Results for 'patient noncompliance'

982 found
Order:
  1.  30
    Self-Governed Agency: A Feminist Approach to Patient Noncompliance.Ruth Tallman - 2018 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 11 (1):76-90.
    This paper attempts to determine the best way to understand-and, thus, treat—patients who claim to hold certain health—related values and goals yet consistently act in ways that undermine and work against those values and goals. Since at least the 1970s, this phenomenon has been known in the medical community as patient noncompliance. This can come in the form of failure to take medication as prescribed, as well as failure to adhere to any number of doctors' orders, including recommendations (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  35
    Empathy and structural injustice in the assessment of patient noncompliance.Yolonda Wilson - 2021 - Bioethics 36 (3):283-289.
    Bioethics, Volume 36, Issue 3, Page 283-289, March 2022.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  44
    The Noncompliant Patient: A Kantian and Levinasian Response.P. Burcher - 2012 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 37 (1):74-89.
    When a patient fails to follow the advice or prescription of a physician, she is termed to be "noncompliant" by the medical community. The medical community’s response to and understanding of patient noncompliance fails to acknowledge noncompliance as either a relational failure between physician and patient or as a patient choice. I offer an analysis of Immanuel Kant and Emmanuel Levinas that refocuses the issue of noncompliance by examining the physician role, the doctor– (...) relationship, and the nature of responsibility. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  4.  22
    The Noncompliant Patient In Search of Autonomy.Peter Conrad - 1987 - Hastings Center Report 17 (4):15-17.
    From a medical perspective, patients who do not comply with the doctor's orders are usually seen as deviant and deviance requires correction. But many chronically ill people view their behavior differently, as a matter of self‐regulation. In this light noncompliance supports people's desires for independence and autonomy, desires that align closely with the therapeutic goals of caregivers.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5. Noncompliance by patients.B. Diamond - 1998 - Nursing Ethics 5:65-65.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  47
    The Noncompliant Patient in Psychiatry: The Case For and Against Covert/Surreptitious Medication.K. S. Latha - 2010 - Mens Sana Monographs 8 (1):96.
    Nonadherence to treatment continues to be one of psychiatry's greatest challenges. To improve adherence and thus improve the care of patients, clinicians and patients' family members sometimes resort to hiding medication in food or drink, a practice referred to as covert/ surreptitious medication. The practice of covert drug administration in food and beverages is well known in the treatment of psychiatrically ill world-wide but no prevalence rates exist. Covert medication may seem like a minor matter, but it touches on legal (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7.  10
    Patient and economic benefits of psychological support for noncompliant patients.Phil Reed, Lisa A. Osborne, C. Mair Whittall, Simon Emery & Roberto Truzoli - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    The current paper provides an overview of treatment noncompliance at various points in the treatment pathway, especially with respect to treatment for Pelvic-floor Dysfunction. The effects of noncompliance on healthcare are considered, and examples of supporting patients psychologically to increase compliance are discussed. An outline of a method to identify costs of non-compliance, and where such costs most intensely impact the healthcare system, is provided. It is suggested that psychological support is effective in terms of increased compliance and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  64
    Why Treat Noncompliant Patients? Beyond the Decent Minimum Account.N. Eyal - 2011 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 36 (6):572-588.
    Patients’ medical conditions can result from their own avoidable risk taking. Some lung diseases result from avoidable smoking and some traffic accidents result from victims’ reckless driving. Although in many nonmedical areas we hold people responsible for taking risks they could avoid, it is normally harsh and inappropriate to deny patients care because they risked needing it. Why? A popular account is that protecting everyone’s "decent minimum," their basic needs, matters more than the benefits of holding people accountable. This account (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9. Rational Noncompliance with Prescribed Medical Treatment.Douglas O. Stewart & Joseph P. DeMarco - 2010 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 20 (3):277-290.
