Results for ' Proxy decision-maker'

980 found
Order:
  1.  24
    Advance planning and proxy decision makers.George J. Annas - 1992 - Ethics and Behavior 2 (1):67 – 68.
  2.  44
    Moral Authority and Proxy Decision-Making.Anthony Wrigley - 2015 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 18 (3):631-647.
    IntroductionExtended decision -making through the use of proxy decision -makers has been enshrined in a range of International Codes, Professional Guidance and Statute,For example, the UK Mental Capacity Act section 9.1; The General Medical Council ; the US National Guardianship Association ; Nuffield Council on Bioethics ; CIOMS-WHO section 6. Court cases such as Re Quinlan in the US have also contributed to establishing the groundings for the legal status of the proxy, albeit in terms of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  45
    Ethical understandings of proxy decision making for research involving adults lacking capacity: A systematic review (framework synthesis) of empirical research.Victoria Shepherd, Kerenza Hood, Mark Sheehan, Richard Griffith, Amber Jordan & Fiona Wood - 2018 - AJOB Empirical Bioethics 9 (4):267-286.
    Background: Research involving adults lacking mental capacity relies on the involvement of a proxy or surrogate, although this raises a number of ethical concerns. Empirical studies have examined attitudes towards proxy decision-making, proxies’ authority as decision-makers, decision accuracy, and other relevant factors. However, a comprehensive evidence-based account of proxy decision-making is lacking. This systematic review provides a synthesis of the empirical data reporting the ethical issues surrounding decisions made by research proxies, and the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  4.  46
    “A Feeling that You’re Helping”: Proxy Decision Making for Alzheimer’s Research.Laura B. Dunn, Jinger G. Hoop, Sahana Misra, Stephanie R. Fisher & Laura Weiss Roberts - 2011 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 1 (2):107-122.
    Surrogate (proxy) decision makers must make research decisions for people with dementia who lack decision-making capacity. Proxies’ decision-making processes are minimally understood. We randomly assigned 82 proxies of AD patients to informed consent for one of three hypothetical protocols with differing levels of risk and benefit. Proxies answered questions about potential benefits of the described research to the patient and society, as well as about whether they would enroll their relative and why or why not. Proxies (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5.  23
    Trusting Families: Responding to Mary Ann Meeker, “Responsive Care Management: Family Decision Makers in Advanced Cancer”.James Lindemann Nelson - 2011 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 22 (2):123-127.
    Mary Ann Meeker’s article admirably reminds readers that family members are involved in—or “responsively manage”—the care of relatives with severe illness in ways that run considerably beyond the stereotypes at play in many bioethical discussions of advance directives. Her observations thus make thinking about the role of families in healthcare provision more adequate to the facts, and this is an important contribution. There’s reason to be worried, however, that one explicit aim of the article—to ease the standing anxieties that many (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Epistemic burdens and the incentives of surrogate decision-makers.Parker Crutchfield & Scott Scheall - 2019 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 22 (4):613-621.
    We aim to establish the following claim: other factors held constant, the relative weights of the epistemic burdens of competing treatment options serve to determine the options that patient surrogates pursue. Simply put, surrogates confront an incentive, ceteris paribus, to pursue treatment options with respect to which their knowledge is most adequate to the requirements of the case. Regardless of what the patient would choose, options that require more knowledge than the surrogate possesses (or is likely to learn) will either (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7.  47
    Relatives as standard surrogate decision-makers for incompetent patients.Stephan Sahm & Regina Will - 2005 - Ethik in der Medizin 17 (1):7-20.
    ZusammenfassungIm Gesetzentwurf des Bundesrates zur Änderung des Betreuungsrechts ist eine regelhafte Stellvertretung durch Angehörige für zur Entscheidung unfähige Patienten vorgesehen. Mithilfe eines strukturierten Fragebogens wurden die Einstellungen von Tumorpatienten, gesunden Kontrollpersonen, Pflegenden und Ärzten zur Präferenz der zu bevollmächtigenden Personen ermittelt. Nur 10–20% der Befragten haben eine Patientenverfügung verfasst. Als Entscheidungbefugte im Falle akuter Erkrankung werden Angehörige und Ärzte gemeinsam genannt. Als Gesundheitsbevollmächtigte werden Ehepartner/lebenspartner bevorzugt und nichtangehörige Personen nur von einer Minderheit genannt. Die grundsätzliche Bereitschaft, als Gesundheitsbevollmächtigte Verantwortung zu (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  15
    Medical Decision Making for Patients Without Proxies: The Effect of Personal Experience in the Deliberative Process.Allyson L. Robichaud - 2015 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 26 (4):355-360.
