Results for 'exact formulas'

954 found
Order:
  1.  44
    Extendible Formulas in Two Variables in Intuitionistic Logic.Nick Bezhanishvili & Dick Jongh - 2012 - Studia Logica 100 (1-2):61-89.
    We give alternative characterizations of exact, extendible and projective formulas in intuitionistic propositional calculus IPC in terms of n -universal models. From these characterizations we derive a new syntactic description of all extendible formulas of IPC in two variables. For the formulas in two variables we also give an alternative proof of Ghilardi’s theorem that every extendible formula is projective.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  2.  35
    Stable Formulas in Intuitionistic Logic.Nick Bezhanishvili & Dick de Jongh - 2018 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 59 (3):307-324.
    In 1995 Visser, van Benthem, de Jongh, and Renardel de Lavalette introduced NNIL-formulas, showing that these are exactly the formulas preserved under taking submodels of Kripke models. In this article we show that NNIL-formulas are up to frame equivalence the formulas preserved under taking subframes of frames, that NNIL-formulas are subframe formulas, and that subframe logics can be axiomatized by NNIL-formulas. We also define a new syntactic class of ONNILLI-formulas. We show that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  3.  37
    Extendible Formulas in Two Variables in Intuitionistic Logic.Nick Bezhanishvili & Dick de Jongh - 2012 - Studia Logica 100 (1):61-89.
    We give alternative characterizations of exact, extendible and projective formulas in intuitionistic propositional calculus IPC in terms of n-universal models. From these characterizations we derive a new syntactic description of all extendible formulas of IPC in two variables. For the formulas in two variables we also give an alternative proof of Ghilardi’s theorem that every extendible formula is projective.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  4.  41
    Formulas in modal logic s4.Katsumi Sasaki - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (4):600-627.
    Here, we provide a detailed description of the mutual relation of formulas with finite propositional variables p1, …, pm in modal logic S4. Our description contains more information on S4 than those given in Shehtman (1978) and Moss (2007); however, Shehtman (1978) also treated Grzegorczyk logic and Moss (2007) treated many other normal modal logics. Specifically, we construct normal forms, which behave like the principal conjunctive normal forms in the classical propositional logic. The results include finite and effective methods (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  40
    The exact strength of the class forcing theorem.Victoria Gitman, Joel David Hamkins, Peter Holy, Philipp Schlicht & Kameryn J. Williams - 2020 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 85 (3):869-905.
    The class forcing theorem, which asserts that every class forcing notion ${\mathbb {P}}$ admits a forcing relation $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}$, that is, a relation satisfying the forcing relation recursion—it follows that statements true in the corresponding forcing extensions are forced and forced statements are true—is equivalent over Gödel–Bernays set theory $\text {GBC}$ to the principle of elementary transfinite recursion $\text {ETR}_{\text {Ord}}$ for class recursions of length $\text {Ord}$. It is also equivalent to the existence of truth predicates for the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  6.  15
    Prenex normalization and the hierarchical classification of formulas.Makoto Fujiwara & Taishi Kurahashi - 2023 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 63 (3):391-403.
    Akama et al. [1] introduced a hierarchical classification of first-order formulas for a hierarchical prenex normal form theorem in semi-classical arithmetic. In this paper, we give a justification for the hierarchical classification in a general context of first-order theories. To this end, we first formalize the standard transformation procedure for prenex normalization. Then we show that the classes $$\textrm{E}_k$$ and $$\textrm{U}_k$$ introduced in [1] are exactly the classes induced by $$\Sigma _k$$ and $$\Pi _k$$ respectively via the transformation procedure (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  17
    On the share of closed IL formulas which are also in GL.Vedran Čačić & Vjekoslav Kovač - 2015 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 54 (7-8):741-767.
    Normal forms for wide classes of closed IL formulas were given in Čačić and Vuković. Here we quantify asymptotically, in exact numbers, how wide those classes are. As a consequence, we show that the “majority” of closed IL formulas have GL-equivalents, and by that, they have the same normal forms as GL formulas. Our approach is entirely syntactical, except for applying the results of Čačić and Vuković. As a byproduct we devise a convenient way of computing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  71
    There exist exactly two maximal strictly relevant extensions of the relevant logic R.Kazimierz Swirydowicz - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (3):1125-1154.