    Patient noncompliance with physician prescriptions, especially in nonsymptomatic chronic diseases, is frequently characterized in the literature as harmful and economically costly (Miller 1997).1 Nancy Houston Miller views patient noncompliance as harmful because noncompliance can result in continued or new health problems leading to hospital admissions. Further, she places the annual monetary cost of noncompliance at $100 billion.Patient noncompliance with prescribed treatment is considered the least understood form of health behavior (Coons 2001). Despite (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  20
    A Noncompliant Patient?K. L. Moseley & S. Truesdell - 1997 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 8 (2):176-177.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  22
    Retransplantation and the “Noncompliant” Patient.Mark G. Kuczewski - 1999 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 8 (3):375-375.
    The patient was a 19-year-old female who was transferred to this children's hospital from a community hospital in a neighboring state. She is well known to the hospital staff because she had a kidney transplanted and retransplanted several times there. Her first transplant as at age 8 and she was retransplanted most recently approximately 3 years ago. She immediately rejected her second kidney and received a third. She is currently admitted because she is again rejecting her kidney, probably due (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  50
    The Ethical Management of the Noncompliant Patient.Alister Browne, Brent Dickson & Rena van der Wal - 2003 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 12 (3):289-299.
    It is a rare patient who always does everything healthcare providers advise. Sometimes no harm comes from this; sometimes good does. But occasionally, great harm comes from not listening, as when it results in patients returning time and again for costly and invasive treatments of, say, infections, valve replacements, pressure ulcers, and so forth. No class of patients arouses more anger and resentment in healthcare providers, who often put out a call to invoke some version of the three strikes (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  14
    Care, Support, and Concern for Noncompliant Patients.Philip R. Muskin - 1997 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 8 (2):178-180.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  23
    Hospital Collections: Can Hill-Burton Noncompliance Be Raised by Former Patients as an Affirmative Defense?Albert Speisman - 1982 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 10 (6):216-221.
  15.  41
    Volitional disability and physician attitudes toward noncompliance.J. Bergen - 1984 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 9 (4).
    We develop the concept of a volitional disability as an aid in understanding those patients who behave in ways that are harmful to themselves in spite of their desire to do otherwise. Using this concept enables us to describe their behavior as intentional but ‘unvoluntary’. We demonstrate the clinical reality of such behavior by giving clinical examples of the behavior of those with phobic, compulsive, and addictive disorders. We then attempt to show how some kinds of self-harming behavior of noncompliant (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  84
    Civil disobedience, conscientious objection, and evasive noncompliance: A framework for the analysis and assessment of illegal actions in health care.James F. Childress - 1985 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 10 (1):63-84.
    This essay explores some of the conceptual and moral issues raised by illegal actions in health care. The author first identifies several types of illegal action, concentrating on civil disobedience, conscientious objection or refusal, and evasive noncompliance. Then he sketches a framework for the moral justification of these types of illegal action. Finally, he applies the conceptual and normative frameworks to several major cases of illegal action in health care, such as "mercy killing" and some decisions not to treat (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  17.  36
    Volitional Disability and Physician Attitudes Toward Noncompliance.R. B. Ferrell, T. R. P. Price, B. Gert & B. J. Bergen - 1984 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 9 (4):333-352.
    We develop the concept of a volitional disability as an aid in understanding those patients who behave in ways that are harmful to themselves in spite of their desire to do otherwise. Using this concept enables us to describe their behavior as intentional but ‘unvoluntary’. We demonstrate the clinical reality of such behavior by giving clinical examples of the behavior of those with phobic, compulsive, and addictive disorders. We then attempt to show how some kinds of self-harming behavior of noncompliant (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  65
    An economic theory of patient decision-making.Douglas O. Stewart & Joseph P. DeMarco - 2005 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 2 (3):153-164.
