Results for 'Ilkka Törmä'

277 found
Order:
  1.  39
    Evaluation of theories.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2007 - In Theo A. F. Kuipers (ed.), General philosophy of science. London: North Holland. pp. 175--217.
  2. (1 other version)Abduction and truthlikeness.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2005 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 83 (1):255-275.
    This paper studies the interplay between two notions which are important for the project of defending scientific realism: abduction and truthlikeness. The main focus is the generalization of abduction to cases where the conclusion states that the best theory is truthlike or approximately true. After reconstructing the recent proposals of Theo Kuipers within the framework of monadic predicate logic, I apply my own notion of truthlikeness. It turns out that a theory with higher truthlikeness does not always have greater empirical (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  3. Survey article. Verisimilitude: the third period.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1998 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49 (1):1-29.
    The modern history of verisimilitude can be divided into three periods. The first began in 1960, when Karl Popper proposed his qualitative definition of what it is for one theory to be more truthlike than another theory, and lasted until 1974, when David Miller and Pavel Trichý published their refutation of Popper's definition. The second period started immediately with the attempt to explicate truthlikeness by means of relations of similarity or resemblance between states of affairs (or their linguistic representations); the (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  4. Critical scientific realism.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1999 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This book comes to the rescue of scientific realism, showing that reports of its death have been greatly exaggerated. Philosophical realism holds that the aim of a particular discourse is to make true statements about its subject matter. Ilkka Niiniluoto surveys different kinds of realism in various areas of philosophy and then sets out his own critical realist philosophy of science.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   217 citations  
  5.  50
    From dynamic disbeliefs to causality and chance: Wolfgang Spohn: Causation, coherence and concepts: A collection of essays. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 256. Dordrecht: Springer, 2009, xvi+386pp, €149,95 HB.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2010 - Metascience 20 (3):549-552.
    From dynamic disbeliefs to causality and chance Content Type Journal Article DOI 10.1007/s11016-010-9478-0 Authors Ilkka Niiniluoto, Department of Philosophy, History, Culture and Art Studies, University of Helsinki, Helsinki, 00014 Finland Journal Metascience Online ISSN 1467-9981 Print ISSN 0815-0796.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  55
    Unification and Confirmation.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2016 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 31 (1):107-123.
    According to the traditional requirement, formulated by William Whewell in his account of the “consilience of inductions” in 1840, a scientific hypothesis should have unifying power in the sense that it explains and predicts several mutually independent phenomena. Variants of this notion of consilience or unification include deductive, inductive, and approximate systematization. Inference from surprising phenomena to their theoretical explanations was called abduction by Charles Peirce. As a unifying theory is independently testable by new kinds of phenomena, it should also (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7. Truth-Seeking by Abduction.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2018 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer.
    This book examines the philosophical conception of abductive reasoning as developed by Charles S. Peirce, the founder of American pragmatism. It explores the historical and systematic connections of Peirce's original ideas and debates about their interpretations. Abduction is understood in a broad sense which covers the discovery and pursuit of hypotheses and inference to the best explanation. The analysis presents fresh insights into this notion of reasoning, which derives from effects to causes or from surprising observations to explanatory theories. The (...)
  8.  43
    Truthlikeness.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1987 - Dordrecht: Reidel.
    The modern discussion on the concept of truthlikeness was started in 1960. In his influential Word and Object, W. V. O. Quine argued that Charles Peirce's definition of truth as the limit of inquiry is faulty for the reason that the notion 'nearer than' is only "defined for numbers and not for theories". In his contribution to the 1960 International Congress for Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science at Stan­ ford, Karl Popper defended the opposite view by defining a compara­tive (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  9.  48
    L. J. Cohen versus Bayesianism.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):349-349.
  10. Defending abduction.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1999 - Philosophy of Science 66 (3):451.
    Charles S. Peirce argued that, besides deduction and induction, there is a third mode of inference which he called " hypothesis " or " abduction." He characterized abduction as reasoning " from effect to cause," and as " the operation of adopting an explanatory hypothesis." Peirce ' s ideas about abduction, which are related also to historically earlier accounts of heuristic reasoning, have been seen as providing a logic of scientific discovery. Alternatively, abduction is interpreted as giving reasons for pursuing (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  11.  17
    Theoretical concepts and hypothetico-inductive inference.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1973 - Boston,: D. Reidel Pub. Co.. Edited by Raimo Tuomela.