    The number of admissions to hospitals of patients without a proxy decision maker is rising. Very often these patients need fairly immediate medical intervention for which informed consent—or informed refusal—is required. Many have recommended that there be a process in place to make these decisions, and that it include a variety of perspectives. People are particularly wary of relying solely on medical staff to make these decisions. The University Hospitals Case Medical Center recruits community members from its (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  28
    Making Medical Decisions for Incapacitated Patients Without Proxies: Part I.Cynthia Griggins, Eric Blackstone, Lauren McAliley & Barbara Daly - 2020 - HEC Forum 32 (1):33-45.
    To date no one has identified or described the population of incapacitated patients being treated in an inpatient setting who lack proxy decision-makers. Nor, despite repeated calls for protocols to be developed for decision-making, has any institution reported on the utilization of such a protocol. In 2005, our urban tertiary care hospital instituted a protocol utilizing community members of the ethics committee to meet with the medical providers and engage in shared decision-making for patients without proxies. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  59
    Proxy consent: moral authority misconceived.A. Wrigley - 2007 - Journal of Medical Ethics 33 (9):527-531.
    The Mental Capacity Act 2005 has provided unified scope in the British medical system for proxy consent with regard to medical decisions, in the form of a lasting power of attorney. While the intentions are to increase the autonomous decision making powers of those unable to consent, the author of this paper argues that the whole notion of proxy consent collapses into a paternalistic judgement regarding the other person’s best interests and that the new legislation introduces only (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  11.  31
    How clinicians can respond when family members question a proxy/surrogate's judgment and decisional capacity.Gregoire Calon & Katherine Drabiak - 2024 - Clinical Ethics 19 (3):277-283.
    Many state laws specify procedures for determining surrogate or proxy decision-makers for end-of-life care in the absence of an advance directive, living will, or other designation. Some laws also set forth criteria that the decision-maker must follow when making medical decisions for an incapacitated patient and determining whether to withdraw life-sustaining treatment. This article provides analysis of a medical ethics case on the question of how to address family allegations that the proxy decision-maker (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  18
    Colorado’s New Proxy Law Allowing Physicians to Serve as Proxies: Moving from Statute to Guidelines.Jean Abbott, Deb Bennett-Woods & Jacqueline J. Glover - 2018 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 29 (1):69-77.
    In 2016, the Colorado legislature passed an amendment to Colorado’s medical proxy law that established a process for the appointment of a physician to act as proxy decision maker of last resort for an unrepresented patient (Colorado HB 16-1101: Medical Decisions For Unrepresented Patients). The legislative process brought together a diverse set of stakeholders, not all of whom supported the legislation. Following passage of the statutory amendment, the Colorado Collaborative for Unrepresented Patients (CCUP), a group of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  10
    Medical Decision Making for Unrepresented Patients: A Reflection on Colorado’s Approach with Implications for Elsewhere.Kristin Furfari - 2022 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 33 (4):297-302.
    Unrepresented patients are some of the most vulnerable patients encountered in the healthcare system today. One of the challenges associated with healthcare for unrepresented patients is the lack of a standardized legal approach to decision making for this highly vulnerable population. Current statutory approaches vary widely without best practices or consensus guidelines. In 2016, Colorado passed a medical proxy law that established a process for the appointment of an independent physician to serve as a temporary proxy (...) maker for an unrepresented patient. Although this approach helps to identify a decision maker when no proxy is available, the appropriate standards for decision making remain uncertain. A peer-to-peer session at the Clinical Ethics Unconference in 2022 approached this conundrum with a focus on the best interests standard and the appropriate use of patients’ context in decision making. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  79
    Decision Making in Health Care: limitations of the substituted judgement principle.Susan Bailey - 2002 - Nursing Ethics 9 (5):483-493.
    The substituted judgement principle is often recommended as a means of promoting the self-determination of an incompetent individual when proxy decision makers are faced with having to make decisions about health care. This article represents a critical ethical analysis of this decision-making principle and describes practical impediments that serve to undermine its fundamental purpose. These impediments predominantly stem from the informality associated with the application of the substituted judgement principle. It is recommended that the principles upon which (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  15.  85
    Collective Moral Imagination: Making Decisions for Persons With Dementia.Elisabeth Boetzkes Gedge - 2004 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 29 (4):435-450.
