View year:

  1. Aristotle on the Causal Efficacy of Perceptible Qualities.Ekrem Çetinkaya - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (7):1-25.
    Aristotle grants perceptible qualities the power to generate sense perception in animals. But it is unclear whether, for him, these qualities can produce any effect other than perception. In this paper I address this issue through a novel approach. To show that they can produce non-perceptual effects, I explore contexts in his extant works where qualities appear to do causal work in nature without leading to perception in animals. This inquiry aims to demonstrate that Aristotle’s realism about qualities survives a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  40
    Aristotle on happiness, virtue, and wisdom.Joachim Aufderheide & Daniel Ferguson - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (6):1502-1507.
    Bryan C. Reece’s Aristotle on Happiness, Virtue, and Wisdom (2023) has the ambitious goal of vindicating the coherence of the Nicomachean Ethics. Since Jaeger’s claim a hundred years ago that Arist...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  22
    Aristotle on happiness, virtue, and wisdom.Joachim Aufderheide & Daniel Ferguson - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (6):1502-1507.
    Volume 32, Issue 6, December 2024, Page 1502-1507.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  7
    Korean women philosophers and the ideal of a female sage: essential writings of Im Yunjidang and Gang Jeongildang. [REVIEW]Dobin Choi - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (6).
    Korean Women Philosophers and the Ideal of a Female Sage explores the lives of two Korean women Confucian scholars of the late Joseon Dynasty, Im Yunjidang (1721–1793) and Gang Jeongildang (1772–18...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  2
    Korean women philosophers and the ideal of a female sage: essential writings of Im Yunjidang and Gang Jeongildang.Dobin Choi - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (6):1508-1512.
    Volume 32, Issue 6, December 2024, Page 1508-1512.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  30
    Speaking of what is not: Hatibz'de and Taşköpriz'de K'sım on the existential import of negative propositions.Yusuf Daşdemir - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (6):1282-1304.
    This paper undertakes an in-depth examination of the intriguing argument for the existential import of negative propositions by the fifteenth-century Ottoman scholar Hatibzâde Mehmed (d. 1496) and the counterarguments by his disciple, Taşköprizâde Kâsım (d. 1513). It argues that this discussion is a significant example of Ottoman scholars engaging in long-standing disputes concerning the nature and ontological ground of negative propositions, which date back to Plato and Aristotle. It is also intended to underline the need for considering not only logic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  18
    Speaking of what is not: Hatibz'de and Taşköpriz'de K'sım on the existential import of negative propositions.Yusuf Daşdemir - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (6):1282-1304.
    This paper undertakes an in-depth examination of the intriguing argument for the existential import of negative propositions by the fifteenth-century Ottoman scholar Hatibzâde Mehmed (d. 1496) and the counterarguments by his disciple, Taşköprizâde Kâsım (d. 1513). It argues that this discussion is a significant example of Ottoman scholars engaging in long-standing disputes concerning the nature and ontological ground of negative propositions, which date back to Plato and Aristotle. It is also intended to underline the need for considering not only logic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Carlos Vaz Ferreira on intellectual flourishing as intellectual liberation.Juan Garcia Torres - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (6):1374-1395.
    I argue for a substantive interpretation of Carlos Vaz Ferreira’s account of intellectual flourishing as intellectual liberation. For Vaz Ferreira, I argue, there is an inescapable master-slave dynamic between language and language users, so that flourishing intellectually essentially involves a type of mastery of language that frees up thinking from enslaving linguistic/conceptual confusions and thus facilitates the acquisition of truth. Central to this project are Vaz Ferreira’s most interesting, and radical, views on the nature of language signification and thus on (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Augustine on memory, the mind, and human flourishing.T. Parker Haratine - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (6):1220-1240.
    Augustine maintains that the mind at least consists of memory, intellect, and will (De Trinitate 10.9.13 & 10.11.17). While it is easy to understand the intellect and will as essential to the mind’s activities, memory proves more difficult to understand. It is not immediately clear, for example, whether a human mind could operate without memory, whether people without memory have minds, and what distinguishes memory from the intellect. To understand the role of memory and its respective activities, this article addresses (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  29
    Anonymus Cantabrigiensis, Commentarium in Sophisticos Elenchos Aristotelis[REVIEW]John Marenbon - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (6):1495-1498.
