Results for 'notational variant'

965 found
Order:
  1.  89
    Notational Variants and Invariance in Linguistics.Kent Johnson - 2015 - Mind and Language 30 (2):162-186.
    This article argues that the much-maligned ‘notational variants’ of a given formal linguistic theory play a role similar to alternative numerical measurement scales. Thus, they can be used to identify the invariant components of the grammar; i.e., those features that do not depend on the choice of empirically equivalent representation. Treating these elements as the ‘meaningful’ structure of language has numerous consequences for the philosophy of science and linguistics. I offer several such examples of how linguistic theorizing can profit (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  2.  76
    Notational Variants and Cognition: The Case of Dependency Grammar.Ryan M. Nefdt & Giosué Baggio - 2024 - Erkenntnis 89 (7):2867-2897.
    In recent years, dependency grammars have established themselves as valuable tools in theoretical and computational linguistics. To many linguists, dependency grammars and the more standard constituency-based formalisms are notational variants. We argue that, beyond considerations of formal equivalence, cognition may also serve as a background for a genuine comparison between these different views of syntax. In this paper, we review and evaluate some of the most common arguments and evidence employed to advocate for the cognitive or neural reality of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. On the Concept of a Notational Variant.Alexander W. Kocurek - 2017 - In Alexandru Baltag, Jeremy Seligman & Tomoyuki Yamada (eds.), Logic, Rationality, and Interaction (LORI 2017, Sapporo, Japan). Springer. pp. 284-298.
    In the study of modal and nonclassical logics, translations have frequently been employed as a way of measuring the inferential capabilities of a logic. It is sometimes claimed that two logics are “notational variants” if they are translationally equivalent. However, we will show that this cannot be quite right, since first-order logic and propositional logic are translationally equivalent. Others have claimed that for two logics to be notational variants, they must at least be compositionally intertranslatable. The definition of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  4.  22
    Kneale’s Natural Deductions as a Notational Variant of Beth’s Tableaus.Zvonimir Šikić - 2022 - Logica Universalis 16 (1):11-26.
    Gentzen’s singular sequential system of first-order logic was an alternative notation for his system of natural deductions. His multiple sequential system was his symmetric generalization that was more appropriate to classical logic. Beth’s tableaus system was a system that was derived directly from the semantic analysis of connectives and quantifiers. It was soon realized that the Beth’s system and the Gentzen’s multiple system were only notational variants of each other. Kneale’s system of multiple natural deductions was a generalization of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  97
    Notational Variance and Its Variants.Rohan French - 2019 - Topoi 38 (2):321-331.
    What does it take for two logics to be mere notational variants? The present paper proposes a variety of different ways of cashing out notational variance, in particular isolating a constraint on any reasonable account of notational variance which makes plausible that the only kinds of translations which can witness notational variance are what are sometimes called definitional translations.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  6. Ontological Pluralism and Notational Variance.Bruno Whittle - 2021 - Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 12:58-72.