    Conceptual change and its connection to the development of new seien tific theories has reeently beeome an intensively discussed topic in philo sophieal literature. Even if the inductive aspects related to conceptual change have already been discussed to some extent, there has so far existed no systematic treatment of inductive change due to conceptual enrichment. This is what we attempt to accomplish in this work, al though most of our technical results are restricted to the framework of monadic languages. We (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  12. (2 other versions)Scientific progress.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1980 - Synthese 45 (3):427 - 462.
  13. Theories, approximations, and idealizations.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1990 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 16:9-57.
  14. Scientific progress as increasing verisimilitude.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2014 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 46:73-77.
    According to the foundationalist picture, shared by many rationalists and positivist empiricists, science makes cognitive progress by accumulating justified truths. Fallibilists, who point out that complete certainty cannot be achieved in empirical science, can still argue that even successions of false theories may progress toward the truth. This proposal was supported by Karl Popper with his notion of truthlikeness or verisimilitude. Popper’s own technical definition failed, but the idea that scientific progress means increasing truthlikeness can be expressed by defining degrees (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  15.  9
    In memoriam: Raimo Tuomela.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2020 - Ajatus 77 (1):7-10.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Suomen Filosofinen Yhdistys 1873-2023: 150 vuotta suomalaisen filosofian historiaa.Ilkka Niiniluoto, Sami Pihlström & Lari Ahokas (eds.) - 2023 - Suomen Filosofinen Yhdistys.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  75
    Analogy and inductive logic.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1981 - Erkenntnis 16 (1):1 - 34.
  18.  49
    Truth-Seeking by Abduction.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2004 - Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 11:57-82.
    In a seminar with the title “Deduction and Induction in the Sciences”, it is intriguing to ask the following questions: Is there a third type of inference besides deduction and induction? Does this third type of inference play a significant role within scientific inquiry? A positive answer to both of these questions was advocated by Charles S. Peirce throughout his career, even though his opinions changed in important ways during the fifty years between 1865 and 1914. Peirce called the third (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  19.  46
    The Significance of Verisimilitude.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1984 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1984:591 - 613.
    The concept of verisimilitude is an indispensable tool for the fallibilist and realist epistemology. Part of the argument for this thesis consists in the important applications of this notion within the history and philosophy of science. But perhaps the harder part is to convince a sceptical reader of the existence of this concept. A general programme for defining and estimating degrees of truthlikeness for various kinds of scientific statements is outlined in some detail. Ten years after Miller's and Tichy's refutation (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  20. Inductive systematization: Definition and a critical survey.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1972 - Synthese 25 (1-2):25 - 81.
    In 1958, to refute the argument known as the theoretician's dilemma, Hempel suggested that theoretical terms might be logically indispensable for inductive systematization of observational statements. This thesis, in some form or another, has later been supported by Scheffler, Lehrer, and Tuomela, and opposed by Bohnert, Hooker, Stegmüller, and Cornman. In this paper, a critical survey of this discussion is given. Several different putative definitions of the crucial notion inductive systematization achieved by a theory are discussed by reference to the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  21. Eino Kaila's critique of metaphysics.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2012 - In Ilkka Niiniluoto & Sami Pihlström (eds.), Reappraisals of Eino Kaila's philosophy. Helsinki: Philosophical Society of Finland.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22.  34
    The Logic and epistemology of scientific change.Ilkka Niiniluoto & Raimo Tuomela (eds.) - 1979 - Amsterdam: North-Holland Pub. Co..
  23.  40
    The development of the Hintikka program.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2004 - In Dov M. Gabbay, John Woods & Akihiro Kanamori (eds.), Handbook of the history of logic. Boston: Elsevier. pp. 311-356.
  24.  21
    Abduction and geometrical analysis. notes on Charles S. Peirce and Edgar Allan Poe.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1999 - In L. Magnani, Nancy Nersessian & Paul Thagard (eds.), Model-Based Reasoning in Scientific Discovery. Kluwer/Plenum. pp. 239--254.
  25. Truthlikeness and bayesian estimation.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1986 - Synthese 67 (2):321 - 346.
  26. Scientific and "radical" ethnomethodology: From incompatible paradigms to ethnomethodological sociology.Ilkka Arminen - 2008 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 38 (2):167-191.
