The Aristotelian conception of habit and its contribution to human neuroscience

Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8:1-10 (2014)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The notion of habit used in neuroscience is an inheritance from a particular theoretical origin, whose main source is William James. Thus, habits have been characterized as rigid, automatic, unconscious, and opposed to goal-directed actions. This analysis leaves unexplained several aspects of human behavior and cognition where habits are of great importance. We intend to demonstrate the utility that another philosophical conception of habit, the Aristotelian, may have for neuroscientific research. We first summarize the current notion of habit in neuroscience, its philosophical inspiration and the problems that arise from it, mostly centered on the sharp distinction between goal-directed actions and habitual behavior. We then introduce the Aristotelian view and we compare it with that of William James. For Aristotle, a habit is an acquired disposition to perform certain types of action. If this disposition involves an enhanced cognitive control of actions, it can be considered a “habit-as-learning”. The current view of habit in neuroscience, which lacks cognitive control and we term “habit-as-routine”, is also covered by the Aristotelian conception. He classifies habits into three categories: (1) theoretical, or the retention of learning understood as “knowing that x is so”; (2) behavioral, through which the agent achieves a rational control of emotion-permeated behavior (“knowing how to behave”); and (3) technical or learned skills (“knowing how to make or to do”). Finally, we propose new areas of research where this “novel” conception of habit could serve as a framework concept, from the cognitive enrichment of actions to the role of habits in pathological conditions. In all, this contribution may shed light on the understanding of habits as an important feature of human action. Habits, viewed as a cognitive enrichment of behavior, are a crucial resource for understanding human learning and behavioral plasticity.

Other Versions

No versions found

Similar books and articles

Habitual actions.Bill Pollard - 2010 - In Timothy O'Connor & Constantine Sandis, A Companion to the Philosophy of Action. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 74–81.
An Integrative Understanding of Habit to Explore its Neural Correlates.J. Bernacer - 2018 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 25 (7-8):112-134.
Psychology of habit.Wendy Wood & Dennis Rünger - 2016 - Annual Review of Psychology 67 (1):289–314.
Why the performance of habit requires attention.Laura Bickel - 2024 - Mind and Language 39 (2):260-270.
Virtue and the Psychology of Habit.Brandon Dahm & Matthew Breuninger - 2022 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 96 (2):291-315.
On Habit.Clare Carlisle - 2014 - New York: Routledge.
Habit and Freedom in Merleau-Ponty and Ricœur.Jakub Capek - 2017 - Journal of Speculative Philosophy 31 (3):432-443.

Analytics

Added to PP
2019-08-25

Downloads
1,224 (#16,203)

6 months
119 (#51,315)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author Profiles

Javier Bernacer
Universidad de Navarra
José Ignacio Murillo
University of Navarra

References found in this work

Thinking, Fast and Slow.Daniel Kahneman - 2011 - New York: New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.
[no title].Daniel Kahneman & Shane Frederick - 2002 - Cambridge University Press.
The Study of Instinct.N. Tinbergen - 1954 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 5 (17):72-76.
The consciousness of self.William James - 1890 - In The Principles of Psychology. London, England: Dover Publications.
Categorization of action slips.Donald A. Norman - 1981 - Psychological Review 88 (1):1-15.

View all 18 references / Add more references