    Ontological pluralism is the view that there are different ways to exist. It is a position with deep roots in the history of philosophy, and in which there has been a recent resurgence of interest. In contemporary presentations, it is stated in terms of fundamental languages: as the view that such languages contain more than one quantifier. For example, one ranging over abstract objects, and another over concrete ones. A natural worry, however, is that the languages proposed by the pluralist (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7.  38
    Questions to Danielle Macbeth on Frege's Logical Notation and Related Topics.Fabrice Pataut - unknown
    Danielle Macbeth's purpose in Macbeth 2005 is threefold. Her monograph proposes "to provide a logical justification for all aspects of Frege's peculiar notation, to motivate and explain the developments in Frege's views over the course of his intellectual life, and to explicate his most developed, critically reflective conception of his Begriffschrift, his formula language of pure thought" (p. vii). I shall focus here on a few selected aspects of the first and third points and leave on the side the discussion (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  40
    (1 other version)Gentzen Gerhard. Recherches sur la déduction logique. French translation of 4422 by Ladrière Jean, with added footnotes by the translator. Presses Universitaires de France, Paris 1955, XI + 170 pp.Feys Robert. Préface. Therein, pp. VII–XI.Feys Robert. Note A. Les méthodes de déduction naturelle. Therein, pp. 1–2.Feys Robert. Note B. Notation explicite des suppositions. Therein, pp. 29–34.Feys Robert. Note C. Méthodes N de Jaśkowski, Bernays et Johannson. Therein pp. 35–39.Feys Robert. Note D. Variantes des calculs LK et LJ. Therein, pp. 77–83.Ladrière Jean. Note E. Un calcul “MK” analogue au calcul NK. Therein, pp. 84–89.Feys Robert. Note F. Signification des séquences et des schémas de structure. Therein, pp. 90–92.Ladriére Jean. Note G. Les schémas de coupure et de fusion de séquences. Therein, pp. 93–97.Ladriére Jean. Note H. Tableau de la démonstration du théorème fondamental. Therein, pp. 98–100.Ladriére Jean. Note I. Marche de la démonstration du théorème fondamental. Therein, pp. [REVIEW]John van Heijenoort - 1957 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 22 (4):350-351.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  29
    Independence results for variants of sharply bounded induction.Leszek Aleksander Kołodziejczyk - 2011 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (12):981-990.
    The theory , axiomatized by the induction scheme for sharply bounded formulae in Buss’ original language of bounded arithmetic , has recently been unconditionally separated from full bounded arithmetic S2. The method used to prove the separation is reminiscent of those known from the study of open induction.We make the connection to open induction explicit, showing that models of can be built using a “nonstandard variant” of Wilkie’s well-known technique for building models of IOpen. This makes it possible to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10. Prefixed tableaus and nested sequents.Melvin Fitting - 2012 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 163 (3):291 - 313.
    Nested sequent systems for modal logics are a relatively recent development, within the general area known as deep reasoning. The idea of deep reasoning is to create systems within which one operates at lower levels in formulas than just those involving the main connective or operator. Prefixed tableaus go back to 1972, and are modal tableau systems with extra machinery to represent accessibility in a purely syntactic way. We show that modal nested sequents and prefixed modal tableaus are notational (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  11. The ’Structure’ of Physics.Jill North - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy 106 (2):57–88.
    We are used to talking about the “structure” posited by a given theory of physics, such as the spacetime structure of relativity. What is “structure”? What does the mathematical structure used to formulate a theory tell us about the physical world according to the theory? What if there are different mathematical formulations of a given theory? Do different formulations posit different structures, or are they merely notational variants? I consider the case of Lagrangian and Hamiltonian classical mechanics. I argue (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  12. A modal perspective on the computational complexity of attribute value grammar.Patrick Blackburn & Edith Spaan - 1993 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 2 (2):129-169.
    Many of the formalisms used in Attribute Value grammar are notational variants of languages of propositional modal logic, and testing whether two Attribute Value Structures unify amounts to testing for modal satisfiability. In this paper we put this observation to work. We study the complexity of the satisfiability problem for nine modal languages which mirror different aspects of AVS description formalisms, including the ability to express re-entrancy, the ability to express generalisations, and the ability to express recursive constraints. Two (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  13. How the Formal Equivalence of Grue and Green Defeats What is New in the New Riddle of Induction.John D. Norton - 2006 - Synthese 150 (2):185-207.
    That past patterns may continue in many different ways has long been identified as a problem for accounts of induction. The novelty of Goodman’s ”new riddle of induction” lies in a meta-argument that purports to show that no account of induction can discriminate between incompatible continuations. That meta-argument depends on the perfect symmetry of the definitions of grue/bleen and green/blue, so that any evidence that favors the ordinary continuation must equally favor the grue-ified continuation. I argue that this very dependence (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  14.  4
    No matter who: what makes one a relativist?Eduardo Pérez-Navarro - 2021 - Theoria : An International Journal for Theory, History and Fundations of Science 36 (2):231-242.