    Ethnomethodology has been torn between scientific and "radical" aspirations insofar as it moves discoursive practices from resources to the topic of the study. Scientific ethnomethodology, such as conversation analysis, studies discoursive praxis as its topic and resource. Standard scientific criteria are accepted to assess the merits of its findings. "Radical" ethnomethodology addresses mundane reasoning exclusively as its topic without recourse to standardized science. I will show that insofar as "radical" ethnomethodology succeeds in bracketing everyday resources, it loses its phenomenon with (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  27.  24
    On the Philosophy of Applied Social Sciences.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2013 - In Hanne Andersen, Dennis Dieks, Wenceslao J. Gonzalez, Thomas Uebel & Gregory Wheeler (eds.), New Challenges to Philosophy of Science. Springer Verlag. pp. 265--274.
  28. Dretske on laws of nature.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 45 (3):431-439.
    In a recent article [4], Fred I. Dretske has proposed a new analysis of natural laws. Dretske rejects the more or less standard view which says that laws are universal truths with a special function or status in science. As an alternative account, he suggests that laws are expressed by singular statements describing the relationship between universal properties and magnitudes: the statement It is a law that F's are G's3.is to be analysed as F-ness ↦ G-ness.I shall argue, however, that (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  29. (1 other version)Verisimilitude vs. legisimilitude.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1982 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 11 (1-2):35-36.
    L. J. Cohen [1] has recently argued that there is an important concept which is not adequately captured by the recent theories of truthlikeness. Cohen points out that, instead of truth about the actual world, much of science pursues \physically necessary truth", and he concludes that \it is legisimilitude that much of science seeks, not verisimilitude". This point is well made, since the earlier accounts of truthlikeness have not paid attention to the important distinction between lawlike and accidental generalizations.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  30. Possible Worlds of History.Ilkka Lähteenmäki - 2018 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 12 (1):164-182.
    _ Source: _Page Count 19 The theory of possible worlds has been minimally employed in the field of theory and philosophy of history, even though it has found a place as a tool in other areas of philosophy. Discussion has mostly focused on arguments concerning counterfactual history’s status as either useful or harmful. The theory of possible worlds can, however be used also to analyze historical writing. The concept of textual possible worlds offers an interesting framework to work with for (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  15
    The Role of al-Madāʾinī’s Students in the Transmission of His Material.Ilkka Lindstedt - 2014 - Der Islam: Journal of the History and Culture of the Middle East 91 (2):295-340.
    Name der Zeitschrift: Der Islam Jahrgang: 91 Heft: 2 Seiten: 295-340.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32. On explicating verisimilitude: A reply to Oddie.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1982 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 33 (3):290-296.
  33.  4
    Kotarbiński’s Semantic Reism.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2023 - Przeglad Filozoficzny - Nowa Seria 32:57-64.
    Tadeusz Kotarbiński (1886–1981) was a prominent member of the Lvov‑Warsaw School. He is most famous as the founder of praxiology, but his contribution to ontology and semantics was significant as well. Kotarbiński introduced the doctrine of reism (in Elementy [Elements], in 1929). Ontological reism is a radical form of nominalism; it claims that there are no other objects than things or concrete individuals. Semantic reism claims that meaningful statements have to contain only concrete terms (names of things). Other terms are (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. On the Human Condition : Philosophical Essays in Honour of the Centennial Anniversary of Georg Henrik von Wright.Ilkka Niiniluoto & Thomas Wallgren (eds.) - 2017
    Academician Georg Henrik von Wright (1916-2003) was an internationally leading analytic philosopher and philosophical logician but also an open-minded bridge-builder between philosophical schools and an inspiring intellectual and cultural personality. His centenary year 2016 was celebrated with several conferences, lecture series, books, and exhibitions in Helsinki, Cambridge, and Cairo. One of the main events was the conference The Human Condition, organized by the Philosophical Society of Finland and the University of Helsinki on 18–20 May 2016. This volume contains five keynote (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Abduction as Discovery and Pursuit.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2018 - In Truth-Seeking by Abduction. Cham, Switzerland: Springer.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  7
    Käsitteen- ja teorianmuodostuksen perusteita.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1975 - [Helsinki: Helsingin yliopiston filosofian laitos].
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Peirce on Abduction.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2018 - In Truth-Seeking by Abduction. Cham, Switzerland: Springer.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  29
    No evidence of a specific adaptation.Ilkka Pyysiäinen - 2006 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 29 (5):483-484.
