon, Steven Weinstein & Paul Thagard - 2006 - Cognitive Science 30 (3):593-603.
    We argue that computation via quantum mechanical processes is irrelevant to explaining how brains produce thought, contrary to the ongoing speculations of many theorists. First, quantum effects do not have the temporal properties required for neural information processing. Second, there are substantial physical obstacles to any organic instantiation of quantum computation. Third, there is no psychological evidence that such mental phenomena as consciousness and mathematical thinking require explanation via quantum theory. We conclude that understanding brain function is unlikely to require (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  38. Creationism and the problem of indiscernible fictional objects.Frederick Kroon - 2015 - In Stuart Brock & Anthony Everett (eds.), Fictional Objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39. Reference and Reduction.Frederick William Kroon - 1980 - Dissertation, Princeton University
    Chapter V attempts to provide the elements of a solution to the problem of how terms in theoretical sciences acquire their reference. Its proposal is that a theory of reference-acquisition for theoretical terms should acknowledge the fact that what fixes the reference of a theoretical term is typically the embedding theory as a whole, not an austere causal description like 'the item causally responsible for event E.' It is argued that there are epistemic reasons for the existence of this phenomenon, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Philosophical explanations and sceptical intuitions.Frederick W. Kroon - 1986 - Philosophical Quarterly 36 (144):391-395.
  41.  13
    Russell’s Descriptions and Meinong’s Assumptions.Frederick Kroon - 2006 - In Andrea Bottani & Richard Davies (eds.), Modes of Existence: Papers in Ontology and Philosophical Logic. Ontos Verlag. pp. 81-104.
  42. Truthmaking and fiction.Frederick W. Kroon - 2000 - Logique Et Analyse 43 (169-170):195-210.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  47
    Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege.Frederick W. Kroon - 1982 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 29:290-291.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. The semantics of 'things in themselves': A deflationary account.Frederick Kroon - 2001 - Philosophical Quarterly 51 (203):165-181.
    Kant's distinction between things in themselves and things as they appear, or appearances, is commonly attacked on the ground that it delivers a radical and incoherent ‘two world’ picture of what there is. I attempt to deflect this attack by questioning these terms of dismissal. Distinctions of the kind Kant draws on are in fact legion, and they make perfectly good sense. The way to make sense of them, however, is not by buying into a profligate ontology but by using (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  45.  50
    On a Moorean solution to instability puzzles.Frederick W. Kroon - 1990 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 68 (4):455 – 461.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46.  63
    Plantinga on God, freedom, and evil.Frederick W. Kroon - 1981 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 12 (2):75 - 96.
  47.  77
    A Utilitarian Paradox.Frederick Kroon - 1980 - Analysis 41 (2):107 - 112.
  48.  63
    Denotation and description in free logic.Frederick W. Kroon - 1991 - Theoria 57 (1-2):17-41.
  49. Fear and Integrity.Frederick Kroon - 2008 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 38 (1):31-49.
    I'll begin this paper with an autobiographical example — an instance of a common enough kind of case involving agents who are faced with making a choice they strongly care about, but who have tendencies that incline them towards choosing an option they prefer not to choose. Later in the paper, I apply some of the general lessons learned from this case to a philosophically more familiar example of a hard-to-make choice, and to the well-known problem the example generates for (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  39
    The Problem of (Fully) Empty Predicates.Bradley Armour-Garb & Frederick Kroon - 2017 - Australasian Philosophical Review 1 (2):163-167.
    ABSTRACTIn our paper, we mount a novel argument, which trades on recent work by Roy Sorensen [2016], following work by Saul Kripke, against Yablo's preferred reading of if-thenism, which is an attempt to read problematically ontologically committing sentences in a way that does not carry such ontological commitments. Although our argument is directed at Yablo's proposed reading of if-thenism, if the argument is successful, other versions of if-thenism may be affected. After reviewing Sorensen's recent work and presenting our argument, we (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 950