Results for ' desire‐based theories of reasons for action'

972 found
Order:
  1. (1 other version)Desire-Based Theories of Reasons, Pleasure and Welfare.Chris Heathwood - 2011 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 6:79-106.
    One of the most important disputes in the foundations of ethics concerns the source of practical reasons. On the desire-based view, only one’s desires provide one with reasons to act. On the value-based view, reasons are instead provided by the objective evaluative facts, and never by our desires. Similarly, there are desire-based and non-desired-based theories about two other phenomena: pleasure and welfare. It has been argued, and is natural to think, that holding a desire-based theory about (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  2. Reasons for actions and desires.Ulrike Heuer - 2004 - Philosophical Studies 121 (1):43–63.
    It is an assumption common to many theories of rationality that all practical reasons are based on a person's given desires. I shall call any approach to practical reasons which accepts this assumption a "Humean approach". In spite of many criticisms, the Humean approach has numerous followers who take it to be the natural and inevitable view of practical reason. I will develop an argument against the Humean view aiming to explain its appeal, as well as to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  3. Desire-Based Theories of Reasons and the Guise of the Good.Kael McCormack - 2023 - Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 9 (47):1288-1321.
    I propose an account of desire that reconciles two apparently conflicting intuitions about practical agency. I do so by exploring a certain intuitive datum. The intuitive datum is that often when an agent desires P she will seem to immediately and conclusively know that there is a reason to bring P about. Desire-based theories of reasons seem uniquely placed to explain this intuitive datum. On this view, desires are the source of an agent’s practical reasons. A desire (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  4.  10
    Reasons for Action.Jonathan Dancy - 2000 - In Practical Reality. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Introduces various distinctions: between the reasons why we should act, those for which we act, and the reasons why we act. It also distinguishes between Humeanism and anti‐Humeanism in the theory of motivation, psychologism, and anti‐psychologism in the theory of motivation, internalism, and externalism and desire‐based and value‐based theories of normative reasons.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  40
    Value-Based Theories of Reasons and Matters of Taste: Aquinas on the Limitations of Reason Alone.Seyyed Mohsen Eslami - 2018 - Divus Thomas 121 (3):371-377.
    In this paper, I explore one line of argument for the Humean Theory of Reasons, the view that all normative reasons are based on desires. Then, I suggest a way to block that argument inspired by Aquinas’s discussions on choice, will, and indeterminacy of reason alone.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Moral Virtue and Reasons for Action.Michelle N. Mason - 2001 - Dissertation, The University of Chicago
    This dissertation urges philosophers to reevaluate how they frame the question of the rationality of moral action. Its motivation is the thought that approaches to the question have suffered from mistakes in the relata. On the part of theories of practical reason, philosophers adopt an inadequate theory of action. On the part of moral theory, philosophers hold narrow conceptions of moral worth. As a result, not only have we failed to vindicate the thought that the moral agent (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  55
    Kant's Theory of Motivation and Rational Agency.Paula Satne - 2009 - Dissertation, The University of Manchester
    It is clear that Kant's theory of motivation plays a central role in his ethical theory as a whole. Nevertheless, it has been subjected to many interpretations: (i) the 'orthodox' interpretation, (ii) the 'Aristotelian' or 'Humean' interpretation and (iii) the 'rationalist' interpretation. The first part of the thesis aims to provide an interpretation of Kant's theory of rational agency and motivation. I argue that the 'orthodox' and 'Aristotelian' interpretations should be rejected because they are incompatible with Kant's conception of freedom, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. An Empirical Theory of Practical Reasons and its Use for Practical Philosophy.Christoph Lumer - 2007 - In Christoph Lumer & Sandro Nannini (eds.), Intentionality, deliberation and autonomy: the action-theoretic basis of practical philosophy. Ashgate Publishing. pp. 157-186.
    In the first part (sections 2-5) an empirical theory of practical reasons is sketched and defended. It consists of: hypotheses about what intentions are, namely optimality beliefs, (2), hypotheses about how intentions are formed on the basis of probabilistic beliefs and intrinsic desires (3), a pluralist theory about intrinsic desires (4) and a theory about motives for moral action (5). In the second part (sections 6-8) it is argued that normative practical philosophy must rely on empirical theories (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  77
    Goals of action and emotional reasons for action. A modern version of the theory of ultimate psychological hedonism.Ulrich Mees & Annette Schmitt - 2008 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 38 (2):157–178.