    Much debate concerning ‘precedent autonomy’ – that is, the authority of former, competent selves to govern the welfare of later, non-competent selves – has assumed a radical discontinuity between selves, and has overlooked the ‘bridging’ role of intimate proxy decision-makers. I consider a recent proposal by Lynn et al. (1999) that presents a provocative alternative, foregrounding an imagined dialogue between the formerly competent patient and her/his trusted others. I consider what standards must be met for such dialogues to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  43
    A survey of the perspectives of patients who are seriously ill regarding end-of-life decisions in some medical institutions of Korea, China and Japan.Kwon Ivo, Koh Younsuck, Yun Young Ho, Suh Sang-Yeon, Heo Dae Seog, Bae Hyunah, Hattori Kenji & Zhai Xiaomei - 2012 - Journal of Medical Ethics 38 (5):310-316.
    Purpose The debate about the end-of-life care decision is becoming a serious ethical and legal concern in the Far-Eastern countries of Korea, China and Japan. However, the issues regarding end-of-life care will reflect the cultural background, current medical practices and socioeconomic conditions of the countries, which are different from Western countries and between each other. Understanding the genuine thoughts of patients who are critically ill is the first step in confronting the issues, and a comparative descriptive study of these (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  60
    Medical Information, Decision-Making and Use of Advance Directives by Chinese Cancer Patients in Hong Kong.Edwin C. Hui, Rico K. Liu, Ashley C. Cheng, Enoch Hsu & Dorian Wu - 2016 - Asian Bioethics Review 8 (2):109-133.
    Out of 288 Hong Kong cancer patients, 92.3% include themselves in decision-making, 71% prefer joint decision-making: with family, with doctor, with doctor plus family, with family minus doctor, and with doctor minus family. <5% want decision-making by “doctor-alone” and <1% desire decision-making by “family-alone”. Harmony, communication and responsibility are reasons for family participation. Most patients prefer “specialist” for information, followed by “family”, “friends”, and “GP”. Trust in doctors and prospects for controlling/curing disease are important factors in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  66
    Substitute decision making in medicine: comparative analysis of the ethico-legal discourse in England and Germany. [REVIEW]Ralf J. Jox, Sabine Michalowski, Jorn Lorenz & Jan Schildmann - 2008 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 11 (2):153-163.
    Health care decision making for patients without decisional capacity is ethically and legally challenging. Advance directives (living wills) have proved to be of limited usefulness in clinical practice. Therefore, academic attention should focus more on substitute decision making by the next of kin. In this article, we comparatively analyse the legal approaches to substitute medical decision making in England and Germany. Based on the current ethico-legal discourse in both countries, three aspects of substitute decision making will (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  19.  60
    The Moral Underpinning of the Proxy-Provider Relationship: Issues of Trust and Distrust.Bart J. Collopy - 1999 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 27 (1):37-45.
    Despite clear legislative and judicial support, a well established ethical consensus, and increased efforts at information dissemination and education, proxy decision making for incapacitated patients continues to produce moral muddle and poor resolutions in end-of-life care.In her analysis of the proxy-doctor relationship, Nancy Dubler spells out the institutionalized patterns that keep the promise of proxy directives so often unrealized. Facing medically complex care of an incapacitated patient, health care teams are apt to view the proxy (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  20.  12
    Concussion management in pediatric patients – ethical concerns.Taryn Knox, Alexander Gilbert & Lynley Anderson - 2024 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 18 (3):267-281.
    Collision sports pose a high risk of concussion. How to respond to this risk is more ethically complex when considering children and adolescents due to a) incomplete evidence regarding the impact of concussion on developing brains, b) physiological and social vulnerability, and c) the young person’s reliance on proxy decision-makers, usually parents. There is also a lack of clear definitions of (a) collision sport (vs. contact sport) and (b) what constitutes a child or adolescent. We consider whether parents (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  42
    Research involving adults lacking capacity to consent: the impact of research regulation on ‘evidence biased’ medicine.Victoria Shepherd - 2016 - BMC Medical Ethics 17 (1):55.