    Editions of difficult, obscure Latin philosophical texts from the Middle Ages rarely receive reviews in general History of Philosophy journals. An exception might be made for an important new editi...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  13
    Abū Bakr al-Rāzī’s ethical decision-making systems.Muhammad Mahdi Montasseri - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (6):1254-1281.
    Ethics plays an essential role in the philosophical framework of Abū Bakr al-Rāzī. Although most of his philosophical works have become extinct, two surviving works serve as primary sources for understanding his ethical theory. Although sharing certain foundational principles, these two works diverge in terms of ethical standards and exhibit distinct logical approaches to ethics, a facet that has largely remained unexplored within contemporary scholarly discourse. I aim to extract and reconstruct both of his ethical decision-making systems by shedding light (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  16
    Why Epicurean happiness is not for everyone.Jan Maximilian Robitzsch - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (6):1203-1219.
    It is often assumed that Epicurean happiness can be achieved by everyone alike. This paper offers a corrective to this view. While it is true that the Epicureans abolish traditional differences among people like those between the sexes, social classes, and so on, they also maintain that there are people who are incapable of achieving happiness because they lack a certain bodily make-up or because they do not have the right ethnic or cultural origin.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  24
    Why Epicurean happiness is not for everyone.Jan Maximilian Robitzsch - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (6):1203-1219.
    It is often assumed that Epicurean happiness can be achieved by everyone alike. This paper offers a corrective to this view. While it is true that the Epicureans abolish traditional differences among people like those between the sexes, social classes, and so on, they also maintain that there are people who are incapable of achieving happiness because they lack a certain bodily make-up or because they do not have the right ethnic or cultural origin.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Kant on phenomenal substance.Lorenzo Spagnesi - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (6):1305-1328.
    In this paper, I offer a systematic account of Kant’s view on ‘phenomenal substance’. Several studies have recently analysed Kant’s notion of substance. However, I submit that more needs to be said about how this notion is reconceptualized within the critical framework to vindicate a genuine and legitimate sense of substance in the phenomenal realm. More specifically, I show that Kant’s transcendental idealism does not commit him to a rejection of substantiality in phenomena. Rather, Kant isolates a general notion of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  31
    The eudaimonist ethics of al-Fārābī and Avicenna.Peter Tarras - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (6):1498-1502.
    Volume 32, Issue 6, December 2024, Page 1498-1502.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  1
    Carlos Vaz Ferreira on intellectual flourishing as intellectual liberation.Juan Garcia Torres - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (6):1374-1395.
    I argue for a substantive interpretation of Carlos Vaz Ferreira’s account of intellectual flourishing as intellectual liberation. For Vaz Ferreira, I argue, there is an inescapable master-slave dynamic between language and language users, so that flourishing intellectually essentially involves a type of mastery of language that frees up thinking from enslaving linguistic/conceptual confusions and thus facilitates the acquisition of truth. Central to this project are Vaz Ferreira’s most interesting, and radical, views on the nature of language signification and thus on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  20
    Do thoughts have parts? Peter Abelard: Yes! Alberic of Paris: No!Denmark Copenhagen - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (5):974-998.
    Spoken sentences have parts. Therefore they take time to speak. For instance, when you say, ‘Socrates is running’, you begin by uttering the subject term Socrates, before carrying on to the predicate. But are the corresponding thoughts also composite? And are such thoughts extended across time, like their spoken counterparts? Peter Abelard gave an affirmative response to both questions. Alberic of Paris denied the first and, as a corollary, denied the second. Here, I first set out Abelard’s account. I then (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  25
    Hobbes and God in Locke’s law of nature.Daniel E. Burns - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (5):999-1029.