    In [60] N. Belnap presented an 8-element matrix for the relevant logic R with the following property: if in an implication A → B the formulas A and B do not have a common variable then there exists a valuation v such that v(A → B) does not belong to the set of designated elements of this matrix. A 6-element matrix of this kind can be found in: R. Routley, R.K. Meyer, V. Plumwood and R.T. Brady [82]. Below we (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  9. A Finite Fragment Of S3.Tomasz Kowalski & John Slaney - 2008 - Reports on Mathematical Logic.
    It is shown that the pure implication fragment of the modal logic [3], pp. 385--387) has finitely many non-equivalent formulae in one variable. The exact number of such formulae is not known. We show that this finiteness result is the best possible, since the analogous fragment of S4, and therefore of [3], in two variables has infinitely many non-equivalent formulae.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  17
    Fundamental theory.Arthur Stanley Eddington & Edmund Taylor Whittaker - 1946 - Cambridge [Eng.]: The University Press. Edited by E. T. Whittaker.
    Fundamental Theory has been called an "unfinished symphony" and "a challenge to the musicians among natural philosophers of the future". This book, written in 1944 but left unfinished because Eddington died too soon, proved to be his final effort at a vision for harmonization of quantum physics and relativity. The work is less connected and internally integrated than 'Protons and Electrons' while representing a later point in the author's thought arc. The really interested student should read both books together.The physical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  11.  19
    Fundamental theory.Arthur Stanley Eddington & Sir Edmund Taylor Whittaker - 1946 - Cambridge [Eng.]: The University Press. Edited by E. T. Whittaker.
    Fundamental Theory has been called an "unfinished symphony" and "a challenge to the musicians among natural philosophers of the future". This book, written in 1944 but left unfinished because Eddington died too soon, proved to be his final effort at a vision for harmonization of quantum physics and relativity. The work is less connected and internally integrated than 'Protons and Electrons' while representing a later point in the author's thought arc. The really interested student should read both books together.The physical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  12. Frege's Judgement Stroke and the Conception of Logic as the Study of Inference not Consequence.Nicholas J. J. Smith - 2009 - Philosophy Compass 4 (4):639-665.
    One of the most striking differences between Frege's Begriffsschrift (logical system) and standard contemporary systems of logic is the inclusion in the former of the judgement stroke: a symbol which marks those propositions which are being asserted , that is, which are being used to express judgements . There has been considerable controversy regarding both the exact purpose of the judgement stroke, and whether a system of logic should include such a symbol. This paper explains the intended role of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  13.  40
    Science as Receptor of Technology: Paul Ehrlich and the Synthetic Dyestuffs Industry.Anthony S. Travis - 1989 - Science in Context 3 (2):383-408.
    The ArgumentIn Germany during the 1870s and 1880s a number of important scientific innovations in chemistry and biology emerged that were linked to advances in the new technology of synthetic dyestuffs. In particular, the rapid development of classical organic chemistry was a consequence of programs in which chemists devised new theories and experimental strategies that were applicable to the processes and products of the burgeoning dye factories. Thereafter, the novel products became the means to examine and measure biological systems. This (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  14.  31
    Gnosis.Marcus Kracht - 2011 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 40 (3):397 - 420.
    The transition from form to meaning is not neatly layered: there is no point where form ends and content sets in. Rather, there is an almost continuous process that converts form into meaning. That process cannot always take a straight line. Very often we hit barriers in our mind, due to the inability to understand the exact content of the sentence just heard. The standard division between formula and interpretation (or value) should therefore be given up when talking about (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15.  19
    The Connection of the Generalized Robinson–Foulds Metric with Partial Wiener Indices.Domagoj Matijević & Damir Vukičević - 2023 - Acta Biotheoretica 71 (1):1-10.
    In this work we propose the partial Wiener index as one possible measure of branching in phylogenetic evolutionary trees. We establish the connection between the generalized Robinson–Foulds (RF) metric for measuring the similarity of phylogenetic trees and partial Wiener indices by expressing the number of conflicting pairs of edges in the generalized RF metric in terms of partial Wiener indices. To do so we compute the minimum and maximum value of the partial Wiener index WT,r,n\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Moorean Phenomena in Epistemic Logic.Wesley H. Holliday & Thomas F. Icard - 2010 - In Lev Dmitrievich Beklemishev, Valentin Goranko & Valentin Shehtman (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic 8. London, England: College Publications. pp. 178-199.