    Bering's findings about the mental representation of dead agents are important, although his opposition between “endemic” and “cultural” concepts is misleading. Endemic and cultural are overlapping, not exclusive categories. It is also diffcult to see why reasoning about the dead would require a specific cognitive mechanism. Bering presents no clear evidence for the claim that the postulated mechanism is an adaptation.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  46
    Theory change, truthlikeness, and belief revision.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2010 - In M. Dorato M. Suàrez (ed.), Epsa Epistemology and Methodology of Science. Springer. pp. 189--199.
  40.  27
    Sequential order and sequence structure: the case of incommensurable studies on mobile phone calls.Ilkka Arminen - 2005 - Discourse Studies 7 (6):649-662.
    Two recent conversation analytical studies draw contrary conclusions from seemingly very similar materials. Hutchby and Barnett ‘show that, far from revolutionizing the organization of telephone conversation, mobile phone talk retains many of the norms associated with landline phone talk’. Arminen and Leinonen, however, state that landline and mobile calls differ systematically from each other. These incommensurate findings raise the question of why the comparisons between landline and mobile call openings have not been able to determine whether social and communicative practices (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  41.  23
    Theories of Truth: Vienna, Berlin, and Warsaw.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1999 - Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 6:17-26.
    Neo-Kantian philosophers sometimes divided the history of philosophy in three periods: philosophy before Kant, Kant, and philosophy after Kant. The admirers of Alfred Tarski are prone, with good justification, to propose a similar division of theories of truth. But even in our post-Tarskian period, the nature and significance of Tarski’s theory of truth is still a matter of controversy.1 Therefore, to understand better Tarski’s achievement and some of our present puzzles, it is instructive to go back to the pre-Tarskian problem (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  42.  69
    Handbook of Epistemology.Ilkka Niiniluoto, Matti Sintonen & Jan Woleński (eds.) - 2004 - Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.
    The twenty-eight essays in this Handbook, all by leading experts in the field, provide the most extensive treatment of various epistemological problems, ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  43. Optimistic realism about scientific progress.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2017 - Synthese 194 (9):3291-3309.
    Scientific realists use the “no miracle argument” to show that the empirical and pragmatic success of science is an indicator of the ability of scientific theories to give true or truthlike representations of unobservable reality. While antirealists define scientific progress in terms of empirical success or practical problem-solving, realists characterize progress by using some truth-related criteria. This paper defends the definition of scientific progress as increasing truthlikeness or verisimilitude. Antirealists have tried to rebut realism with the “pessimistic metainduction”, but critical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  44.  68
    10 Truthlikeness and economic theories.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2002 - In Uskali Mäki (ed.), Fact and Fiction in Economics: Models, Realism and Social Construction. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 214.
    In a series of carefully argued and stimulating papers on realism, Usakli Maki has pointed out that economic theories typically are unrealistic in two senses: by violating "the-whole-truth" and "nothing-but-the-truth" (Maki 1989, 1992b, 1994b). He suggests that realism in economics can still be rescued by regarding theories as partially true descriptions of essences and as lawlike statements about tendencies. In this chapter, I defend realism by an alternative strategy: idealizational (or "isolational") statements are counterfactual conditional (Niiniluoto 1986), and the concepts (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  45.  28
    Biodiversity, microbes and human well-being.Ilkka Hanski - 2014 - Ethics in Science and Environmental Politics 14 (1):19-25.
  46. The aim and structure of applied research.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1993 - Erkenntnis 38 (1):1 - 21.
    The distinction between basic and applied research is notoriously vague, despite its frequent use in science studies and in science policy. In most cases it is based on such pragmatic factors as the knowledge and intentions of the investigator or the type of research institute. Sometimes the validity of the distinction is denied altogether. This paper suggests that there are two ways of distinguishing systematically between basic and applied research: (i) in terms of the utilities that define the aims of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  47. Novel facts and bayesianism.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1983 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34 (4):375-379.
  48. Handbook of Epistemology.Ilkka Niiniluoto, Matti Sintonen & Jan Wolenski - 2006 - Erkenntnis 64 (3):415-418.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49.  16
    Does meditation swamp working memory?Pyysiainen Ilkka - 2006 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 29 (6).
  50.  12
    No evidence of a specific adaptation.Pyysiainen Ilkka - 2006 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 29 (5):484.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 277