    Locke bases his moral and political philosophy on his doctrine of the ‘law of nature’. Scholars have debated the content and grounding of this law and its relationship to Christian theology. The ambiguities of the Lockean natural law’s content are traceable to an unclear grammatical construction in a crucial passage of the Treatises of Government, which can be resolved by following out a related set of arguments in that work. The ambiguities of the Lockean natural law’s grounding can then be (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  22
    Do the wise always succeed? A split-level reading of Euthydemus 278–282.Matthew Matherne - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (5):933-954.
    At Euthydemus 278–282, Socrates produces an argument that has almost universally been agreed to entail that wisdom is sufficient for happiness, necessary for happiness, or both. According to these standard readings, this is because Socrates ties wisdom to correct use of one's assets. Since wisdom is necessary or sufficient for correct use and correct use is necessary or sufficient for happiness, wisdom bears the same relation(s) to happiness, mutatis mutandis. I propose a split-level reading of this passage. On the level (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Do Thoughts Have Parts? Peter Abelard: Yes! Alberic of Paris: No!Boaz Faraday Schuman - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (5):974-998.
    Spoken sentences have parts. Therefore they take time to speak. For instance, when you say, “Socrates is running”, you begin by uttering the subject term ("Socrates"), before carrying on to the predicate. But are the corresponding predications in thought also composite? And are such thoughts extended across time, like their spoken counterparts? Peter Abelard gave an affirmative response to both questions. Alberic of Paris denied the first and, as a corollary, denied the second. Here, I first set out Abelard’s account. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  13
    Do thoughts have parts? Peter Abelard: Yes! Alberic of Paris: No!.Boaz Faraday Schuman - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (5):974-998.
    Spoken sentences have parts. Therefore they take time to speak. For instance, when you say, ‘Socrates is running’, you begin by uttering the subject term Socrates, before carrying on to the predicate. But are the corresponding thoughts also composite? And are such thoughts extended across time, like their spoken counterparts? Peter Abelard gave an affirmative response to both questions. Alberic of Paris denied the first and, as a corollary, denied the second. Here, I first set out Abelard’s account. I then (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Induction and certainty in the physics of Wolff and Crusius.Hein van den Berg & Boris Demarest - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (5):1052-1073.
    In this paper, we analyse conceptions of induction and certainty in Wolff and Crusius, highlighting their competing conceptions of physics. We discuss (i) the perspective of Wolff, who assigned induction an important role in physics, but argued that physics should be an axiomatic science containing certain statements, and (ii) the perspective of Crusius, who adopted parts of the ideal of axiomatic physics but criticized the scope of Wolff’s ideal of certain science. Against interpretations that take Wolff’s proofs in physics to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  26
    Mind and knowledge of mind in classical Islamic philosophy.Anthony Robert Booth, Jari Kaukua & Andrew Stephenson - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (4):699-703.
    Classical Islamic philosophy has in recent years started to receive the sort of attention that this rich period and tradition in the history of philosophy deserves. A consequence of this has been that people working in the field are beginning to approach it in a more philosophically thematic way, and in such a way that its insights look relevant to contemporary research. Questions concerning the mind (Ar. dhihn), the intellect (Ar. ʿaql), or the soul (Ar. nafs), occupied a central place (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  43
    Recognition and the self in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit.Stephen Houlgate - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (4):925-932.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  36
    Recognition and the self in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit.Stephen Houlgate - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (4):925-932.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  58
    Pragmatism and scientific philosophy in Carnap and Quine.Robert Sinclair - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (4):895-902.
    Critical Review of The Philosophical Project of Carnap and Quine, edited by Sean Morris, Cambridge University Press, 2023.Scholarly opinion concerning the Carnap–Quine relationship and their centra...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  13
    Pragmatism and scientific philosophy in Carnap and Quine.Japan Tokyo - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (4):895-902.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  46
    The philosophy of hope: beatitude in Spinoza.Johannes Wagner - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (4):913-919.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  27
    Thinking with Rosa: assent in philosophy of the Islamic world.Peter Adamson - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (3):647-665.