    A well-known open problem in epistemic logic is to give a syntactic characterization of the successful formulas. Semantically, a formula is successful if and only if for any pointed model where it is true, it remains true after deleting all points where the formula was false. The classic example of a formula that is not successful in this sense is the “Moore sentence” p ∧ ¬BOXp, read as “p is true but you do not know p.” Not only is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  17. (1 other version)Proper forcing and remarkable cardinals.Ralf-Dieter Schindler - 2000 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 6 (2):176-184.
    The present paper investigates the power of proper forcings to change the shape of the universe, in a certain well-defined respect. It turns out that the ranking among large cardinals can be used as a measure for that power. However, in order to establish the final result I had to isolate a new large cardinal concept, which I dubbed “remarkability.” Let us approach the exact formulation of the problem—and of its solution—at a slow pace.Breathtaking developments in the mid 1980s (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  18.  55
    Is KΛΕΟΣ ΑΦθΙΤΟΝ a Homeric Formula?Margalit Finkelberg - 1986 - Classical Quarterly 36 (1):1-5.
    Since being brought to light in 1853 by Adalbert Kuhn, the fact that the Homeric expressionκλέος ἄφθιτονhas an exact parallel in the Veda has played an extremely important role in formulating the hypothesis that Greek epic poetry is of Indo-European origin. Yet only with Milman Parry's analysis of the formulaic character of Homeric composition did it become possible to test the antiquity ofκλέος ἄφθιτονon the internal grounds of Homeric diction.It is generally agreed that the conservative character of oral composition (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19.  63
    Nonlinear stochastic integrals for hyperfinite Lévy processes.Tom Lindstrøm - 2008 - Logic and Analysis 1 (2):91-129.
    I develop a notion of nonlinear stochastic integrals for hyperfinite Lévy processes and use it to find exact formulas for expressions which are intuitively of the form $\sum_{s=0}^t\phi(\omega,dl_{s},s)$ and $\prod_{s=0}^t\psi(\omega,dl_{s},s)$ , where l is a Lévy process. These formulas are then applied to geometric Lévy processes, infinitesimal transformations of hyperfinite Lévy processes, and to minimal martingale measures. Some of the central concepts and results are closely related to those found in S. Cohen’s work on stochastic calculus for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  43
    Comparison of the Polar Decision Rules for Various Types of Distributions.Luba Sapir - 2004 - Theory and Decision 56 (3):325-343.
    We focus on the dichotomous choice model, which goes back as far as Condorcet (1785; Essai sur l'application de l'analyse a la probabilité des décisions rendues a la pluralité des voix, Paris). A group of experts is required to select one of two alternatives, of which exactly one is regarded as correct. The alternatives may be related to a wide variety of areas. A decision rule translates the individual opinions of the members into a group decision. A decision rule is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  27
    ΚΛΕΟΣ ΑΦΘITON and Oral Theory.Anthony T. Edwards - 1988 - Classical Quarterly 38 (01):25-.
    In a recent article Margalit Finkelberg raises the question of whether or not the phrase κλοσ π;θιτον at Iliad 9.413 is indeed a Homeric formula: λετο μν μοι νóατοσ, τρ κλοσ π;θιτον σται Her purpose is to ‘test the antiquity of κλοσ π;θιτον on the internal grounds of Homeric diction’ .1 Proposing to use specifically the analytic techniques of oral theory, she argues that this phrase does not represent a survival from an Indo-European heroic poetry, as has been suggested from (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  65
    An Indian solution to 'incompleteness'.U. A. Vinaya Kumar - 2009 - AI and Society 24 (4):351-364.
    Kurt Gödel’s Incompleteness theorem is well known in Mathematics/Logic/Philosophy circles. Gödel was able to find a way for any given P (UTM), (read as, “P of UTM” for “Program of Universal Truth Machine”), actually to write down a complicated polynomial that has a solution iff (=if and only if), G is true, where G stands for a Gödel-sentence. So, if G’s truth is a necessary condition for the truth of a given polynomial, then P (UTM) has to answer first that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  23
    Moorean Phenomena in Epistemic Logic.Wesley H. Holliday & Thomas F. Icard Iii - 1998 - In Marcus Kracht, Maarten de Rijke, Heinrich Wansing & Michael Zakharyaschev (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic. CSLI Publications. pp. 178-199.