    Society is failing in its moral obligation to improve the standard of healthcare provided to vulnerable populations, such as people who lack decision making capacity, by a misguided paternalism that seeks to protect them by excluding them from medical research. Uncertainties surround the basis on which decisions about research participation is made under dual regulatory regimes, which adds further complexity. Vulnerable individuals’ exclusion from research as a result of such regulation risks condemning such populations to poor quality care as (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22.  97
    Counterfactual reasoning in surrogate decision making – another look.Mats Johansson & Linus Broström - 2009 - Bioethics 25 (5):244-249.
    Incompetent patients need to have someone else make decisions on their behalf. According to the Substituted Judgment Standard the surrogate decision maker ought to make the decision that the patient would have made, had he or she been competent. Objections have been raised against this traditional construal of the standard on the grounds that it involves flawed counterfactual reasoning, and amendments have been suggested within the framework of possible worlds semantics. The paper shows that while this approach (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23. Capacity and Consent in England and Wales: The Mental Capacity Act under Scrutiny.Peter Herissone-Kelly - 2010 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 19 (3):344-352.
    The Mental Capacity Act 2005 came into force in England and Wales in 2007. Its primary purpose is to provide “a statutory framework to empower and protect people who may lack capacity to make some decisions for themselves.” Examples of such people are those with dementia, learning disabilities, mental health problems, and so on. The Act also gives those who currently have capacity a legal framework within which they can make arrangements for a time when they may come to lack (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  19
    Legitimising values.John McMillan - 2022 - Journal of Medical Ethics 48 (6):357-357.
    While apparently helpful concepts such as ”best interests“ appear to have the virtue of simplicity, they are really place holders for the communication, time and listening that’s required to understand what truly matters to patients and others involved in healthcare. When we know what matters to a patient, we can have confidence that we have a “legitimate” view of what’s important to them. Two papers in this issue of the Journal of Medical Ethics explore different ways in which values can (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  51
    Too Close to the Knives: Children's Rights, Parental Authority, and Best Interests in the Context of Elective Pediatric Surgeries.Maggie Taylor - 2018 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 28 (3):281-308.
    This paper advances a novel conception of the child’s best interest in regard to pediatric surgeries that do not promote the preventive or therapeutic health needs of children, or elective pediatric surgeries (EPS). First, children’s capacity for decision-making is examined, and the best decision-making model for EPS is identified as the Best Interest Standard. What follows is a discussion of the interests of children in the context of EPS, the correlation of fundamental interests to rights, and guidelines for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  7
    ‘It’s not making a decision, it’s prompting the discussions’: a qualitative study exploring stakeholders’ views on the acceptability and feasibility of advance research planning (CONSULT-ADVANCE).Victoria Shepherd, Kerenza Hood & Fiona Wood - 2024 - BMC Medical Ethics 25 (1):1-23.
    Background Health and care research involving people who lack capacity to consent requires an alternative decision maker to decide whether they participate or not based on their ‘presumed will’. However, this is often unknown. Advance research planning (ARP) is a process for people who anticipate periods of impaired capacity to prospectively express their preferences about research participation and identify who they wish to be involved in future decisions. This may help to extend individuals’ autonomy by ensuring that (...) decisions are based on their actual wishes. This qualitative study aimed to explore stakeholders’ views about the acceptability and feasibility of ARP and identify barriers and facilitators to its implementation in the UK. Methods We conducted semi-structured interviews with 27 researchers, practitioners, and members of the public who had participated in a preceding survey. Interviews were conducted remotely between April and November 2023. Data were analysed thematically. Results Participants were supportive of the concept of ARP, with differing amounts of support for the range of possible ARP activities depending on the context. Six main themes were identified: (1) Planting a seed – creating opportunities to initiate/engage with ARP; (2) A missing part of the puzzle – how preferences expressed through ARP could help inform decisions; (3) Finding the sweet spot – optimising the timing of ARP; (4) More than a piece of paper – finding the best mode for recording preferences; (5) Keeping the door open to future opportunities – minimising the risk of unintended consequences; and (6) Navigating with a compass – principles underpinning ARP to ensure safeguarding and help address inequalities. Participants also identified a number of implementation challenges, and proposed facilitative strategies that might overcome them which included embedding advance research planning in existing future planning processes and research-focused activities. Conclusions This study provides a routemap to implementing ARP in the UK to enable people anticipating impaired capacity to express their preferences about research, thus ensuring greater opportunities for inclusion of this under-served group, and addressing the decisional burden experienced by some family members acting as proxies. Development of interventions and guidance to support ARP is needed, with a focus on ensuring accessibility. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  31
    Death, taxes and uncertainty: Economic motivations in end-of-life decision making.George Slade Mellgard & Jacob M. Appel - 2022 - Clinical Ethics 17 (1):90-94.