    As part of her argument that relativism and contextualism are nothing but notational variants of each other, Stojanovic holds that contextualism is flexible enough to achieve whatever relativism might do if the matter is what truth-value is assigned to each pair of sentence and context. In this paper, I reply to this statement by arguing that contextualism cannot be made as flexible as relativism without in fact turning it into a version of relativism. The key to my response to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15.  70
    Can there be a feature‐placing language?Krasimira Filcheva - 2023 - European Journal of Philosophy 31 (3):655-672.
    The aim of this article is to argue against the real possibility of languages without subject‐predicate structure, so‐called feature‐placing languages. They were first introduced by Strawson (1959/1990), later given formal expression through Quine's Predicate Functor Logic (Quine, 1960, Quine, 1971/Quine, 1976, Quine, 1992), and further elaboration in (Hawthorne & Cortens, 1995). I argue that, on the presumption that feature‐placing languages are not mere notational variants on first‐order languages, the idea of such languages is incoherent. The argument for this view (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16. Talking about taste: Disagreement, implicit arguments, and relative truth.Isidora Stojanovic - 2007 - Linguistics and Philosophy 30 (6):691-706.
    In this paper, I take issue with an idea that has emerged from recent relativist proposals, and, in particular, from Lasersohn, according to which the correct semantics for taste predicates must use contents that are functions of a judge parameter rather than implicit arguments lexically associated with such predicates. I argue that the relativist account and the contextualist implicit argument-account are, from the viewpoint of semantics, not much more than notational variants of one another. In other words, given any (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   138 citations  
  17. Is Phenomenal Character Out There in the World?Jeff Speaks - 2014 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 91 (2):465-482.
    In recent work, Michael Tye has criticized a certain sort of representationalist view of experience for holding that phenomenal characters are properties of experiences. Instead, Tye holds that phenomenal character is 'out there in the world.' This paper has two aims. One is to argue for the somewhat surprising conclusion that Tye’s apparently radical new view is not a change in view at all, but a notational variant of a standard representationalist theory. My more general aim, though, is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  18.  47
    Intuitionistic sets and numbers: small set theory and Heyting arithmetic.Stewart Shapiro, Charles McCarty & Michael Rathjen - forthcoming - Archive for Mathematical Logic.
    It has long been known that (classical) Peano arithmetic is, in some strong sense, “equivalent” to the variant of (classical) Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (including choice) in which the axiom of infinity is replaced by its negation. The intended model of the latter is the set of hereditarily finite sets. The connection between the theories is so tight that they may be taken as notational variants of each other. Our purpose here is to develop and establish a constructive version (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. On Two Interpretations of the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Prudential Value.Joseph van Weelden - 2019 - Utilitas 31 (2):137-156.
    This article considers two different ways of formulating a desire-satisfaction theory of prudential value. The first version of the theory (the object view) assigns basic prudential value to the state of affairs that is the object of a person’s desire. The second version (the combo view) assigns basic prudential value to the compound state of affairs in which (a) a person desires some state of affairs and (b) this state of affairs obtains. My aims in this article are twofold. First, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  20. Derrida’s Differance and Plato’s Different.I. I. I. Wheeler - 1999 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (4):999-1013.
    This essay shows that Derrida’s discussion of “Differance,” is remarkably parallel to Plato’s discussion of Difference in the Parmenides. Plato’s presentation of “Parmenides’” discussion of generation from a One which Is is a version of Derrida’s preconceptual spacing. Derrida’s implicit reference to Plato both interprets Plato and explains the obscure features of “Differance.” Derrida’s paradoxical remarks about Differance are very like what Plato implies about Difference.Derrida’s Differance addresses the puzzle that concepts are required to construct the beings in a plurality (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. How to be an adverbialist about phenomenal intentionality.Kyle Banick - 2018 - Synthese 198 (1):661-686.