    A well-known open problem in epistemic logic is to give a syntactic characterization of the successful formulas. Semantically, a formula is successful if and only if for any pointed model where it is true, it remains true after deleting all points where the formula was false. The classic example of a formula that is not successful in this sense is the “Moore sentence” p ∧ ¬ BOX p, read as “p is true but you do not know p.” Not (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24. Unification in intuitionistic logic.Silvio Ghilardi - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (2):859-880.
    We show that the variety of Heyting algebras has finitary unification type. We also show that the subvariety obtained by adding it De Morgan law is the biggest variety of Heyting algebras having unitary unification type. Proofs make essential use of suitable characterizations (both from the semantic and the syntactic side) of finitely presented projective algebras.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  25.  6
    Moorean Phenomena in Epistemic Logic.Wesley H. Holliday & Thomas F. Icard Iii - 1998 - In Marcus Kracht, Maarten de Rijke, Heinrich Wansing & Michael Zakharyaschev (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic. CSLI Publications. pp. 178-199.
    A well-known open problem in epistemic logic is to give a syntactic characterization of the successful formulas. Semantically, a formula is successful if and only if for any pointed model where it is true, it remains true after deleting all points where the formula was false. The classic example of a formula that is not successful in this sense is the “Moore sentence” p ∧ ¬ BOX p, read as “p is true but you do not know p.” Not (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  22
    Terminal notions in set theory.Jindřich Zapletal - 2001 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 109 (1-2):89-116.
    In mathematical practice certain formulas φ are believed to essentially decide all other natural properties of the object x. The purpose of this paper is to exactly quantify such a belief for four formulas φ, namely “x is a Ramsey ultrafilter”, “x is a free Souslin tree”, “x is an extendible strong Lusin set” and “x is a good diamond sequence”.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  45
    Predicate provability logic with non-modalized quantifiers.Giorgie Dzhaparidze - 1991 - Studia Logica 50 (1):149 - 160.
    Predicate modal formulas with non-modalized quantifiers (call them Q-formulas) are considered as schemata of arithmetical formulas, where is interpreted as the provability predicate of some fixed correct extension T of arithmetic. A method of constructing 1) non-provable in T and 2) false arithmetical examples for Q-formulas by Kripke-like countermodels of certain type is given. Assuming the means of T to be strong enough to solve the (undecidable) problem of derivability in QGL, the Q-fragment of the predicate (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  57
    A Characterization of Lewisian Causal Models.Jiji Zhang - 2023 - In Natasha Alechina, Andreas Herzig & Fei Liang (eds.), Logic, Rationality, and Interaction: 9th International Workshop, LORI 2023, Jinan, China, October 26–29, 2023, Proceedings. Springer Nature Switzerland. pp. 94-108.
    An important component in the interventionist account of causal explanation is an interpretation of counterfactual conditionals as statements about consequences of hypothetical interventions. The interpretation receives a formal treatment in the framework of functional causal models. In Judea Pearl’s influential formulation, functional causal models are assumed to satisfy a “unique-solution” property; this class of Pearlian causal models includes the ones called recursive. Joseph Halpern showed that every recursive causal model is Lewisian, in the sense that from the causal model one (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  53
    (1 other version)Plurivalent Logics.Graham Priest - 2014 - Australasian Journal of Logic 11 (1).
    In this paper, I will describe a technique for generating a novel kind of semantics for a logic, and explore some of its consequences. It would be natural to call the semantics produced by the technique in question ‘many-valued'; but that name is, of course, already taken. I call them, instead, ‘plurivalent'. In standard logical semantics, formulas take exactly one of a bunch of semantic values. I call such semantics ‘univalent'. In a plurivalent semantics, by contrast, formulas may (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  30.  28
    Complementary Proof Nets for Classical Logic.Gabriele Pulcini & Achille C. Varzi - 2023 - Logica Universalis 17 (4):411-432.
    A complementary system for a given logic is a proof system whose theorems are exactly the formulas that are not valid according to the logic in question. This article is a contribution to the complementary proof theory of classical propositional logic. In particular, we present a complementary proof-net system, $$\textsf{CPN}$$ CPN, that is sound and complete with respect to the set of all classically invalid (one-side) sequents. We also show that cut elimination in $$\textsf{CPN}$$ CPN enjoys strong normalization along (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  64
    Is there a logic of confirmation transfer?Peter Milne - 2000 - Erkenntnis 53 (3):309-335.