    Economic motivations are key drivers of human behavior. Unfortunately, they are largely overlooked in literature related to medical decisionmaking, particularly with regard to end-of-life care. It is widely understood that the directions of a proxy acting in bad faith can be overridden. But what of cases in which the proxy or surrogate appears to be acting in good faith to effectuate the patient’s values, yet doing so directly serves the decision-maker’s financial interests? Such situations are not (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  29
    Psychiatric Advance Directives as an Ethical Communication Tool: An Analysis of Definitions.Virginia A. Brown, Jaime Thomas & Billy Table - 2020 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 31 (4):353-363.
    A psychiatric advance directive (PAD) is a communication tool that promotes patients’ autonomy and gives capacitated adults who live with serious mental illnesses the ability to record their preferences for care and designate a proxy decision maker before a healthcare crisis. Despite a high degree of interest by patients and previous studies that recommend that clinicians facilitate the completion of PADs, the rate of implementation of PADs remains low. Research indicates that many clinicians lack the necessary experience (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  10
    Familiar Interests and Strange Analogies: Baergen and Woodhouse on Extra-Familial Interests.James Lindemann Nelson - 2013 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 24 (4):338-342.
    The article by Professor Baergen and Dr. Woodhouse makes a succinct and serious contribution to progress in bioethical understanding of deciding for others. They begin with what is by now a familiar claim: family proxy decision makers may sometimes make decisions on behalf of incapacitated relatives that depart from what might be optimal from the patient’s point of view, since the well-being of family members, or of the family as such, may be substantially affected by the direction of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30. A direct advance on advance directives.David Shaw - 2012 - Bioethics 26 (5):267-274.
    Advance directives (ADs), which are also sometimes referred to as ‘living wills’, are statements made by a person that indicate what treatment she should not be given in the event that she is not competent to consent or refuse at the future moment in question. As such, ADs provide a way for patients to make decisions in advance about what treatments they do not want to receive, without doctors having to find proxy decision-makers or having recourse to the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  31.  71
    Cultural Aspects of Nondisclosure.Celia J. Orona, Barbara A. Koenig & Anne J. Davis - 1994 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 3 (3):338.
    A basic assumption in current western medicine is that good healthcare involves informed choices. Indeed, making informed choices is not only viewed as “good practice” but a right to which each individual is entitled, a perspective only recently developed in the medical field.Moreover, in the case of ethical decisions, much of the discussion on the role of the family is cast within the autonomy paradigm of contemporary bioethics; that is, family members provide emotional support but do not make decisions for (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  32.  10
    When Should Providers Defer versus Impose Their Views?Edmund G. Howe - 2023 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 34 (4):289-295.
    This piece discusses perhaps the most agonizing ethical decision ethics consultants and other providers encounter. This is the extent to which providers should defer decisions to patients or to their proxy decision makers as opposed to imposing their own views as to what they think is ethically right. It discusses the most difficult issues these providers may encounter, especially when they wish to depart from authoritative bodies’ standards or guidelines, and it presents initial steps providers may take (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Ethical issues in starting and stopping end-stage dialysis.Richard Hull - manuscript
    Three ethical principles currently determine both law and practice with respect to starting and stopping dialysis in end stage renal disease cases: Medical Futility, Respect for Life, and Patient Sel-determination. Even where dialysis is not medically futile, patients possessing capacity, and patients lacking capacity but with valid, functioning proxy decision-makers, self-determination is the dominant principle, in that efforts to prolong and preserve life may be set aside or not initiated at the request of the adequately informed patient or (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  48
    Autonomy, shared agency and prediction.Sungwoo Um - 2022 - Journal of Medical Ethics 48 (5):313-314.