    Patient autonomy, as exercised in the informed consent process, is a central concern in bioethics. The typical bioethicist's analysis of autonomy centers on decisional capacity—finding the line between autonomy and its absence. This approach leaves unexplored the structure of reasoning behind patient treatment decisions. To counter that approach, we present a microeconomic theory of patient decision-making regarding the acceptable level of medical treatment from the patient's perspective. We show that a rational patient's desired treatment level (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  19.  21
    Compliance or Collaboration? the Meaning for the Patient.Katherine N. Moore - 1995 - Nursing Ethics 2 (1):71-77.
    Noncompliance exasperates health care professionals, leaves them worrying about the effective outcome of medical care, and results in noncompliant patients being labelled as 'difficult' or 'troublesome'. It is suggested that professionals who label a patient as noncompliant are following convenient paternalistic principles rather than considering the impact of a prescribed regimen on an individual patient. In this paper, the author considers autonomy and respect to be foremost in patient care. Further, compliance does not necessarily indicate that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  11
    Financial Decision-Making Capacity and Patient-Centered Discharge.Annette Mendola - 2020 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 31 (2):178-183.
    An ethically sound discharge from the hospital can be impeded by a number of factors, including a lack of payor for a patient’s care, a lack of appropriate discharge options, and a lack of authority to sign a patient into a long-term facility. In some cases, the primary barrier involves the patient’s lack of financial decision-making capacity.When a patient’s income comes primarily from government assistance, financial decision making is connected to both the individual’s well-being and to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  19
    Positive Change in Perception and Care for a Difficult Patient.Melissa Cavanaugh - 2023 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 13 (1):1-2.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Positive Change in Perception and Care for a Difficult PatientMelissa CavanaughIf you asked any healthcare professional if they had ever cared for a difficult patient, I am certain the answer would be a resounding "Yes!" I have encountered many over my forty-two years as an RN. The story of Ms. E. is one of exceptional challenge and, I hope, success.I met Ms. E. in 2012 when I took (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  19
    The Hang Up.Laura Specker Sullivan - 2020 - Hastings Center Report 50 (3):15-16.
    Over the past year, our ethics service has had numerous consultations involving patients who use the emergency department for regular dialysis. Sometimes, they have access to outpatient hemodialysis that they forgo; other times, they've been “fired” from this kind of outpatient facility, and so the ED is their last option. In most of these cases, we're called because the patient is disruptive once admitted to the ICU and behavior plans haven't helped. But the call from a resident this March (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  51
    Covert treatment in psychiatry: Do no harm, true, but also dare to care.Ajai R. Singh - 2008 - Mens Sana Monographs 6 (1):81.
    _Covert treatment raises a number of ethical and practical issues in psychiatry. Viewpoints differ from the standpoint of psychiatrists, caregivers, ethicists, lawyers, neighbours, human rights activists and patients. There is little systematic research data on its use but it is quite certain that there is relatively widespread use. The veil of secrecy around the procedure is due to fear of professional censure. Whenever there is a veil of secrecy around anything, which is aided and abetted by vociferous opposition from some (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  36
    Commentary.Robert Gatter - 1999 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 8 (3):377-378.
    This case is not about whether retransplant candidates should receive organs over first-time candidates, or whether risks of transplant failure from psychological or social factors are relevant to allocating organs. Rather, it concerns only this patient's qualifications to wait for a kidney transplant. Should the patient's prior transplants, noncompliance, and poor social network exclude her even from the waiting list? Do attending physicians inappropriately favor their patients over all others in need of transplants just by listing them? (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  46
    Spirituality in Nursing Theory and Practice: Dilemmas for Christian Bioethics.S. A. Salladay & J. A. Shelly - 1997 - Christian Bioethics 3 (1):20-38.
    Moral strangerhood is due in part to competing worldviews. The profession of nursing is experiencing a paradigm shift which creates ethical dilemmas for both Christian nurses and Christian patients. Nursing's new focus on spirituality and spiritual care presents itself as broadly defining a desired state or patient outcome — spiritual integrity — supposed to be applicable to all patients of all faiths. Analysis of nursing's definition of spirituality reveals assumptions and values consistent with an Eastern/New Age worldview which may (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  24
    Listen Carefully.Josephine Ensign - 2015 - Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 58 (1):32-32.
