Results for 'Hm Friedman'

961 found
Order:
  1.  12
    358 PG. Hinman.J. Barwise, L. Blum, M. Shub, S. Smale, Fr Drake, Ss Wainer, E. Engeler, Hm Friedman, Ro Gandy & Cme Yates - 1999 - In Edward R. Griffor, Handbook of computability theory. New York: Elsevier. pp. 358.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. The Epistemic and the Zetetic.Jane Friedman - 2020 - Philosophical Review 129 (4):501-536.
    Call the norms of inquiry zetetic norms. How are zetetic norms related to epistemic norms? At first glance, they seem quite closely connected. Aren't epistemic norms norms that bind inquirers qua inquirers? And isn't epistemology the place to look for a normative theory of inquiry? While much of this thought seems right, this paper argues that the relationship between the epistemic and the zetetic is not as harmonious as one might have thought and liked. In particular, this paper argues that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   134 citations  
  3. Why Suspend Judging?Jane Friedman - 2017 - Noûs 51 (2):302-326.
    In this paper I argue that suspension of judgment is intimately tied to inquiry and in particular that one is suspending judgment about some question if and only if one is inquiring into that question.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   190 citations  
  4. The aim of inquiry?Jane Friedman - 2024 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 108 (2):506-523.
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, EarlyView.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  5. The Methodology of Positive Economics.Milton Friedman - 1953 - In Essays in Positive Economics. University of Chicago Press. pp. 3-43.
  6. Question‐directed attitudes.Jane Friedman - 2013 - Philosophical Perspectives 27 (1):145-174.
    In this paper I argue that there is a class of attitudes that have questions (rather than propositions or something else) as contents.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   134 citations  
  7. What are friends for?: feminist perspectives on personal relationships and moral theory.Marilyn Friedman - 1993 - Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
    A contribution to the feminist discussion on moral theory, exploring the debate between moral impartiality and the partiality that characterizes personal relationships, the ethic of care and its relation to justice in a gender asymmetrical society, and the role of intimate friendship in an era of the dissolution of both extended and nuclear families.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  8.  48
    An exploration of social identity: The structure of the BBC news-sharing community on Twitter.Julius Adebayo, Musso Tiziana, Kawandeep Virdee, Casey Friedman & Bar-Yam Yaneer - 2014 - Complexity 19 (5):55-63.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9. Rational Agnosticism and Degrees of Belief.Jane Friedman - 2013 - Oxford Studies in Epistemology 4:57.
    There has been much discussion about whether traditional epistemology's doxastic attitudes are reducible to degrees of belief. In this paper I argue that what I call the Straightforward Reduction - the reduction of all three of believing p, disbelieving p, and suspending judgment about p, not-p to precise degrees of belief for p and not-p that ought to obey the standard axioms of the probability calculus - cannot succeed. By focusing on suspension of judgment (agnosticism) rather than belief, we can (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  10. Zetetic Epistemology.Jane Friedman - forthcoming - In Baron Reed & A. K. Flowerree, Towards an Expansive Epistemology: Norms, Action, and the Social Sphere. Routledge.
    In this paper I explore the contours of a picture of normative epistemology that speaks centrally to the question of how to inquire rather than just the question of what to believe. What if normative epistemology were expanded to encompass inquiry in full? I argue that while a 'zetetic epistemology' builds on traditional normative epistemology in many appealing ways, it also faces some challenges.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  11.  38
    The Machinery of Freedom.David Friedman - unknown
    Capitalism is the best. It's free enterprise. Barter. Gimbels, if I get really rank with the clerk, 'Well I don't like this', how I can resolve it? If it really gets ridiculous, I go, 'Frig it, man, I walk.' What can this guy do at Gimbels, even if he was the president of Gimbels? He can always reject me from that store, but I can always go to Macy's. He can't really hurt me. Communism is like one big phone company. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  12. Teleological epistemology.Jane Friedman - 2019 - Philosophical Studies 176 (3):673-691.
    It is typically thought that some epistemic states are valuable—knowing, truly or accurately believing, understanding. These are states it’s thought good to be in and it’s also said that we aim or want to be in them. It is then sometimes claimed that these sorts of thoughts about epistemic goods or values ground or explain our epistemic norms. For instance, we think subjects should follow their evidence when they form their beliefs. But why should they? Why not believe against the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  13.  62
    The Kantian Legacy in Nineteenth-Century Science.Michael Friedman & Alfred Nordmann (eds.) - 2006 - MIT Press.