    In this paper we present a modern version of the classic theory of “ultimate psychological hedonism” . As does the UPH, our two-dimensional model of metatelic orientations also postulates a fundamentally hedonistic motivation for any human action. However, it makes a distinction between “telic” or content-based goals of actions and “metatelic” or emotional reasons for actions. In our view, only the emotional reasons for action, but not the goals of action, conform to the UPH. After (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  3
    Reasons for Action as Events and States.А. А Санженаков - 2024 - Siberian Journal of Philosophy 21 (4):87-95.
    The article examines the ontological status of reasons for action. There are two positions: the reasons for actions (desires and beliefs) are construed either as states or dispositions, or as events. Anticausalists believe that reasons for actions are states and therefore they cannot be causes of actions, since causation is possible only between events. D. Davidson argues against this view, showing, on the one hand, that our mental states can be causal conditions, and, on the other (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  16
    The Influence of Guanxi Between Boundary Spanners on Opportunistic Behaviors Based on the Theory of Reasoned Action Model.Shu-Kuan Zhao & Jia-Ming Cai - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    This study constructs a mechanism of the influence of Guanxi between boundary spanners on opportunistic behaviors in collaborative innovation projects based on the theory of reasoned action model. The study conducts a survey in the automobile industry in Changchun, Jilin Province, China, and analyzes the research data using the structural equation model. The findings show that Guanxi has a negative an significant influence on opportunistic behavior attitudes and subjective norms., Guanxi has the greater influence on subjective norms than attitudes. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Can Desires Provide Reasons for Action.Ruth Chang - 2004 - In R. Jay Wallace, Philip Pettit, Samuel Scheffler & Michael Smith (eds.), Reason and Value: Themes From the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz. New York: Clarendon Press. pp. 56--90.
    What sorts of consideration can be normative reasons for action? If we systematize the wide variety of considerations that can be cited as normative reasons, do we find that there is a single kind of consideration that can always be a reason? Desire-based theorists think that the fact that you want something or would want it under certain evaluatively neutral conditions can always be your normative reason for action. Value-based theorists, by contrast, think that what plays (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  13. Group-based reasons for action.Christopher Woodard - 2003 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 6 (2):215-229.
    This article endorses a familiar, albeit controversial, argument for the existence of group-based reasons for action, but then rejects two doctrines which other advocates of such reasons usually accept. One such doctrine is the willingness requirement, which says that a group-based reason exists only if (sufficient) other members of the group in question are willing to cooperate. Thus the paper argues that there is sometimes a reason, which derives from the rationality of some group action, to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  14.  13
    Practical Argumentation in the Making: Discursive Construction of Reasons for Action.Marcin Lewiński - 2018 - In Sarah Bigi & Fabrizio Macagno (eds.), Argumentation and Language — Linguistic, Cognitive and Discursive Explorations. Cham: Springer Verlag.
    The goal of this chapter is to catalogue ways in which practical argumentation —argumentation aimed at deciding on a course of action—is produced discursively in deliberative discussions. This is a topic largely neglected in the literature on PA focused primarily on the abstract features of practical inference. I connect to this literature by arguing that the complex scheme of PA inferentially hinges on three different principles for rationally selecting means to achieve the desired goal: the means have to be (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15. A Theory of Reasons for Action.David A. J. Richards - 1976 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 6 (3):607-623.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  16. Additive Theories of Rationality: A Critique.Matthew Boyle - 2016 - European Journal of Philosophy 24 (3):527-555.
    Additive theories of rationality, as I use the term, are theories that hold that an account of our capacity to reflect on perceptually-given reasons for belief and desire-based reasons for action can begin with an account of what it is to perceive and desire, in terms that do not presuppose any connection to the capacity to reflect on reasons, and then can add an account of the capacity for rational reflection, conceived as an independent (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   89 citations  
  17.  38
    Reasons for action: Wittgensteinian and Davidsonian perspectives in historical and meta-philosophical context.Hans Johann Glock - unknown
    My paper reflects on the debate about reasons for action and action explanations between Wittgensteinian teleological approaches and causalist theories inspired by Davidson. After a brief discussion of similarities and differences in the philosophy of language, I sketch the prehistory and history of the controversy. I show that the conflict between Wittgenstein and Davidson revolves neither around revisionism nor around naturalism. Even in the philosophy of mind and action, Davidson is not as remote from Wittgenstein (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Reasons for Action: Wittgensteinian and Davidsonian perspectives in historical, meta-philosophical and philosophical context.Hans-Johann Glock - 2014 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 3 (1):7-46.