    The patient preference predictor is a computer-based algorithm devised to predict the medical treatment that decisionally incapacitated patients would have preferred. The target paper argues against various criticisms to the effect that the use of a PPP is inconsistent with proper respect for patient autonomy.1 In this commentary, I aim to add some clarifications to the complex relationship between autonomy and the PPP. First, I highlight one way in which the decision of a surrogate designated by the patient realises (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35.  12
    Who’s at the Table? Moral Obligations to Equal-Priority Surrogates in Clinical Ethics Consultations.Autumn Fiester & Meghan O’Brien - 2014 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 25 (4):273-280.
    Existing state surrogate decision-maker laws are fragmented and inconsistent and fail to ensure that all eligible decision makers of the same surrogate priority class are included in the healthcare decisions made for an incapacitated loved one. In this article, we explore three categories of harm that result from failing to include all surrogates of equal priority in a patient’s healthcare decision, namely harms to the patient, harms to the excluded surrogate, and harms to the family. Given (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  46
    Empirical Fallacies in the Debate on Substituted Judgment.Mats Johansson & Linus Broström - 2012 - Health Care Analysis (1):1-9.
    According to the Substituted Judgment Standard a surrogate decision maker ought to make the decision that the incompetent patient would have made, had he or she been competent. This standard has received a fair amount of criticism, but the objections raised are often wide of the mark. In this article we discuss three objections based on empirical research, and explain why these do not give us reason to abandon the Substituted Judgment Standard.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  69
    Issues Involving Informed Consent for Research Participants with Alzheimer’s Disease.Adnan Qureshi & Amer Johri - 2008 - Journal of Academic Ethics 6 (3):197-203.
    Alzheimer’s disease is the most common form of dementia which is estimated to impact 350,000 people over 65 years of age in Canada. The lack of effective treatment and the growing number of people who are expected to be diagnosed with Alzheimer’s disease in the near future are compelling reasons why continued research is in this area is necessary. With additional research, there needs to be greater recognition of the complexity of seeking ongoing informed consent from those with Alzheimer’s disease. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  82
    Informed consent in texas: Theory and practice.Mark J. Cherry & H. Tristram Engelhardt - 2004 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 29 (2):237 – 252.
    The legal basis of informed consent in Texas may on first examination suggest an unqualified affirmation of persons as the source of authority over themselves. This view of individuals in the practice of informed consent tends to present persons outside of any social context in general and outside of their families in particular. The actual functioning of law and medical practice in Texas, however, is far more complex. This study begins with a brief overview of the roots of Texas law (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  39. Promoting advance planning for health care and research among older adults: A randomized controlled trial.Gina Bravo, Marcel Arcand, Danièle Blanchette, Anne-Marie Boire-Lavigne, Marie-France Dubois, Maryse Guay, Paule Hottin, Julie Lane, Judith Lauzon & Suzanne Bellemare - 2012 - BMC Medical Ethics 13 (1):1-13.
    Background: Family members are often required to act as substitute decision-makers when health care or research participation decisions must be made for an incapacitated relative. Yet most families are unable to accurately predict older adult preferences regarding future health care and willingness to engage in research studies. Discussion and documentation of preferences could improve proxies' abilities to decide for their loved ones. This trial assesses the efficacy of an advance planning intervention in improving the accuracy of substitute decision-making (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  40. Wanted Dead or Alive: Organ Donation and Ethical Limitations on Surrogate Consent for Non-Competent Living Donors.A. Wrigley - 2013 - In Nicky Priaulx & Anthony Wrigley (eds.), Ethics, Law and Society Vol. V: Ethics of Care, Theorising the Ethical, and Body Politics. Ashgate. pp. 209-234.
    People have understandable concerns over what happens to their bodies, both during their life and after they die. Consent to organ donation is often perceived as an altruistic decision made by individuals prior to their death so that others can benefit from use of their organs once they have died. More recently, live organ donation has also been possible, where an individual chooses to donate an organ or body tissue that will not result in their death (such as a (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  13
    Moral Distress for the Physician Assistant.Sharyn L. Kurtz - 2013 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 3 (2):13-16.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Moral Distress for the Physician AssistantSharyn L. KurtzMy morning rounds as an inpatient medical oncology physician assistant began as usual. I arrived at the hospital early to receive 7 a.m. sign out from the covering resident. The overnight report began favorably. All patients remained stable. Even my patient, whom I will call Mrs. Walker,* had a quiet night. However, given her tenuous admission presentation, including altered mental status, hypercalcemia (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  28
    Informed Consent and the Roman Rite of Exorcism.Timothy J. Egan - 2015 - The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 15 (3):531-546.
