Results for 'Fred Kröger'

934 found
Order:
  1. Knowledge and the Flow of Information.Fred I. Dretske - 1981 - Stanford, CA: MIT Press.
    This book presents an attempt to develop a theory of knowledge and a philosophy of mind using ideas derived from the mathematical theory of communication developed by Claude Shannon. Information is seen as an objective commodity defined by the dependency relations between distinct events. Knowledge is then analyzed as information caused belief. Perception is the delivery of information in analog form for conceptual utilization by cognitive mechanisms. The final chapters attempt to develop a theory of meaning by viewing meaning as (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1010 citations  
  2. Misrepresentation.Fred Dretske - 1986 - In Radu J. Bogdan (ed.), Belief: Form, Content, and Function. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 17--36.
  3. (2 other versions)Conscious experience.Fred Dretske - 1993 - Mind 102 (406):263-283.
  4. Whistle-Blower Narratives: The Experience of Choiceless Choice.C. Fred Alford - 2007 - Social Research: An International Quarterly 74 (1):223-248.
    Most whistleblowers talk as if they never had a choice about whether to blow the whistle. This doesn't mean they acted suddenly, or impulsively, only that they believe they could not have done otherwise. Trying to make sense of this near universal answer to the question "Why did you do it?" the essay draws on narrative theory. Narrative theory distinguishes between actant and sender—that is, between actor and his or her values. This distinction helps to explain what it means to (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  5. Experience as representation.Fred Dretske - 2003 - Philosophical Issues 13 (1):67-82.
  6. (1 other version)Precis of knowledge and the flow of information.Fred I. Dretske - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):55-90.
    A theory of information is developed in which the informational content of a signal (structure, event) can be specified. This content is expressed by a sentence describing the condition at a source on which the properties of a signal depend in some lawful way. Information, as so defined, though perfectly objective, has the kind of semantic property (intentionality) that seems to be needed for an analysis of cognition. Perceptual knowledge is an information-dependent internal state with a content corresponding to the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   104 citations  
  7. Bringing science to life: A synthesis of the research evidence on the effects of context‐based and STS approaches to science teaching.Judith Bennett, Fred Lubben & Sylvia Hogarth - 2007 - Science Education 91 (3):347-370.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  8.  65
    Epistemology and Cognition.Fred Dretske - 1988 - Journal of Philosophy 85 (5):265-270.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   96 citations  
  9. How do you know you are not a zombie.Fred Dretske - 2003 - In Brie Gertler (ed.), Privileged Access: Philosophical Accounts of Self-Knowledge. Ashgate. pp. 1--14.
  10.  44
    Intuitionism As Generalization.Fred Richman - 1990 - Philosophia Mathematica (1-2):124-128.
  11.  24
    The Structure of Biological Science.Fred Gifford - 1991 - Noûs 25 (1):123-125.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  12. The semantics of fictional names.Fred Adams, Gary Fuller & Robert Stecker - 1997 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 78 (2):128–148.
    In this paper we defend a direct reference theory of names. We maintain that the meaning of a name is its bearer. In the case of vacuous names, there is no bearer and they have no meaning. We develop a unified theory of names such that one theory applies to names whether they occur within or outside fiction. Hence, we apply our theory to sentences containing names within fiction, sentences about fiction or sentences making comparisons across fictions. We then defend (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  13.  26
    Philosophy, Evolution and Human Nature.Fred Gifford - 1985 - Philosophical Review 94 (4):602.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  14. (1 other version)Types and ontology.Fred Sommers - 1963 - Philosophical Review 72 (3):327-363.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  15. Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language: An Elementary Exposition.Fred Feldman - 1986 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 46 (4):683-687.
  16. Borel sets and Ramsey's theorem.Fred Galvin & Karel Prikry - 1973 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (2):193-198.
  17. The termination thesis.Fred Feldman - 2000 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 24 (1):98–115.
    The Termination Thesis (or “TT”) is the view that people go out of existence when they die. Lots of philosophers seem to believe it. Epicurus, for example, apparently makes use of TT in his efforts to show that it is irrational to fear death. He says, “as long as we exist, death is not with us; but when death comes, then we do not exist.”1 Lucretius says pretty much the same thing, but in many more words and more poetically: “Death (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  18. Minimal rationality.Fred I. Dretske - 2006 - In Susan Hurley & Matthew Nudds (eds.), Rational Animals? Oxford University Press.