    My paper reflects on the debate about reasons for action and action explanations between Wittgensteinian teleological approaches and causalist theories inspired by Davidson. After a brief discussion of similarities and differences in the philosophy of language, I sketch the prehistory and history of the controversy. I show that the conflict between Wittgenstein and Davidson revolves neither around revisionism nor around naturalism. Even in the philosophy of mind and action, Davidson is not as remote from Wittgenstein (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  19.  56
    Julia Markovits: Moral Reason: Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2014, 224 p. , £35.00. [REVIEW]David Rocheleau-Houle - 2015 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 18 (3):663-664.
    Julia Markovits’ Moral Reason is a defense of internalism about moral reasons and a desire-based account of reasons for action. Even though she defends this position, she does not consider herself committed to relativism and to a desire-based understanding of what reasons there are. Indeed, it is crucial to make a distinction between two kinds of inquiry about reasons for action. On one side, we find “analytic inquiry” where the purpose is to define what (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  74
    A theory of reasons for action.David A. J. Richards - 1971 - Oxford,: Clarendon Press.
  21. Desire-based Reasons, Naturalism, and the Possibility of Vindication.Attila Tanyi - 2009 - Polish Journal of Philosophy 3 (2):87-107.
    The aim of the paper is to critically assess the idea that reasons for action are provided by desires (the Model). I start from the claim that the most often employed meta-ethical background for the Model is ethical naturalism; I then argue against the Model through its naturalist background. For the latter purpose I make use of two objections that are both intended to refute naturalism per se. One is G. E. Moore’s Open Question Argument (OQA), the other (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  20
    The normativity of what we care about: a love-based theory of practical reasons.Katrien Schaubroeck - 2013 - Leuven: Leuven University Press.
    A love-based reason theory as a new perspective in the debate on practical reasons. Reasons and obligations pervade our lives. The alarm clock gives us a reason to get up in the morning, the expectations of colleagues or clients give us a reason to do our jobs well, the misery in developing countries gives us a reason to donate money, headaches give us a reason to take an aspirin. Looking for unity in variety, philosophers wonder what makes a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Moral knowledge and ethical character.Robert Audi - 1997 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This book offers a unified collection of published and unpublished papers by Robert Audi, a renowned defender of the rationalist position in ethics. Taken together, the essays present a vigorous, broadly-based argument in moral epistemology and a related account of reasons for action and their bearing on moral justification and moral character. Part I details Audi's compelling moral epistemology while Part II offers a unique vision of ethical concepts and an account of moral explanation, as well as a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  24.  69
    From Morality to the End of Reason: An Essay on Rights, Reasons, and Responsibility.Ingmar Persson - 2013 - New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
    Many philosophers think that if you're morally responsible for a state of affairs, you must be a cause of it. Ingmar Persson argues that this strand of common sense morality is asymmetrical, in that it features the act-omission doctrine, according to which there are stronger reasons against performing some harmful actions than in favour of performing any beneficial actions. He analyses the act-omission doctrine as consisting in a theory of negative rights, according to which there are rights not to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  25. Sobel on Pleasure, Reason, and Desire.Attila Tanyi - 2011 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 14 (1):101-115.
    The paper begins with a well-known objection to the idea that reasons for action are provided by desires. The objection holds that since desires are based on reasons (first premise), which they transmit but to which they cannot add (second premise), they cannot themselves provide reasons for action. In the paper I investigate an attack that has recently been launched against the first premise of the argument by David Sobel. Sobel invokes a counterexample: hedonic desires, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26. A Theory of Reasons for Action.[author unknown] - 1973 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 163:494-494.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  27.  27
    Desire-based and Value-based Nomative Reasons.Julian Savulescu - 1999 - Bioethics 13 (5):405-413.