    Historians of philosophy, science, and mathematics explore the influence of Kant's philosophy on the evolution of modern scientific thought.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  14. Zetetic Rights and Wrong(ing)s.Daniel C. Friedman - forthcoming - Philosophical Quarterly.
    What do we owe those with whom we inquire? Presumably, quite a bit. Anything beyond what is necessary to secure knowledge? Yes. In this paper, I argue for a class of ‘zetetic rights.’ These are rights distinctive to participants in group inquiry. Zetetic rights help protect important central interests of inquirers. These include a right to aid, a right against interference, and a right to exert influence over the course of inquiry. Building on arguments by Fricker (2015), I defend these (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. The Re-evaluation of Logical Positivism.Michael Friedman - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy 88 (10):505-519.
  16. The conceptual underpinnings of pretense: Pretending is not 'behaving-as-if.'.Ori Friedman & Alan M. Leslie - 2007 - Cognition 105 (1):103-124.
    The ability to engage in and recognize pretend play begins around 18 months. A major challenge for theories of pretense is explaining how children are able to engage in pretense, and how they are able to recognize pretense in others. According to one major account, the metarepresentational theory, young children possess both production and recognition abilities because they possess the mental state concept, PRETEND. According to a more recent rival account, the Behavioral theory, young children are behaviorists about pretense, and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  17.  21
    Patient Experiences with the Use of Telephone Interpreter Services: An Exploratory, Qualitative Study of Spanish-Speaking Patients at an Urban Community Health Center.Maria Garcia-Jimenez, Alessandra Calvo-Friedman, Karyn Singer & Michael Tanner - 2019 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 9 (2):149-162.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Synthetic history reconsidered.Michael Friedman - 2010 - In Michael Friedman, Mary Domski & Michael Dickson, Discourse on a New Method: Reinvigorating the Marriage of History and Philosophy of Science. Open Court.
  19. Regulative and constitutive.Michael Friedman - 1992 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 30 (S1):73-102.
  20. Popper, Weber, and Hayek: The epistemology and politics of ignorance.Jeffrey Friedman - 2005 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 17 (1-2):1-58.
    Karl Popper's methodology highlights our scientific ignorance: hence the need to institutionalize open‐mindedness through controlled experiments that may falsify our fallible theories about the world. In his endorsement of “piecemeal social engineering,” Popper assumes that the social‐democratic state and its citizens are capable of detecting social problems, and of assessing the results of policies aimed at solving them, through a process of experimentation analogous to that of natural science. But we are not only scientifically but politically ignorant: ignorant of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  21. The consistency of classical set theory relative to a set theory with intuitionistic logic.Harvey Friedman - 1973 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (2):315-319.
  22. Harvey Friedman's Research on the Foundations of Mathematics.Harvey Friedman & L. A. Harrington - 1985
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23. The Impracticality of Impartiality.Marilyn Friedman - 1989 - Journal of Philosophy 86 (11):645-656.
  24. (1 other version)Physicalism and the indeterminacy of translation.Michael Friedman - 1975 - Noûs 9 (4):353-374.
  25. Poincaré's conventionalism and the logical positivists.Michael Friedman - 1995 - Foundations of Science 1 (2):299-314.
    The logical positivists adopted Poincare's doctrine of the conventionality of geometry and made it a key part of their philosophical interpretation of relativity theory. I argue, however, that the positivists deeply misunderstood Poincare's doctrine. For Poincare's own conception was based on the group-theoretical picture of geometry expressed in the Helmholtz-Lie solution of the space problem, and also on a hierarchical picture of the sciences according to which geometry must be presupposed be any properly physical theory. But both of this pictures (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  26. Transcendental philosophy and a priori knowledge: A neo-Kantian perspective.Michael Friedman - 2000 - In Paul Artin Boghossian & Christopher Peacocke, New Essays on the A Priori. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
  27.  43
    Women in Philosophy.Marilyn Friedman - 2013 - In Katrina Hutchison & Fiona Jenkins, Women in Philosophy: What Needs to Change? New York, NY: Oxford University Press USA. pp. 21.
  28.  71
    Quantum Logic, Conditional Probability, and Interference.Michael Friedman & Hilary Putnam - 1978 - Dialectica 32 (3‐4):305-315.
  29. (1 other version)The ant colony as a test for scientific theories of consciousness.Daniel A. Friedman & Eirik Søvik - 2019 - Synthese (2):1-24.