    In Thinking with Assent: Renewing a Traditional Account of Knowledge and Belief, Maria Rosa Antognazza offers a historical narrative of pre-modern epistemology. She argues that until very recently, philosophers generally held that “knowing and believing are distinct in kind in the strong sense that they are mutually exclusive mental states”. This paper tests, and ultimately confirms, that account by applying it two thinkers of the Islamic world, al-Fārābī (d.950 CE) and Ibn Sīnā (Avicenna, d.1037 CE). It is shown that both (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  37
    Leibniz’s opposition to monism.Maria Rosa Antognazza - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (3):666-686.
    Leibniz's metaphysics appears to go a long way towards monism: it supports a strong dependence of limited things on the absolute or God and understands this dependence not only as causal dependence but also as a pervasive ontological dependence which involves the communality of nature between absolute and limited. Yet, Leibniz stops short of affirming monism. Why? This paper takes a fresh look at Leibniz's reasons for opposing monism through the lens of a virtually unknown text of 1698 on the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Kant as a Carpenter of Reason: The Highest Good and Systematic Coherence.Alexander T. Englert - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (3):496-524.
    What is the highest good actually good for in Kant’s third Critique? While there are well-worked out answers to this question in the literature that focus on the highest good’s practical importance, this paper argues that there is an important function for the highest good that has to do exclusively with contemplation. This important function becomes clear once one notices that coherent [konsequent] thinking, for Kant, was synonymous with "bündiges" thinking, and that both are connected with the highest good in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  32
    Reinhold on intellectual intuition.Elise Frketich - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (3):547-563.
    Kant describes intellectual intuition as a kind of non-sensible intuition that creates its objects and provides knowledge of them as noumena. Although he precludes intellectual intuition from the human mind, Reinhold attributes it to the human mind. Pioneering research has already shown that Reinhold deviates from Kant in this way to explain the possibility of a priori self-cognition. It has also already shown that Fichte follows Reinhold by deviating from Kant in the same way. Yet, other aspects of Reinhold’s doctrine (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  45
    Remembering Maria Rosa Antognazza (1964–2023).Sacha Golob, Michael Beaney & Mogens Lærke - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (3):633-646.
    A little over a year ago, we lost one of the leading historians of philosophy of her generation, Prof. Maria Rosa Antognazza. So many in this community also lost a dear friend.Rosa, as she was know...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  23
    The concept of dignity in Edmund Burke’s writings on the French revolution.Samuel Harrison - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (3):525-546.
    This paper argues that the concept of dignity played an important role in the political thought of Edmund Burke. It seeks to show that, in contrast with the egalitarian and individual version of dignity associated with Immanuel Kant, Burke devised a conception of dignity that rested on reverence, grandeur and formality, to be manifested through institutions, customs, and social relations. Burkean dignity was thus closely linked with the ancient constitution. In his thought, dignity played an essential role in maintaining social (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  37
    Ottobah Cugoano on chattel slavery and the moral limitations of ius gentium.Aminah Hasan-Birdwell - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (3):473-495.
    This article considers Ottobah Cugoano’s philosophical response to the moral and legal contradictions of the practice of human trafficking in his Thoughts and Sentiments on the Evil and Wicked Traffic of the Slavery and Commerce of the Human Species (1787). It analyses Cugoano’s critique of the origins of slavery in general and the practices of ancient slavery, from which seventeenth-century proslavery advocates drew political, theological, and moral justifications of the African slave trade. According to Cugoano’s analysis, there is a necessary (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36. Mary Astell on Self-Government and Custom.Marie Jayasekera - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (3):452-472.
    This paper identifies, develops, and argues for an interpretation of Mary Astell’s understanding of self-government. On this interpretation, what is essential to self-government, according to Astell, is an agent’s responsiveness to her own reasoning. The paper identifies two aspects of her theory of self-government: an ‘authenticity’ criterion of what makes our motives our own and an account of the capacities required for responsiveness to our own reasoning. The authenticity criterion states that when our motives arise from some external source without (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Beatrice Edgell’s Myth of the Given.Uriah Kriegel - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (3):587-605.