    Kriegel has revived adverbialism as a theory of consciousness. But recent attacks have shed doubt on the viability of the theory. To save adverbialism, I propose that the adverbialist take a stance on the nature of adverbial modification. On one leading theory, adverbial modification turns on the instantiation by a substance of a psychological type. But the resulting formulation of adverbialism turns out to be a mere notational variant on the relationalist approaches against which Kriegel dialectically situates adverbialism. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  22.  91
    Second-order logic : ontological and epistemological problems.Marcus Rossberg - 2006 - Dissertation, St Andrews
    In this thesis I provide a survey over different approaches to second-order logic and its interpretation, and introduce a novel approach. Of special interest are the questions whether second-order logic can count as logic in some proper sense of logic, and what epistemic status it occupies. More specifically, second-order logic is sometimes taken to be mathematical, a mere notational variant of some fragment of set theory. If this is the case, it might be argued that it does not (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  23. Indexicality and Cognitive Significance: the Indispensability of Sense.João Branquinho - 2017 - Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia 73 (3-4):1517-1540.
    This paper is devoted to the topic of indexicality in relation to the problem of cognitive significance. I undertake a critical examination of what I call the Millian Notational Variance Claim; this is the claim that those versions of a neo-Fregean semantics for demonstratives and other indexicals which rest upon the notion of a de re sense are eventually notational variants of a directly referential or Millian semantics for indexicals. I try to show that several lines of reasoning (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. The formal equivalence of grue and green and how it undoes the new Riddle of induction.John D. Norton - unknown
    The hidden strength of Goodman's ingenious "new riddle of induction" lies in the perfect symmetry of grue/bleen and green/blue. The very same sentence forms used to define grue/bleen in terms of green/blue can be used to define green/blue in terms of grue/bleen by permutation of terms. Therein lies its undoing. In the artificially restricted case in which there are no additional facts that can break the symmetry, grue/bleen and green/blue are merely notational variants of the same facts; or, if (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25. On Wright’s Inductive Definition of Coherence Truth for Arithmetic.Jeffrey Ketland - 2003 - Analysis 63 (1):6-15.
    In “Truth – A Traditional Debate Reviewed”, Crispin Wright proposed an inductive definition of “coherence truth” for arithmetic relative to an arithmetic base theory B. Wright’s definition is in fact a notational variant of the usual Tarskian inductive definition, except for the basis clause for atomic sentences. This paper provides a model-theoretic characterization of the resulting sets of sentences "cohering" with a given base theory B. These sets are denoted WB. Roughly, if B satisfies a certain minimal condition, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  44
    Paraconsistent or Paracomplete?Hartry Field - 2019 - In Can Başkent & Thomas Macaulay Ferguson (eds.), Graham Priest on Dialetheism and Paraconsistency. Cham, Switzerland: Springer Verlag. pp. 73-125.
    This paper attempts a comprehensive account of the comparative merits of paracomplete and dialetheic approaches to the semantic paradoxes. It argues that aside from issues about conditionals, there can be no strong case for paracomplete approaches over dialetheic, or dialetheic over paracomplete, and indeed that in absence of conditionals, the two approaches are plausibly seen as notational variants. Graham Priest disagrees: many of his arguments favoring dialetheic solutions over paracomplete do not turn on issues about conditionals. The paper discusses (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. A Language for Ontological Nihilism.Catharine Diehl - 2018 - Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 5:971-996.
    According to ontological nihilism there are, fundamentally, no individuals. Both natural languages and standard predicate logic, however, appear to be committed to a picture of the world as containing individual objects. This leads to what I call the \emph{expressibility challenge} for ontological nihilism: what language can the ontological nihilist use to express her account of how matters fundamentally stand? One promising suggestion is for the nihilist to use a form of \emph{predicate functorese}, a language developed by Quine. This proposal faces (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  28. On Danielle Macbeth's "Frege's Logic".Fabrice Pataut - unknown
    Danielle Macbeth's purpose in Macbeth 2005 is threefold. Her monograph proposes "to provide a logical justification for all aspects of Frege's peculiar notation, to motivate and explain the developments in Frege's views over the course of his intellectual life, and to explicate his most developed, critically reflective conception of his Begriffschrift, his formula language of pure thought". I shall focus here on a few selected aspects of the first and third points and leave on the side the discussion of the (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  38
    セマンティック Web 推論と議論エージェント推論の統合.Sawamura Hajime Wakaki Toshiko - 2007 - Transactions of the Japanese Society for Artificial Intelligence 22 (3):322-331.