    Trying to obtain a medical history from a patient, I listen to her story. She’s a difficult patient, as in noncompliant, narcotic-seeking chronic-pain-in-the-ass patient. There’s a Physician’s Field Guide to the Difficult Patient, a chapter for each type. If you stop to listen, to question the words used, you may never finish this medical..
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  70
    Professionalism Department.Mark Wicclair & David Barnard - 2012 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 21 (2):247-248.
    In this issue of CQ, we are pleased to inaugurate a new Department, Professionalism, with an article by Jeffrey Blustein entitled “When Doctors Break the Rules: On the Ethics of Physician Noncompliance.” The article examines the ethical dilemmas physicians face when they believe that promoting the best interests of patients requires them to break one or more institutional rules.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  9
    Comment.John Wilkinson - 1998 - Nursing Ethics 5 (2):167-172.
    A recent article published in Nursing Ethics, written by Professor Bridgit Dimond, highlighted the topic of noncompliance by patients and attention was drawn to a number of issues relevant to health care professionals. In this response, some specific challenges facing nurses are considered in the light of Professor Dimond’s arguments. In doing so, the notion of compliance as an appropriate concept in modern nursing practice is questioned. The recommendations to emerge include strategies to consider patient response to treatment (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  20
    The Transformation: Power in Persistence and Perspective.Tyler Bendrick - 2023 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 13 (1):7-10.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Transformation:Power in Persistence and PerspectiveTyler BendrickWe've got another meth napper," my resident stated. With an introduction like that, it is hard not to be immediately labeled as a "difficult patient." Being the only Spanish-speaking person on the team, I, a third-year medical student, became the primary point of contact for this severely injured patient. He was an only-Spanish-speaking, 36-year-old male admitted [End Page 7] to our (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  24
    Conflicting Voices.James M. Badger & Rosalind Ekman Ladd - 2011 - Jona's Healthcare Law, Ethics, and Regulation 13 (3):79-83.
    al treatment of episodic substance intoxicated states with or without self-inflicted injuries. Patients later can develop comorbid medical illnesses associated with nonadherence of treatment or iatrogenic conditions, both of which result in complex end-of-life-care decisions. Institutional familiarity of repeat patients often leaves healthcare providers feeling responsible for the patient despite having little influence over the patients' ultimate behavioral outcomes. This article describes a patient with chronic alcohol abuse, treatment noncompliance, severe personality disorder, recurrent suicidal ideation, self-injurious behavior, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  23
    Physicians' Refusals of Service on Grounds of Conscience.Lance K. Stell - 2019 - Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 62 (3):452-469.
    … no physician, in so far as he is a physician, considers his own good in what he prescribes, but the good of his patient, for the true physician … is not a mere money-maker.A physician shall, in the provision of appropriate patient care, except in emergencies, be free to choose whom to serve, with whom to associate, and the environment in which to provide medical care.[We] are agents. Our constitution is put in our power. We are charged (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  59
    Rejoinder.Douglas O. Stewart & Joseph P. DeMarco - 2006 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 3 (3):137-138.
  33. Timothy F. Murphy.A. Patient'S. Right To Know - 1994 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 19 (4-6):553-569.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Subject Index to Volume 29.Teen Smokers, Adolescent Patient Confidentiality & Whom Are We Kidding - 2001 - Substance 125 (131):279.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  5
    Lisa’s Story.Lisa P. Patient) & Jeanne Kerwin - 2024 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 14 (1):7-10.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Lisa’s StoryLisa P. (wife of patient) and Jeanne KerwinMy husband suffered from sudden onset of heart failure with a very low ejection fraction and was on IV Milrinone at the age of 47. One of the most powerful things he told me was that he was not afraid to die and therefore did not want to move forward with Milrinone. He eventually “did it for the kids.” After (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  19
    trotz schlechter Prognose?Ein Patient - 2008 - Ethik in der Medizin 20 (1):53.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Artificial Intelligence and Patient-Centered Decision-Making.Jens Christian Bjerring & Jacob Busch - 2020 - Philosophy and Technology 34 (2):349-371.