    Wilfrid Sellars’ “myth of the given” had a momentous influence on 20th-century epistemology, putting under pressure the internalist foundationalism so prominent in early analytic philosophy. In this paper, I argue that the core themes in Sellars’ argument are anticipated in the work of the London philosopher and psychologist Beatrice Edgell (1871-1948). Indeed, in some respects Edgell’s argument against the myth of the given is even more compelling than Sellars’. The paper logically reconstructs and historically contextualizes Edgell’s line of argument, as (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  7
    Thinking with Rosa: assent in philosophy of the Islamic world.Germany Munich - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (3):647-665.
    Volume 32, Issue 3, May 2024, Page 647-665.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  54
    “We shall remove the Sun”: Henry More’s Neoplatonic adaptation of Jacob Böhme’s philosophy.Cecilia Muratori - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (3):426-451.
    This article presents a detailed analysis of how the Cambridge Platonist Henry More (1614–1687) adapted the philosophy of the German mystic Jacob Böhme (1575–1624). For More, Böhme’s errors can be amended only by intervening radically in his philosophical system, discussing not what Böhme said, but what he should have said. In particular, the essay studies how and why More, in Censura, altered a scheme used by Böhme in his Clavis to explain visually the core of his philosophical insight. It claims (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  61
    Samuel Alexander on relations, Russell, and Bradley.Oliver Thomas Spinney - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (3):564-586.
    In this article I describe the contributions made by Samuel Alexander to the issue of relations which so vexed Bertrand Russell and F. H. Bradley in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. I provide a novel understanding of Alexander’s position concerning relations and describe the way in which he viewed his position as superior to those of Bradley and Russell. I offer, therefore, a more complete picture of a philosophical debate central to the relevant period, through the introduction of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  62
    Comparisons in the history of philosophy: a review of The metaphysics of Margaret Cavendish and Anne Conway: monism, vitalism, and self-motion, by Marcy P. Lascano, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2023, pp. 240, £54.00 (hb), ISBN: 9780197651636. [REVIEW]Peter West - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (3).
    In The Metaphysics of Margaret Cavendish and Anne Conway, Marcy P. Lascano holds up the metaphysical views of two early modern women philosophers alongside one another in order to demonstrate that...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  26
    A crisis of recognition: gender, race, and the struggle to be seen in pre-modernity.Hannah Dawson - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (2):319-351.
    ABSTRACT It used to be said that shame culture waned in early modernity, but there is a growing body of historiography on the vital role that recognition and the opinion of others continued to play. Honour mattered; for some it was the mark and the maker of your true self. While philosophers like Hobbes, Locke, Mandeville, Hume, Smith, and Rousseau disagreed in their evaluations of the phenomenon, they were united in thinking that the great engine of recognition whirred like furious (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  25
    Recognition and respect in early modern philosophy.Tim Stuart-Buttle & Heikki Haara - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (2):243-246.
    Recognition has, over the past three decades, come to occupy a central place in moral and political philosophy, and critical theory; but to the extent that scholars have exhibited an interest in tr...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Materialism from Hobbes to Locke: by Stewart Duncan, New York, Oxford University Press, 2022, pp. 240, £ 56.00 (hb), ISBN 9780197613009. [REVIEW]Ruth Boeker - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (1):231-237.
    Stewart Duncan’s excellent book Materialism from Hobbes to Locke offers an insightful study of the debates concerning materialism during the seventeenth century. When we hear the expression ‘materialism’, we often associate with it the question of whether the human mind is an entirely material entity. Although the question of whether the human mind is material plays an important role throughout the seventeenth-century debates examined in this book, Duncan offers a broader understanding of materialism that is not restricted to the human (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  91
    Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics on virtue competition.Bradford Jean-Hyuk Kim - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (1):1-21.