    The appearance of consciousness in the universe remains one of the major mysteries unsolved by science or philosophy. Absent an agreed-upon definition of consciousness or even a convenient system to test theories of consciousness, a confusing heterogeneity of theories proliferate. In pursuit of clarifying this complicated discourse, we here interpret various frameworks for the scientific and philosophical study of consciousness through the lens of social insect evolutionary biology. To do so, we first discuss the notion of a forward test versus (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30. Reconsidering the dynamics of reason: Response to Ferrari, Mormann, Nordmann, and Uebel.Michael Friedman - 2012 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 43 (1):47-53.
  31. Scientific Disagreements, Fast Science and Higher-Order Evidence.Daniel C. Friedman & Dunja Šešelja - 2023 - Philosophy of Science 90 (4):937-957.
    Scientific disagreements are an important catalyst for scientific progress. But what happens when scientists disagree amidst times of crisis, when we need quick yet reliable policy guidance? In this paper we provide a normative account for how scientists facing disagreement in the context of ‘fast science’ should respond, and how policy makers should evaluate such disagreement. Starting from an argumentative, pragma-dialectic account of scientific controversies, we argue for the importance of ‘higher-order evidence’ (HOE) and we specify desiderata for scientifically relevant (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32. Whither relevant arithmetic?Harvey Friedman & Robert K. Meyer - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (3):824-831.
    Based on the relevant logic R, the system R# was proposed as a relevant Peano arithmetic. R# has many nice properties: the most conspicuous theorems of classical Peano arithmetic PA are readily provable therein; it is readily and effectively shown to be nontrivial; it incorporates both intuitionist and classical proof methods. But it is shown here that R# is properly weaker than PA, in the sense that there is a strictly positive theorem QRF of PA which is unprovable in R#. (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  33.  27
    On metaphors of mathematics: Between Blumenberg’s nonconceptuality and Grothendieck’s waves.Michael Friedman - 2024 - Synthese 203 (5):1-27.
    How can metaphors account for the formation of mathematical concepts, for changes in mathematical practices, or for the handling of mathematical problems? Following Hans Blumenberg’s thought, this paper aims to unfold a possible answer to these questions by viewing the metaphorical frameworks accompanying these changes as essential for an understanding of how changes in mathematical practices have been accounted for. I will focus especially on cases in which these changes were caused by encounters with a mathematical object which did not (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  47
    The number of normal measures.Sy-David Friedman & Menachem Magidor - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (3):1069-1080.
    There have been numerous results showing that a measurable cardinal κ can carry exactly α normal measures in a model of GCH, where a is a cardinal at most κ⁺⁺. Starting with just one measurable cardinal, we have [9] (for α = 1), [10] (for α = κ⁺⁺, the maximum possible) and [1] (for α = κ⁺, after collapsing κ⁺⁺) . In addition, under stronger large cardinal hypotheses, one can handle the remaining cases: [12] (starting with a measurable cardinal of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  35. Pettit's civic republicanism and male domination.Marilyn Friedman - 2008 - In Cecile Laborde & John Maynor, Republicanism and Political Theory. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  36.  43
    Regularity properties on the generalized reals.Sy David Friedman, Yurii Khomskii & Vadim Kulikov - 2016 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 167 (4):408-430.
  37. Wissenschaftslogik: The role of logic in the philosophy of science.Michael Friedman - 2008 - Synthese 164 (3):385-400.
    Carl Hempel introduced what he called "Craig's theorem" into the philosophy of science in a famous discussion of the "problem of theoretical terms." Beginning with Hempel's use of 'Craig's theorem," I shall bring out some of the key differences between Hempel's treatment of the "problem of theoretical terms" and Carnap's in order to illuminate the peculiar function of Wissenschaftslogik in Carnap's mature philosophy. Carnap's treatment, in particular, is fundamentally antimetaphysical—he aims to use the tools of mathematical logic to dissolve rather (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  38. Political Epistemology.Jeffrey Friedman - 2014 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 26 (1-2):i-xiv.
    ABSTRACTNormative political epistemologists, such as epistemic democrats, study whether political decision makers can, in principle, be expected to know what they need to know if they are to make wise public policy. Empirical political epistemologists study the content and sources of real-world political actors' knowledge and interpretations of knowledge. In recent years, empirical political epistemologists have taken up the study of the ideas of political actors other than voters, such as bureaucrats and politicians. Normative political epistemologists could follow this lead (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  39.  93
    Slow consistency.Sy-David Friedman, Michael Rathjen & Andreas Weiermann - 2013 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (3):382-393.