    Advanced AI systems are rapidly making their way into medical research and practice, and, arguably, it is only a matter of time before they will surpass human practitioners in terms of accuracy, reliability, and knowledge. If this is true, practitioners will have a prima facie epistemic and professional obligation to align their medical verdicts with those of advanced AI systems. However, in light of their complexity, these AI systems will often function as black boxes: the details of their contents, calculations, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  38.  17
    Competency frameworks, nursing perspectives, and interdisciplinary collaborations for good patient care: Delineating boundaries.Maya Zumstein-Shaha & Pamela J. Grace - 2023 - Nursing Philosophy 24 (1):e12402.
    To enhance patient care in the inevitable conditions of complexity that exist in contemporary healthcare, collaboration among healthcare professions is critical. While each profession necessarily has its own primary focus and perspective on the nature of human healthcare needs, these alone are insufficient for meeting the complex needs of patients (and potential patients). Persons are inevitably contextual entities, inseparable from their environments, and are subject to institutional and social barriers that can detract from good care or from accessing healthcare. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  30
    Love Your Patient as Yourself: On Reviving the Broken Heart of American Medical Ethics.Tyler Tate & Joseph Clair - 2023 - Hastings Center Report 53 (2):12-25.
    This article presents a radical claim: American medical ethics is broken, and it needs love to be healed. Due to a unique set of cultural and economic pressures, American medical ethics has adopted a mechanistic mode of ethical reasoning epitomized by the doctrine of principlism. This mode of reasoning divorces clinicians from both their patients and themselves. This results in clinicians who can ace ethics questions on multiple‐choice tests but who fail either to recognize a patient's humanity or to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  40.  13
    Short literature notices.Doctor–Patient Talk - 1999 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 2 (1):55-67.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  48
    The “Difficult” Patient Reconceived: An Expanded Moral Mandate for Clinical Ethics.Autumn Fiester - 2012 - American Journal of Bioethics 12 (5):2-7.
    Between 15 and 60% of patients are considered ?difficult? by their treating physicians. Patient psychiatric pathology is the conventional explanation for why patients are deemed ?difficult.? But the prevalence of the problem suggests the possibility of a less pathological cause. I argue that the phenomenon can be better explained as a response to problematic interactions related to health care delivery. If there are grounds to reconceive the ?difficult? patient as reacting to the perception of ill treatment, then there (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  42.  44
    The potential impact of decision role and patient age on end-of-life treatment decision making.B. J. Zikmund-Fisher, H. P. Lacey & A. Fagerlin - 2008 - Journal of Medical Ethics 34 (5):327-331.
    Background: Recent research demonstrates that people sometimes make different medical decisions for others than they would make for themselves. This finding is particularly relevant to end-of-life decisions, which are often made by surrogates and require a trade-off between prolonging life and maintaining quality of life. We examine the impact of decision role, patient age, decision maker age and multiple individual differences on these treatment decisions. Methods: Participants read a scenario about a terminally ill cancer patient faced with a (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  43.  23
    Ethical conflicts in patient relationships: Experiences of ambulance nursing students.Anders Bremer & Mats Holmberg - 2020 - Nursing Ethics 27 (4):946-959.