    For many, striving to attain first place in an athletic competition is explicable. Less explicable is striving to attain first place in a virtue (aretē) competition. Yet this latter dynamic appears in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. There is 4.3’s magnanimity, the crown of the virtues, which seemingly manifests itself in outdoing one’s peers in virtue. Such one-upmanship also seems operant with 9.8’s praiseworthy self-lover, who seeks to get as much of the fine (to kalon) as possible for herself. Contrary to many (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  62
    Are the later Mohists preference-satisfaction consequentialists? A discussion of Daniel Stephens’ “Later Mohist ethics and philosophical progress in ancient China”.Bradford Jean-Hyuk Kim - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (1):218-30.
    The Mohists may have been the first consequentialists on earth. Their most important principles are that right action is what benefits the world and that the underlying outlook for benefiting the world is inclusive care, whereby each person receives equal consideration. The early Mohists are clearly objective-list consequentialists, whereby benefiting the world amounts to promoting the most basic goods. Stephens argues that the later Mohists shift to a preference-satisfaction consequentialism whereby benefiting the world amounts to promoting what happens to please (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  30
    The fabric of creation: theories of place and space in sixth to ninth-century Byzantine philosophy.Alisa Kunitz-Dick - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (1):22-44.
    This article examines the definitions of place or location (topos) and as a consequence, space, in Byzantine philosophy, from Maximos the Confessor to Photios. These philosophers draw, on one hand, on the Aristotelian, Platonic, and Neoplatonic sources, and on the other hand, on the Judeo-Christian tradition. Firstly, Maximos the Confessor sets out a novel definition in which place is conceptually inseparable from time, is needed for substances to exist, and in which place is the boundary between the created and uncreated. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  65
    Cook Wilson on judgement.Simon Wimmer - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (1):126-149.
    John Cook Wilson is increasingly recognised as an important predecessor of ordinary language philosophy. He emphasizes the authority of ordinary language in philosophical theorizing. At the same time, however, he circumscribes the limits of that authority and identifies cases in which it threatens to mislead us. My aim is to consider in detail one case where, according to Cook Wilson, ordinary language has misled philosophical theorizing. Judgement was one of the core notions of the logic, epistemology, and philosophy of mind (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  58
    Reply to Manuel Fasko’s discussion of Mary Shepherd: a guide.Deborah Boyle - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32:1-6.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Nietzsche as Panpsychist.Justin Remhof - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 1 (5):1-23.
    This paper argues that Nietzsche is a panpsychist. Panpsychism holds that mental features are ubiquitous and fundamental in reality. I first argue that Nietzsche’s rejection of Cartesian dualism leads him to substance monism. To better understand his monism, I examine Nietzsche’s rejection of Newtonian atomism. Nietzsche holds that bundles of forces, or will to power, are more fundamental than hard, extended atoms. So, will to power is fundamental. I then investigate Nietzsche’s remarks on organic and inorganic nature to show that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  51.  35
    Hans-Georg Gadamer's "On the idea of a system in philosophy" (1924).Haley Burke & Fridolin Neumann - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy:1-27.
    This article is the first English translation of Gadamer's early essay “On the Idea of a System in Philosophy” (“Zur Systemidee in der Philosophie”) from 1924. Influenced by Marburg Neo-Kantianism and Heidegger's hermeneutic phenomenology, Gadamer is concerned with the problems that arise with the idea of systematicity in philosophy. In particular, he focuses on conceiving of an idea of a system that does justice to the historical variability of philosophical thoughts. He shows that systematicity and history are, in fact, not (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  52. The Great Guide to the Preservation of Life: Malebranche on the Imagination.Colin Chamberlain - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy:1-26.
    Nicolas Malebranche (1638-1715) holds that the senses, imagination, and passions aim at survival and the satisfaction of the body’s needs, rather than truth or the good of the mind. Each of these faculties makes a distinctive and, indeed, an indispensable contribution to the preservation of life. Commentators have largely focused on how the senses keep us alive. By comparison, the imagination and passions have been neglected. In this paper, I reconstruct Malebranche’s account of how the imagination contributes to the preservation (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  53. Aristotle on Logical Consequence.Phil Corkum - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy:1-23.