    Though many kinds of multi-agent systems based on argumentation have been proposed where only rule-based knowledge is taken into account, they have been unable to handle the ontological knowledge so far. In our daily life, however, there are a lot of human argumentation where both ontological and rule knowledges are used. For example, in e-commerce, a seller and a buyer usually use ontologies about products along with their respective strategic rules for buying and selling. Recent progress of the Semantic Web (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Are Salmon's 'Guises' Disguised Fregean Senses?João Branquinho - 1990 - Analysis 50 (1):19 - 24.
    In a review of Frege's Puzzle1, Graeme Forbes makes the claim that Salmon's account of belief might be seen, under certain conditions, as a mere notational variant of a neo-Fregean theory; and thus that such an account might be reduced to a neo-Fregean one simply by rewriting it in terms of Fregean terminology. With a view to supporting his claim, Forbes offers an outline of an account of belief which, according to him, would satisfy the following conditions: (i) (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  31.  80
    Derrida's Differance and Plato's Different.Samuel C. Wheeler - 1999 - Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 59 (4):999-1013.
    This essay shows that Derrida's discussion of "Differance," is remarkably parallel to Plato's discussion of Difference in the Parmenides. Plato's presentation of "Parmenides'" discussion of generation from a One which Is is a version of Derrida's preconceptual spacing. Derrida's implicit reference to Plato both interprets Plato and explains the obscure features of "Differance." Derrida's paradoxical remarks about Differance are very like what Plato implies about Difference. Derrida's Differance addresses the puzzle that concepts are required to construct the beings in a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  32.  24
    A note on the gifted mathematician that you claim to be.Alexander Grosu & Manfred Krifka - 2022 - Linguistics and Philosophy 45 (6):1227-1233.
    The paper is a reply to Bassi and Rasin ( 2018 ) on the treatment of sentences like [_The gifted mathematician that you claim to be_] _should have solved this task without problems_ by Grosu and Krifka ( 2007 ), which was published in _Linguistics and Philosophy_. Grosu and Krifka provide an analysis of the _de dicto_ interpretation in which the bracketed expression refers to an individual concept. Bassi and Rasin question this because equivalent expressions in Hebrew, in which the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Is semantics formal?Mark Schroeder - manuscript
    In this paper I will be concerned with the question of the extent to which semantics can be thought of as a purely formal exercise, which we can engage in in a way that is neutral with respect to how our formal system is to be interpreted. I will be arguing, to the contrary, that the features of the formal systems which we use to do semantics are closely linked, in several different ways, to the interpretation that we give to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  34. How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love 'Sherlock Holmes': A Reply to Garcia-Carpintero.Heidi Savage - 2020 - Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 1 (XXXIX):105-134.
    In “Semantics of Fictional Terms,” Garcia-Carpintero critically surveys the most recent literature on the topic of fictional names. One of his targets is realism about fictional discourse. Realists about fictional discourse believe that: (a) it contains true sentences that have fictional names as their subjects; (b) sentences containing names can be true only if those names have referents; (c) fictional names have fictional characters – abstract objects – as their referents. The fundamental problem that arises for realists is that not (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  70
    Strategic vs. Parametric choice in Newcomb’s Problem and the Prisoner’s Dilemma: Reply to Walker.José Luis Bermúdez - 2015 - Philosophia 43 (3):787-794.
    In Bermúdez 2013 I argued against David Lewis’s well-known and widely accepted claim that Newcomb’s problem and the prisoner’s dilemma are really notational variants of a single problem. Mark Walker’s paper in this journal takes issue with my argument. In this note I show how Walker’s criticisms are misplaced. The problems with Walker’s argument point to more general and independently interesting conclusions about, first, the relation between deliberation and decision and, second, the differences between the prisoner’s dilemma, which is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36.  50
    On Equivalence Relations Between Interpreted Languages, with an Application to Modal and First-Order Language.Kai F. Wehmeier - 2021 - Erkenntnis 88 (1):193-213.