    The biblical healings by Jesus and the primitive Church, the liturgical development of the Roman Rite of Exorcism, and the current practice of exorcists reflect a relationship between exorcism and the medical healing arts. Since mutuality characterizes all healer–sufferer interactions, informed consent is a central concept in physician–patient and exorcist–energumen relationships. Informed consent requires adequate information, decision-maker competence, and freedom from coercion. The determination of freedom from coercion is a particular challenge in exorcism, and guidelines for its assess­ment (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  65
    Inapplicability of advance directives in a paternalistic setting: the case of a post-communist health system. [REVIEW]Gentian Vyshka & Jera Kruja - 2011 - BMC Medical Ethics 12 (1):12-.
    Background: The Albanian medical system and Albanian health legislation have adopted a paternalistic position with regard to individual decision making. This reflects the practices of a not-so-remote past when state-run facilities and a totalitarian philosophy of medical care were politically imposed. Because of this history, advance directives concerning treatment refusal and do-not-resuscitate decisions are still extremely uncommon in Albania. Medical teams cannot abstain from intervening even when the patient explicitly and repeatedly solicits therapeutic abstinence. The Albanian law on health (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44.  73
    Advance Directives to Withhold Oral Food and Water in Dementia.Ann M. Heath - 2016 - The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 16 (3):421-434.
    Euthanasia advocates have recently begun counseling people to create advance directives calling for oral food and water to be withheld if the person reaches a certain stage of dementia. The author shows that these directives are in fact requests for euthanasia, and they leave vulnerable people subject to poor-quality care. Both surrogate decision makers and Catholic institutions have a moral obligation not to implement such directives, and surrogates, rather than withdrawing as proxies, have a moral obligation to advocate for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Proxy decision-making.José Miola - 2014 - In Charles Foster, Jonathan Herring & Israel Doron (eds.), The law and ethics of dementia. Portland, Oregon: Hart Publishing.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Proxy decision-making : a legal perspective.Winsor C. Schmidt - 2014 - In Charles Foster, Jonathan Herring & Israel Doron (eds.), The law and ethics of dementia. Portland, Oregon: Hart Publishing.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Tracking decision makers under uncertainty.Amos Arieli & Ariel Rubinstein - unknown
    Eye tracking is used to investigate human choice procedures. We infer from eye movement patterns in choice problems where the deliberation process is clear to deliberations in problems of choice between two lotteries. The results indicate that participants tend to compare prizes and probabilities separately. The data provide little support for the hypothesis that decision makers use an expected utility type of calculation exclusively. This is particularly true when the calculations involved in comparing the lotteries are complicated.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  48.  39
    Study on Agriculture Decision-Makers Behavior on Sustainable Energy Utilization.Josef Maroušek - 2013 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 26 (3):679-689.
    Phytomass cultivation for energy use is increasingly popular in Europe for high profits guaranteed by subsidy. Although public interest in ecology is on an increasing level, direct combustion is still preferred even though scholars have been warning about formations of hazardous compounds for a long-time. However, the reduction of subsidies would negatively affect an already bad situation in Czech agriculture, since most farmers became fully dependent on subsidies due to quotas, restrictions, and other unequal business conditions in European Union. It (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  49.  18
    Decision-makers’ attitudes toward the use of care robots in welfare services.Outi Tuisku, Satu Pekkarinen, Lea Hennala & Helinä Melkas - forthcoming - AI and Society:1-14.
    The purpose of this study was to investigate the attitudes of decision-makers toward the use of care robots in welfare services. We investigated their knowledge regarding the use of care robots in welfare services as well as their attitudes toward using robots in their own care and in the care of various user groups, for example, children, youths, and older people. We conducted an online survey with a range of Finnish decision-makers as respondents. The respondents were divided into (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  20
    (Re)Conceptualising ‘good’ proxy decision-making for research: the implications for proxy consent decision quality.Victoria Shepherd - 2022 - BMC Medical Ethics 23 (1):1-11.
    People who are unable to make decisions about participating in research rely on proxies to make a decision based on their wishes and preferences. However, patients rarely discuss their preferences about research and proxies find it challenging to determine what their wishes would be. While the process of informed consent has traditionally been the focus of research to improve consent decisions, the more conceptually complex area of what constitutes ‘good’ proxy decision-making for research has remained unexplored. Interventions (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 980