    This paper is a response to John Harris’ provocative ‘Justice and Equal Opportunities in Health Care’. The aim of this short response is to locate the difference between Harris and me within a broader debate about the nature of reasons for action. I argue that Harris is appealing to a desire‐based conception of normative reasons. I highlight some of the deficiencies of a desire‐based conception of reasons, and contrast it with a value‐based account.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  28.  29
    A Theory of Reasons for Action.G. R. Grice - 1974 - Philosophical Review 83 (1):139.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  31
    Beliefs, Desires, Weak Intentionality and the Identity of the History of Ideas.Robert Lamb - 2011 - Intellectual History Review 21 (1):85-94.
    The question why Bevir's account of intentionality is conceptualized purely in terms of individual beliefs is important as such a conceptualization appears to depart from standard accounts of intentionality within the philosophy of mind, that include reference to individual desires. It is beliefs and desires which are usually considered the rock?bottom components of individual intentional states, yet Bevir defines weak intentions solely in terms of the former while explicitly rejecting attention to the latter. There are a number of difficulties which (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  19
    Aufgeklärtes Eigeninteresse. Eine Theorie theoretischer und praktischer Rationalität [Enlightened Self-Interest. A Theory of Theoretical and Practical Rationality].Stefan Gosepath - 1992 - Frankfurt am Main, Deutschland: Suhrkamp.
    The subject of my dissertation is "rationality". In this book I undertake a comprehensive, systematic and independent treatment of the problem of rationality. This furthers progress toward a general theory of rationality, one that represents and defends a uniform conception of reason. The structure and general outline are as follows: Part I: General Definition of the Concept; Part II: Rationality in the Theoretical Realm; Part III: Rationality in the Practical Realm (parts II and III are divided respectively into A. Relative (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  31.  26
    A Theory of Reasons for Action. By David A. J. Richards. Oxford and Toronto: Oxford University Press. 1971. xiv, 370. $15.50. [REVIEW]Jan Narveson - 1973 - Dialogue 12 (1):116-120.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  17
    A Theory of Fan-Type Dissociation.Martin Camper - 2020 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 53 (4):433-449.
    ABSTRACT One of the most important developments in twentieth-century rhetorical theory is Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca's insight that concepts, when under strain, can be split or dissociated into two separate terms. Not a simple binary, these terms remain interconnected in a value hierarchy with one term serving as the normative frame for the other. Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca theorize that either term can be dissociated further, producing a fan-type dissociation. Unlike ordinary dissociations, fan-types place three or more terms in hierarchical relationship, resulting (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Prudence, Morality, and the Humean Theory of Reasons.Eden Lin - 2015 - Philosophical Quarterly 65 (259):220-240.
    Humeans about normative reasons claim that there is a reason for you to perform a given action if and only if this would promote the satisfaction of one of your desires. Their view has traditionally been thought to have the revisionary implication that an agent can sometimes lack any reason to do what morality or prudence requires. Recently, however, Mark Schroeder has denied this. If he is right, then the Humean theory accords better with common sense than it (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  34. An Adam Smithian account of moral reasons.Nir Ben-Moshe - 2020 - European Journal of Philosophy 28 (4):1073-1087.
    The Humean Theory of Reasons, according to which all of our reasons for action are explained by our desires, has been criticized for not being able to account for “moral reasons,” namely, overriding reasons to act on moral demands regardless of one's desires. My aim in this paper is to utilize ideas from Adam Smith's moral philosophy in order to offer a novel and alternative account of moral reasons that is both desire-based and accommodating (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35.  50
    The Constitution of Constitutivism.Olof Leffler - 2019 - Dissertation, University of Leeds
    Why be moral? According to constitutivism, there are features constitutive of agency, actual or ideal, the properties of which explain why moral norms are normative for us. I aim to investigate whether this idea is plausible. I start off critically. After defining constitutivism and outlining its attractions and problems (chapter 1), I discuss the theories of various features of agency that are supposed to ground morality according to the leading constitutivists in the literature. I find these theories wanting. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  7
    Against Exclusionary Reasons as Only Razian Facts.Carlos Gálvez Bermúdez - 2025 - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 38 (1):51-71.