  19. Philosophy of Medicine.Fred Gifford (ed.) - 2011 - Boston: Elsevier.
    This volume covers a wide range of conceptual, epistemological and methodological issues in the philosophy of science raised by reflection upon medical science and practice.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  20.  65
    Community-equipoise and the ethics of randomized clinical trials.Fred Gifford - 1995 - Bioethics 9 (2):127–148.
    This paper critically examines a particular strategy for resolving the central ethical dilemma associated with randomized clinical trials — the “community equipoise” strategy . The dilemma is that RCTs appear to violate a physician's duty to choose that therapy which there is most reason to believe is in the patient's best interest, randomizing patients even once evidence begins to favor one treatment. The community equipoise strategy involves the suggestion that our judgment that neither treatment is to be preferred is to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  21.  98
    Characterization and existence in modal meinongianism.Fred Kroon - 2012 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 86 (1):23-34.
  22. Empty names and pragmatic implicatures.Fred Adams & Gary Fuller - 2007 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (3):449-461.
    What are the meanings of empty names such as ‘Vulcan,’ ‘Pegasus,’ and ‘Santa Claus’ in such sentences as ‘Vulcan is the tenth planet,’ ‘Pegasus flies,’ and especially ‘Santa Claus does not exist’?Our view, developed in Adams et al., consists of a direct-reference account of the meaning of empty names in combination with a pragmatic-implicature account of why we have certain intuitions that seem to conflict with a direct-reference account.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  23.  75
    The conflict between randomized clinical trials and the therapeutic obligation.Fred Gifford - 1986 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 11 (4):347-366.
    The central dilemma concerning randomized clinical trials (RCTs) arises out of some simple facts about causal methodology (RCTs are the best way to generate the reliable causal knowledge necessary for optimally-informed action) and a prima facie plausible principle concerning how physicians should treat their patients (always do what it is most reasonable to believe will be best for the patient). A number of arguments related to this in the literature are considered. Attempts to avoid the dilemma fail. Appeals to informed (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  24. (1 other version)The ordinary language tree.Fred Sommers - 1959 - Mind 68 (270):160-185.
    No categories
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  25. What good is consciousness?Fred Dretske - 1997 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27 (1):1-15.
    If consciousness is good for something, conscious things must differ in some causally relevant way from unconscious things. If they do not, then, as Davies and Humphreys conclude, too bad for consciousness: ‘psychological theory need not be concerned with this topic.’Davies and Humphreys are applying a respectable metaphysical idea — the idea, namely, that if an object's having a property does not make a difference to what that object does, if the object's causal powers are in no way enhanced by (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  26.  64
    The Challenge of TBL: A Responsibility to Whom?Fred Robins - 2006 - Business and Society Review 111 (1):1-14.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  27. Structural ontology.Fred Sommers - 1971 - Philosophia 1 (1-2):21-42.
  28.  65
    So-called "clinical equipoise" and the argument from design.Fred Gifford - 2007 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 32 (2):135 – 150.
    In this article, I review and expand upon arguments showing that Freedman's so-called "clinical equipoise" criterion cannot serve as an appropriate guide and justification for the moral legitimacy of carrying out randomized clinical trials. At the same time, I try to explain why this approach has been given so much credence despite compelling arguments against it, including the fact that Freedman's original discussion framed the issues in a misleading way, making certain things invisible: Clinical equipoise is conflated with community equipoise, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  29.  62
    Freedman's 'clinical equipoise' and sliding-scale all-dimensions-considered equipoise'.Fred Gifford - 2000 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25 (4):399 – 426.
    It is often claimed that a clinical investigator may ethically participate (e.g., enroll patients) in a trial only if she is in equipoise (if she has no way to ground a preference for one arm of the study). But this is a serious problem, for as data accumulate, it can be expected that there will be a discernible trend favoring one of the treatments prior to the point where we achieve the trial's objective. In this paper, I critically evaluate Benjamin (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  30. The Unity of Reason: Essays in Kant’s Philosophy.Fred L. Rush, Dieter Henrich, Richard Velkley, Guenter Zoeller, Manfred Kuehn, Louis Hunt, Jeffrey Edwards, Eckart Forster, Abraham Anderson & Taylor Carman - 1998 - Journal of Philosophy 95 (3):149.