    The fact that “natural” theories, i.e. theories which have something like an “idea” to them, are almost always linearly ordered with regard to logical strength has been called one of the great mysteries of the foundation of mathematics. However, one easily establishes the existence of theories with incomparable logical strengths using self-reference . As a result, PA+Con is not the least theory whose strength is greater than that of PA. But still we can ask: is there a sense in which (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  40. Uniformly defined descending sequences of degrees.Harvey Friedman - 1976 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 41 (2):363-367.
  41. Tolerance, intuition, and empiricism.Michael Friedman - 2009 - In Pierre Wagner, Carnap's Logical syntax of language. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 236--249.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  42.  46
    The new consensus: I. The Fukuyama thesis.Jeffrey Friedman - 1989 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 3 (3-4):373-410.
    Fukuyama's argument that we have recently reached ?The End of History?; is defended against writers who fail to appreciate the Hegelian meaning of Fukuyama's ?Endism,?; but is criticized for using simplistic dichotomies that evade the economic and ideological convergence of East and West. Against Fukuyama, the economic critique of socialism, revisionist scholarship on early Soviet economic history, and the history of the libertarian ideas of Rousseau, Kant, Hegel and Marx are deployed to show that history ?ended?; years ago: the creeds (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  43.  50
    On recovery: re-directing the concept by differentiation of its meanings.Yael Friedman - 2021 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 24 (3):389-399.
    Recovery is a commonly used concept in both professional and everyday contexts. Yet despite its extensive use, it has not drawn much philosophical attention. In this paper, I question the common understanding of recovery, show how the concept is inadequate, and introduce new and much needed terminology. I argue that recovery glosses over important distinctions and even misrepresents the process of moving away from malady as "going back" to a former state of health. It does not invite important nuances needed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  11
    The Court of Reason and its Authority.Michael Friedman - 2021 - In Camilla Serck-Hanssen & Beatrix Himmelmann, The Court of Reason: Proceedings of the 13th International Kant Congress. De Gruyter. pp. 191-208.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  71
    Projective mad families.Sy-David Friedman & Lyubomyr Zdomskyy - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (12):1581-1587.
    Using almost disjoint coding we prove the consistency of the existence of a definable ω-mad family of infinite subsets of ω together with.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  46.  51
    (1 other version)Scientific Philosophy from Helmholtz to Carnap and Quine.Michael Friedman - 2012 - Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 16:1-11.
    The concept of a “scientific philosophy” first developed in the mid nineteenth century, as a reaction against what was viewed as the excessively speculative and metaphysical character of post-Kantian German idealism. One of the primary intellectual models of this movement was a celebrated address by Hermann von Helmholtz, “Über das Sehen des Menschen,” delivered at the dedication of a monument to Kant at Königsberg in 1855. Helmholtz begins by asking, on behalf of the audience, why a natural scientist like himself (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  47.  47
    Political Epistemology, Technocracy, and Political Anthropology: Reply to a Symposium on Power Without Knowledge.Jeffrey Friedman - 2020 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 32 (1):242-367.
    A political epistemology that enables us to determine if political actors are likely to know what they need to know must be rooted in an ontology of the actors and of the human objects of their knowledge; that is, a political anthropology. The political anthropology developed in Power Without Knowledge envisions human beings as creatures whose conscious actions are determined by their interpretations of what seem to them to be relevant circumstances; and whose interpretations are, in turn, determined by webs (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  49
    Postmodernism vs. Postlibertarianism.Jeffrey Friedman - 1991 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 5 (2):145-158.
    “Postmodernism” denotes efforts to replace foundationalist philosophy with contextu‐alist, immanentist forms of reason. “Postlibertarianism” denotes efforts to transcend contemporary minimal statism, questioning both its “libertarian” moral superstructure and its underlying consequentialist claims and seeking to determine whether the latter can be generalized in a way that displaces the former. Efforts to reach minimal‐statist conclusions by postmodern means seem bound to aggravate the problem that plagues contemporary minimal statism: its failure to be true to its consequentialist foundations, reflected in its long‐standing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  49.  81
    (1 other version)Was Spinoza fooled by the ontological argument?Joel I. Friedman - 1982 - Philosophia 11 (3-4):307-344.
  50. The contribution of rational choice theory to macrosociological research.Debra Friedman & Michael Hechter - 1988 - Sociological Theory 6 (2):201-218.
    Because it consists of an entire family of specific theories derived from the same first principles, rational choice offers one approach to generate explanations that provide for micro-macro links, and to attack a wide variety of empirical problems in macrosociology. The aims of this paper are (1) to provide a bare skeleton of all rational choice arguments; (2) to demonstrate their applicability to a range of macrosociological concerns by reviewing a sample of both new and classic works; and (3) to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
1 — 50 / 961