    Compare two conceptions of validity: under an example of a modal conception, an argument is valid just in case it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false; under an example of a topic-neutral conception, an argument is valid just in case there are no arguments of the same logical form with true premises and a false conclusion. This taxonomy of positions suggests a project in the philosophy of logic: the reductive analysis of the modal conception (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  54.  28
    Divine teleology in Spinoza's thought: an underexplored side of Spinoza’s philosophical journey.Shozo Kamiya - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy:1-19.
    This paper shows that Spinoza went through a drastic change in his view on divine teleology, and that this change is worth paying attention to. In the Short Treatise (KV), Spinoza endorsed a version of divine teleology. As is widely recognized, however, he explicitly rejects divine teleology in the Ethics. I argue that this marks a significant change in his view. To illustrate the significance, I argue that Spinoza consistently maintains the following two premises in both the KV and the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  55.  24
    Resonating strings: understanding the transition from Hume’s Treatise to Second Enquiry.Lauren Kopajtic - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy:1-29.
    What, if anything, changes between Hume's moral theory as presented in the Treatise of Human Nature and then in the Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals? This question has received increased attention, especially focused on Hume's presentation of sympathy and humanity, and the connection of those principles to Hume's account of moral sentiments. While there is a strong consensus that Hume is making important stylistic changes to the presentation of his views, scholars are divided on the question of whether there (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  56. Against the Extremes: Georg Simmel’s Social and Economic Pluralism.Johannes Steizinger - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy:1-21.
    We live in times of an increasing polarization in which the margins of the political spectrum begin to dominate our social imagination again. While the neoliberal iteration of the capitalist project suggests an extreme individualism as the normative default position, the devastating impact of the globalized economy on many has reignited the pursuit of socialist alternatives. In this constellation, Simmel’s social theory of modernity can be a useful resource to undercut the return of the old battle between opposite economic systems. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  57. The possibility of knowing the essence of bodies through scientific experiments in Spinoza’s controversy with Boyle.Oliver Istvan Toth - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy:1-25.
    In this paper, I argue for a novel reading of Spinoza’s position in his exchangewith Boyle about Boyle’s experiment with nitre. Boyle claimed to have shownthrough experiments that nitre ceased to be nitre after heating. Spinozadisagreed and proposed the alternative hypothesis that nitre has changed itsstate and not its nature. Spinoza’s position was construed in the literature asrational scepticism denying that experiments can yield knowledge ofessences because all sensory experience is underdetermined and open tomultiple interpretations. I argue for an alternative (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  58.  11
    Schlick on intuition and prediction.Andreas Vrahimis - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy:1-11.
    Textor’s The Disappearance of the Soul and the Turn Against Metaphysics examines the voluntarist background of Schlick’s epistemology, including his conception of knowledge as essentially involving judgements that relate at least two terms, and his connected objection against according intuition epistemic status. Textor interprets Schlick’s conception of intuition in light of Schopenhauer’s distinction between ordinary and extra-ordinary cognition. Thus Textor argues that Schlick takes intuition to be a form of ‘steady contemplation’ (Disappearance, 348) of an object that is ‘either a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  59.  83
    Simple Esteem and the Method of Commonplaces in Pufendorf.Andreas Blank - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy:1-22.
    In his discussion of simple esteem—one of the moral entities meant to regulate human actions—Pufendorf invokes a juridical commonplace: the rule that, before evidence to the contrary, we should presume others to be good. This argumentative strategy is an illuminating example for understanding his method of commonplaces. The present paper has three goals: (1) to analyze how Pufendorf adopted from legal humanism the view that presumptions should be based on considerations of what comes about most easily in nature; (2) to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  60.  42
    Henri Bergson and the philosophy of religion Henri Bergson and the philosophy of religion, by Matyáš Moravec, New York, Routledge, 2024, pp. 198, £130.00 (hb), ISBN: 978-1-03-239253-0. [REVIEW]Anthony Feneuil - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy:1-6.
    Henri Bergson is usually considered to be a ‘continental’ philosopher. This stimulating book is an attempt to introduce his philosophy into contemporary analytic philosophy of religion. Therefore,...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
 Previous issues
  
Next issues