    Background Working as an ambulance nurse involves facing ethically problematic situations with multi-dimensional suffering, requiring the ability to create a trustful relationship. This entails a need to be clinically trained in order to identify ethical conflicts. Aim To describe ethical conflicts in patient relationships as experienced by ambulance nursing students during clinical studies. Research design An exploratory and interpretative design was used to inductively analyse textual data from examinations in clinical placement courses. Participants The 69 participants attended a 1-year (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  44. Medit︠s︡ina, vrach-pat︠s︡ient: medit︠s︡ina: vrach-pat︠s︡ient: rezulʹtaty mnogoletnikh nabli︠u︡deniĭ i osmysleniĭ = Medicine, physician-patient: the result of long term observation and reflections.Mark T︠S︡yvkin - 1996 - Nʹi︠u︡-Ĭork: Izd-vo "Mir Collection".
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. What is Patient-Centered Care? A Typology of Models and Missions.Sandra J. Tanenbaum - 2015 - Health Care Analysis 23 (3):272-287.
    Recently adopted health care practices and policies describe themselves as “patient-centered care.” The meaning of the term, however, remains contested and obscure. This paper offers a typology of “patient-centered care” models that aims to contribute to greater clarity about, continuing discussion of, and further advances in patient-centered care. The paper imposes an original analytic framework on extensive material covering mostly US health care and health policy topics over several decades. It finds that four models of patient-centered (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  46.  85
    Doing what the patient orders: Maintaining integrity in the doctor‐patient relationship.Jeffrey Blustein - 1993 - Bioethics 7 (4):289-314.
    No profession has undergone as much scrutiny in the past several decades as that of medicine. Indeed, one might well argue that no profession has ever undergone so much change in so short a time. An essential part of this change has been the growing insistence that competent, adult patients have the right to decide about the course of their own medical treatment. However, the familiar and widely accepted principle of patient self-determination entails a corollary that has received little (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  47. Shared Decision Making, Paternalism and Patient Choice.Lars Sandman & Christian Munthe - 2010 - Health Care Analysis 18 (1):60-84.
    In patient centred care, shared decision making is a central feature and widely referred to as a norm for patient centred medical consultation. However, it is far from clear how to distinguish SDM from standard models and ideals for medical decision making, such as paternalism and patient choice, and e.g., whether paternalism and patient choice can involve a greater degree of the sort of sharing involved in SDM and still retain their essential features. In the article, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  48.  33
    Conscience in Reproductive Health Care: Prioritizing Patient Interests.Carolyn McLeod - 2020 - Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
    Conscience in Reproductive Health Care responds to the growing worldwide trend of health care professionals conscientiously refusing to provide abortions and similar reproductive health services in countries where these services are legal and professionally accepted. Carolyn McLeod argues that conscientious objectors in health care should prioritize the interests of patients in receiving care over their own interest in acting on their conscience. She defends this "prioritizing approach" to conscientious objection over the more popular "compromise approach" without downplaying the importance of (...)
  49. Free Choice and Patient Best Interests.Emma C. Bullock - 2016 - Health Care Analysis 24 (4):374-392.
    In medical practice, the doctrine of informed consent is generally understood to have priority over the medical practitioner’s duty of care to her patient. A common consequentialist argument for the prioritisation of informed consent above the duty of care involves the claim that respect for a patient’s free choice is the best way of protecting that patient’s best interests; since the patient has a special expertise over her values and preferences regarding non-medical goods she is ideally (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  50. Zhuangzi's "Difference Stories" and Patient Moral Relativism.Waldemar Brys - 2024 - In Xiangnong Hu & Yong Huang (eds.), Ethics in the Zhuangzi: Dialogues on the State of the Field. Cham: Springer. pp. 65-76.
    I examine passages from the Zhuangzi that proponents of interpreting Zhuangzian ethics as "patient moral relativism" (PMR) primarily draw on to support their view. I consider whether in these passages Zhuangzi morally evaluates agents or their actions, and if he does, whether his evaluations support ascribing to him PMR. My argument is that Zhuangzi either fails to make the required moral evaluations or he makes moral evaluations that do not accord with PMR. A PMR-friendly reading is possible only if (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 982