    I examine notions of equivalence between logics (understood as languages interpreted model-theoretically) and develop two new ones that invoke not only the algebraic but also the string-theoretic structure of the underlying language. As an application, I show how to construe modal operator languages as what might be called typographical notational variants of _bona fide_ first-order languages.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37. Logical Realism and the Riddle of Redundancy.Óscar Antonio Monroy Pérez - 2023 - Mind 131 (524):1083-1107.
    According to an influential view, when it comes to representing reality, some words are better suited for the job than others. This is elitism. There is reason to believe that the set of the best, or elite, words should not be redundant or arbitrary. However, we are often forced to choose between these two theoretical vices, especially in cases involving theories that seem to be mere notational variants. This is the riddle of redundancy: both redundancy and arbitrariness are vicious, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Derrida’s Differance and Plato’s Different.Samuel C. Wheeler Iii - 1999 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (4):999 - 1013.
    This essay shows that Derrida's discussion of "Differance," is remarkably parallel to Plato's discussion of Difference in the Parmenides. Plato's presentation of "Parmenides'" discussion of generation from a One which Is is a version of Derrida's preconceptual spacing. Derrida's implicit reference to Plato both interprets Plato and explains the obscure features of "Differance." Derrida's paradoxical remarks about Differance are very like what Plato implies about Difference. Derrida's Differance addresses the puzzle that concepts are required to construct the beings in a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39. Indexical Sinn: Fregeanism versus Millianism.João Branquinho - 2014 - Revista de Filosofia Aurora 26 (39):465-486.
    This paper discusses two notational variance views with respect to indexical singular reference and content: the view that certain forms of Millianism are at bottom notational variants of a Fregean theory of reference, the Fregean Notational Variance Claim; and the view that certain forms of Fregeanism are at bottom notational variants of a direct reference theory, the Millian Notational Variance Claim. While the former claim rests on the supposition that a direct reference theory could be (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  27
    Studies on Semantics in Generative Grammar. [REVIEW]L. J. - 1974 - Review of Metaphysics 27 (3):605-606.
    Three long papers are collected here which constitute Chomsky’s major theoretical work on syntax and semantics subsequent to the "standard theory" of Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. Since 1965, transformational-generative linguists have suggested various changes in "standard theory," centering on the relationship between the syntactic and semantic components in natural language grammars. In these papers Chomsky explains several specific problems that require the extension of standard theory and he criticizes the proposals and arguments of the generative semanticists, attempting to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Logic and Ontological Pluralism.Jason Turner - 2012 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 41 (2):419-448.
    Ontological pluralism is the doctrine that there are different ways or modes of being. In contemporary guise, it is the doctrine that a logically perspicuous description of reality will use multiple quantifiers which cannot be thought of as ranging over a single domain. Although thought defeated for some time, recent defenses have shown a number of arguments against the view unsound. However, another worry looms: that despite looking like an attractive alternative, ontological pluralism is really no different than its counterpart, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  42. Parsimony hierarchies for inductive inference.Andris Ambainis, John Case, Sanjay Jain & Mandayam Suraj - 2004 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 69 (1):287-327.
    Freivalds defined an acceptable programming system independent criterion for learning programs for functions in which the final programs were required to be both correct and "nearly" minimal size, i.e., within a computable function of being purely minimal size. Kinber showed that this parsimony requirement on final programs limits learning power. However, in scientific inference, parsimony is considered highly desirable. A lim-computablefunction is (by definition) one calculable by a total procedure allowed to change its mind finitely many times about its output. (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43. On Ramsey's 'Silly Delusion' Regarding Tractatus 5.53.Kai Wehmeier - 2009 - In Giuseppe Primiero (ed.), Acts of Knowledge: History, Philosophy and Logic. College Publications.