    Legal rules are often understood in terms of exclusionary reasons, and exclusionary reasons are normally understood as reasons for action according to R az. In this paper, I engage with the literature on the _metaphysics of reasons for action_ and explain how exclusionary reasons can be used in different conceptions of what reasons for action _are_ (and not only by the one defended by J oseph R az ). To do that, I (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  79
    Review of Non-Bayesian Decision Theory. Beliefs and Desires as Reasons for Action[REVIEW]Mikaël Cozic - 2011 - Economics and Philosophy 27 (1):53-59.
  38. Kant's Theory of Moral Motivation: The Construction of a Rationalist Internalism.Mark Timmons - 1982 - Dissertation, The University of Nebraska - Lincoln
    My aim in this work is to consider Kant's ethical theory against the background of the main traditions in ethics which Kant opposed, especially ethical empiricism. I argue that the central issue that divided Kant and the opposed traditions concerns moral motivation. As Kant characterized ethical empiricism, and in general all opposed ethical theories, such theories adopted an Aristotelian view of human motivation according to which all action is based on desires. Kant argued that such ethical (...) did not allow for the possibility of moral action--action based on purely rational motives, independent of desires. Kant thus rejected the Aristotelian view as adequate to explain the possibility of moral motivation and constructed an alternative view. I maintain that Kant wanted to construct a view according to which motivation is "internal to" moral reasons, as the empiricists maintained, yet such reasons are independent of human desire, i.e., "objective," as the rationalists maintained. I call this view of motivation, Kant's 'rational internalism.' ;My work is comprised of an introduction, eight chapters and a conclusion. Chapter 1 concerns the central question of Kant's ethical works: "How is morality possible?" which I claim should be read as a question about the possibility of moral motivation. In Chapters 2 and 3, I investigate empiricism in ethics, and in particular, the ethical views of Hobbes, Hutcheson and Hume. Chapters 4 through 7 contain my analysis of Kant's central criticism of ethical empiricism , and in Chapter 8 I present Kant's theory of moral motivation. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. The Master of the Passions? An Examination of the Role of Reason in Action.Paul Griseri - 1988 - Dissertation, University of Kent at Canterbury (United Kingdom)
    Available from UMI in association with The British Library. ;Is reason the slave of the passions? In Part I it is argued that neither the humean nor the kantian answers to this question can be maintained simpliciter. Each side of the controversy has to make significant concessions to the other. One consequence of this is that humean and kantian approaches to action are less clearly distinguished than might initially be supposed. ;In Part II several central notions are examined. The (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  55
    Theories of Practical Reason.Eric Wiland - 2002 - Metaphilosophy 33 (4):450-467.
    Leading theories of practical reason can be grouped into one of four families: psychologism, realism, compatibilism, and Aristotelianism. Although there are many differences among the theories within each family, I ignore these in order to ask which family is most likely to deliver a satisfactory philosophical account of reasons for action. I articulate three requirements we should expect any adequate theory of practical reason to meet: it should account for how reasons explain action, how (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  71
    Movement! Action! Belief?: notes for a critique of deleuze's cinema philosophy.J. M. Bernstein - 2012 - Angelaki 17 (4):77-93.
    Deleuze's philosophy of cinema departs from the standard conception of modernist aesthetics that sees art withdrawing from representation in order to reflect upon the specificity of its medium. While ambitious and influential, Deleuze's attempt fails. Overdetermined by its own metaphysics, it forsakes the real importance of the movies. It is unable to explain how they function and why they matter. This essay pursues three lines of criticism: Deleuze cannot account for the aesthetic specificity of cinema because he deposes the primacy (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  66
    A Humean explanation of acting on normative reasons.Elizabeth Radcliffe - 2020 - Synthese 199 (1-2):1269-1292.
    This article presents a limited defense of Humeanism about practical reason. Jonathan Dancy and other traditional objective-reasons theorists argue that all practical reasons, what we think about when we deliberate, are facts or states of affairs in the world. On the Humean view, the reasons that motivate us are belief-desire combinations, which are in the mind. Thus, Dancy and others reject Humeanism on the grounds that it cannot allow that anyone acts from a normative reason. I argue, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Reasons for Being Flexible. Desires, Intentions, and Plans.Piotr T. Makowski - 2016 - In Timo Airaksinen (ed.), Desire: The Concept and its Practical Context. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers. pp. 59-78.