  31. Dretske's replies.Fred Dretske - 1991 - In Dretske and His Critics. Cambridge: Blackwell.
  32.  61
    Axiomatic thermodynamics and extensive measurement.Fred S. Roberts & R. Duncan Luce - 1968 - Synthese 18 (4):311 - 326.
  33. Narrow content: Fodor's folly.Fred Adams, David Drebushenko, Gary Fuller & Robert Stecker - 1990 - Mind and Language 5 (3):213-29.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  34.  85
    Marras on Sellars on thought and language.Fred Wilson - 1975 - Philosophical Studies 28 (August):91-102.
  35.  19
    Reason and Morality.Fred Feldman - 1983 - Noûs 17 (3):475-482.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  36. Absent qualia.Fred Dretske - 1996 - Mind and Language 11 (1):78-85.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  37.  18
    How can we collectivise a set of visions about social epistemology?Fred D'Agostino - unknown
  38.  85
    Names, contents, and causes.Fred Adams & Gary Fuller - 1992 - Mind and Language 7 (3):205-21.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  39. The Metaphysics of Freedom.Fred Dretske - 1992 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (1):1-13.
    I offer Jimmy a dollar to wiggle his ears. He wiggles them because he wants the dollar and, as a result of my offer, thinks he will earn it by wiggling his ears. So I cause him to believe something that explains, or helps to explain, why he wiggles his ears. If I push a button, and a bell, wired to the button, rings because the button is depressed, I cause the bell to ring. I make it ring. Indeed, I (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  40. Autonomy.Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller & Jeffrey Paul - 2007 - Philosophical Quarterly 57 (227):311-313.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  41.  69
    Where people don't promise.Fred Korn & Shulamit R. Decktor Korn - 1982 - Ethics 93 (3):445-450.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  42.  45
    Stenius on the paradoxes.Fred Kroon - 1984 - Theoria 50 (2-3):178-211.
  43.  32
    Distribution matters.Fred Sommers - 1975 - Mind 84 (333):27-46.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  44. Putting information to work.Fred Dretske - 1990 - In Philip P. Hanson (ed.), Information, Language and Cognition. University of British Columbia Press.
  45.  77
    Church's thesis without tears.Fred Richman - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (3):797-803.
    The modern theory of computability is based on the works of Church, Markov and Turing who, starting from quite different models of computation, arrived at the same class of computable functions. The purpose of this paper is the show how the main results of the Church-Markov-Turing theory of computable functions may quickly be derived and understood without recourse to the largely irrelevant theories of recursive functions, Markov algorithms, or Turing machines. We do this by ignoring the problem of what constitutes (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46.  50
    Kung-sun lung, designated things, and logic.Fred Rieman - 1980 - Philosophy East and West 30 (3):305-319.
  47.  21
    Intuitionistic notions of boundedness in ℕ.Fred Richman - 2009 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 55 (1):31-36.
    We consider notions of boundedness of subsets of the natural numbers ℕ that occur when doing mathematics in the context of intuitionistic logic. We obtain a new characterization of the notion of a pseudobounded subset and we formulate the closely related notion of a detachably finite subset. We establish metric equivalents for a subset of ℕ to be detachably finite and to satisfy the ascending chain condition. Following Ishihara, we spell out the relationship between detachable finiteness and sequential continuity. Most (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48. The enigma of death.Fred Feldman - 1992 - Philosophia 21 (3-4):163-181.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49.  10
    Shame-Sensitive Public Health.Fred Cooper, Luna Dolezal & Arthur Rose - forthcoming - Journal of Medical Humanities:1-15.
    In this article, we argue that shaming interventions and messages during Covid-19 have drawn the relationship between public health and shame into a heightened state of contention, offering us a valuable opportunity to reconsider shame as a desired outcome of public health work, and to push back against the logics of individual responsibility and blame for illness and disease on which it sits. We begin by defining shame and demonstrating how it is conceptually and practically distinct from stigma. We then (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. (1 other version)The Logic of Probabilities in Hume's Argument against Miracles.Fred Wilson - 1989 - Hume Studies 15 (2):255-276.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Logic of Probabilities in Hume's Argument against Miracles Fred Wilson The position is often stated that Hume's discussion of miracles is inconsistent with his views on the logical or ontological status oflaws ofnature and with his more general scepticism. Broad, for one, has so argued.1 Hume's views on induction are assumed to go somethinglike this. Any attempt to demonstrate knowledge ofmatters offact presupposes causal reasoning, but the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
1 — 50 / 934