    We investigate a variant of the variable convention proposed at Tractatus 5.53ff for the purpose of eliminating the identity sign from logical notation. The variant in question is what Hintikka has called the strongly exclusive interpretation of the variables, and turns out to be what Ramsey initially (and erroneously) took to be Wittgenstein's intended method. We provide a tableau calculus for this identity-free logic, together with soundness and completeness proofs, as well as a proof of mutual interpretability with (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44.  38
    A Walk with Goodstein.David Fernández-Duque & Andreas Weiermann - 2024 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 30 (1):1-19.
    Goodstein’s principle is arguably the first purely number-theoretic statement known to be independent of Peano arithmetic. It involves sequences of natural numbers which at first appear to diverge, but eventually decrease to zero. These sequences are defined relative to a notation system based on exponentiation for the natural numbers. In this article, we provide a self-contained and modern analysis of Goodstein’s principle, obtaining some variations and improvements. We explore notions of optimality for notation systems and apply them to the classical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  82
    The power and the limits of Wittgenstein's N operator.James W. McGray - 2006 - History and Philosophy of Logic 27 (2):143-169.
    The power of Wittgenstein's N operator described in the Tractatus is that every proposition which can be expressed in the Russellian variant of the predicate calculus familiar to him has an equivalent proposition in an extended variant of his N operator notation. This remains true if the bound variables are understood in the usual inclusive sense or in Wittgenstein's restrictive exclusive sense. The problematic limit of Wittgenstein's N operator comes from his claim that symbols alone reveal the logical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  46.  38
    Tarskian consequence relations bilaterally: some familiar notions.Sergey Drobyshevich - 2019 - Synthese 198 (S22):5213-5240.
    This paper is dedicated to developing a formalism that takes rejection seriously. Bilateral notation of signed formulas with force indicators is adopted to define signed consequences which can be viewed as the bilateral counterpart of Tarskian consequence relations. Its relation to some other bilateral approaches is discussed. It is shown how David Nelson’s logic N4 can be characterized bilaterally and the corresponding completeness result is proved. Further, bilateral variants of three familiar notions are considered and investigated: that of a fragment, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  47.  17
    Handbook of Mathematical Induction: Theory and Applications.David S. Gunderson - 2010 - Chapman & Hall/Crc.
    Handbook of Mathematical Induction: Theory and Applications shows how to find and write proofs via mathematical induction. This comprehensive book covers the theory, the structure of the written proof, all standard exercises, and hundreds of application examples from nearly every area of mathematics. In the first part of the book, the author discusses different inductive techniques, including well-ordered sets, basic mathematical induction, strong induction, double induction, infinite descent, downward induction, and several variants. He then introduces ordinals and cardinals, transfinite induction, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48.  50
    Generalizations of the Kruskal-Friedman theorems.L. Gordeev - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (1):157-181.
    Kruskal proved that finite trees are well-quasi-ordered by hom(e)omorphic embeddability. Friedman observed that this statement is not provable in predicative analysis. Friedman also proposed (see in [Simpson]) some stronger variants of the Kruskal theorem dealing with finite labeled trees under home(e)omorphic embeddability with a certain gap-condition, where labels are arbitrary finite ordinals from a fixed initial segment of ω. The corresponding limit statement, expressing that for all initial segments of ω these labeled trees are well-quasi-ordered, is provable in Π 1 (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49.  12
    Formal Logic: Its Scope and Limits.John P. Burgess (ed.) - 2006 - Hackett Publishing Company.
    The first beginning logic text to employ the tree method--a complete formal system of first-order logic that is remarkably easy to understand and use--this text allows students to take control of the nuts and bolts of formal logic quickly, and to move on to more complex and abstract problems. The tree method is elaborated in manageable steps over five chapters, in each of which its adequacy is reviewed; soundness and completeness proofs are extended at each step, and the decidability proof (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50. Complex Predicates.Robert Stalnaker - 1977 - The Monist 60 (3):327-339.
    I am going to describe a variant formulation of classical extensional first-order logic and contrast it with the standard formulation. The formulation I will give is in one clear sense equivalent to the standard one, and it is a routine task to show that it is equivalent to it in this sense. So one might regard my formulation as a mere notational variation. But there are also ways in which the two formulations I will contrast are not equivalent, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
1 — 50 / 965