    The structure of this paper is as follows. My starting point is psychological flexibility (henceforth, PF) as it has been presented in psychology. Here I offer a synthetic view which embraces the most crucial aspects of flexibility, and describes its functional roles and underlying mechanisms. Secondly, I move my attention onto the field of current action theory and discuss two elementary concepts we commonly use when describing our actions: intention and desire. Of course, there are many “theories of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  9
    Hume e o debate contempor'neo sobre as razões motivantes.André Chagas Ferreira de Souza - 2023 - Educação E Filosofia 37 (80):899-932.
    Resumo: Este artigo busca colocar a filosofia de David Hume diante de algumas teorias contemporâneas a respeito do tema das razões para agir ou motivantes. Há certa dificuldade em se afirmar que Hume aborda as razões motivantes, um conceito contemporâneo voltado a explicar aquilo que efetivamente impele um agente e referente ao lugar do desejo e da crença. Há dois grupos, intitulados respectivamente como humeanos e não-humeanos, de modo que para o primeiro, supostamente mais alinhado a Hume, o desejo tem (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Reason and Desire: The Case of Affective Desires.Attila Tanyi - 2010 - European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 6 (2):67-89.
    The paper begins with an objection to the Desire-Based Reasons Model. The argument from reason-based desires holds that since desires are based on reasons (first premise), which they transmit but to which they cannot add (second premise), they cannot themselves provide reasons for action. In the paper I investigate an attack that has recently been launched against the first premise of this argument by Ruth Chang. Chang invokes a counterexample: affective desires. The aim of the paper (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46. Desire-based Reasons, Naturalism, and Tolerable Revisionism: Lessons from Moore and Parfit.Attila Tanyi - 2009 - Cuadernos de Anuario Filosófico 212:49-57.
    My aim in this paper is to critically assess the idea that reasons for action are provided by desires (the Desire-based Reasons Model or the Model). I start from the claim that the most often employed meta-ethical background for the Model is ethical naturalism; I then consider attempts to argue against the Model through its naturalism. I make use of two objections that are both intended to refute naturalism per se. One is the indirect version of G. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. (1 other version)Desires, values, reasons, and the dualism of practical reason.Michael Smith - 2009 - Ratio 22 (1):98-125.
    In On What Matters Derek Parfit argues that facts about reasons for action are grounded in facts about values and against the view that they are grounded in facts about the desires that subjects would have after fully informed and rational deliberation. I describe and evaluate Parfit's arguments for this value-based conception of reasons for action and find them wanting. I also assess his response to Sidgwick's suggestion that there is a Dualism of Practical Reason. Parfit (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  48.  43
    Parameterized Complexity of Theory of Mind Reasoning in Dynamic Epistemic Logic.Iris van de Pol, Iris van Rooij & Jakub Szymanik - 2018 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 27 (3):255-294.
    Theory of mind refers to the human capacity for reasoning about others’ mental states based on observations of their actions and unfolding events. This type of reasoning is notorious in the cognitive science literature for its presumed computational intractability. A possible reason could be that it may involve higher-order thinking. To investigate this we formalize theory of mind reasoning as updating of beliefs about beliefs using dynamic epistemic logic, as this formalism allows to parameterize ‘order of thinking.’ We prove that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49.  11
    Acting for reasons : a grass root approach.Ralf Stoecher - 2009 - In Constantine Sandis (ed.), New essays on the explanation of action. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 276-292.
    There are many accounts of what it is to act for a reason. Yet, most of these accounts are committed to what might be called the standard theory of human agency. According to the standard theory actions are events that result from the agent's having mental attitudes of a specific kind (e.g. a pair of beliefs and desires or a particular intention), which on the one hand cause the event and on the other hand show it to be reasonable from (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  89
    The Mirage of Motivation Reason Internalism.Saleh Afroogh - 2022 - Journal of Value Inquiry 58 (1):111-129.
    What is it for an agent to have a reason to do a certain action? Does this mean that she would desire to do the action under specified conditions, or that there is some external consideration, which she ought to follow? The former affective (i.e., desire-based) theory is ascribed to Humeans, whereas the latter cognitive theory is adopted by Kantians. The debate between the two views has seemingly ended up in a theoretical standoff, and most of the theorists (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 972