    This article begins by exploring a lost topic in the philosophy of science:the properties of the relations evidence confirming h confirmsh'' and, more generally, evidence confirming each ofh1, h2, ..., hm confirms at least one of h1, h2,ldots;, hn''.The Bayesian understanding of confirmation as positive evidential relevanceis employed throughout. The resulting formal system is, to say the least, oddlybehaved. Some aspects of this odd behaviour the system has in common withsome of the non-classical logics developed in the twentieth century. Oneaspect (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  32. Tractarian First-Order Logic: Identity and the N-Operator.Brian Rogers & Kai F. Wehmeier - 2012 - Review of Symbolic Logic 5 (4):538-573.
    In theTractatus, Wittgenstein advocates two major notational innovations in logic. First, identity is to be expressed by identity of the sign only, not by a sign for identity. Secondly, only one logical operator, called “N” by Wittgenstein, should be employed in the construction of compound formulas. We show that, despite claims to the contrary in the literature, both of these proposals can be realized, severally and jointly, in expressively complete systems of first-order logic. Building on early work of Hintikka’s, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  33.  36
    Basic Propositional Calculus I.Mohammad Ardeshir & Wim Ruitenburg - 1998 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 44 (3):317-343.
    We present an axiomatization for Basic Propositional Calculus BPC and give a completeness theorem for the class of transitive Kripke structures. We present several refinements, including a completeness theorem for irreflexive trees. The class of intermediate logics includes two maximal nodes, one being Classical Propositional Calculus CPC, the other being E1, a theory axiomatized by T → ⊥. The intersection CPC ∩ E1 is axiomatizable by the Principle of the Excluded Middle A V ∨ ⌝A. If B is a formula (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  34.  23
    A Natural Deduction System for Orthomodular Logic.Andre Kornell - 2024 - Review of Symbolic Logic 17 (3):910-949.
    Orthomodular logic is a weakening of quantum logic in the sense of Birkhoff and von Neumann. Orthomodular logic is shown to be a nonlinear noncommutative logic. Sequents are given a physically motivated semantics that is consistent with exactly one semantics for propositional formulas that use negation, conjunction, and implication. In particular, implication must be interpreted as the Sasaki arrow, which satisfies the deduction theorem in this logic. As an application, this deductive system is extended to two systems of predicate (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  79
    Bi-Simulating in Bi-Intuitionistic Logic.Guillermo Badia - 2016 - Studia Logica 104 (5):1037-1050.
    Bi-intuitionistic logic is the result of adding the dual of intuitionistic implication to intuitionistic logic. In this note, we characterize the expressive power of this logic by showing that the first order formulas equivalent to translations of bi-intuitionistic propositional formulas are exactly those preserved under bi-intuitionistic directed bisimulations. The proof technique is originally due to Lindstrom and, in contrast to the most common proofs of this kind of result, it does not use the machinery of neither saturated models (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  36. The Anger of Achilles: Mēnis in Greek Epic (review).Jenny Strauss Clay - 1997 - American Journal of Philology 118 (4):631-637.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:The Anger of Achilles: Mēnis in Greek EpicJenny Strauss ClayLeonard Muellner. The Anger of Achilles: Mēnis in Greek Epic. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1996. ix + 219 pp. Cloth, $39.95.At the beginning of Greek literature, and hence the whole classical tradition, stands an enigmatic word: mēnis. Usually translated as "wrath" or "anger," mēnis constitutes the subject of the Iliad, but its precise meaning and implications remain elusive. Muellner's (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Semantic analysis of tense logics.S. K. Thomason - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (1):150-158.
    Although we believe the results reported below to have direct philosophical import, we shall for the most part confine our remarks to the realm of mathematics. The reader is referred to [4] for a philosophically oriented discussion, comprehensible to mathematicians, of tense logic.The “minimal” tense logicT0is the system having connectives ∼, →,F(“at some future time”), andP(“at some past time”); the following axioms:(whereGandHabbreviate ∼F∼ and ∼P∼ respectively); and the following rules:(8) fromαandα → β, inferβ,(9) fromα, infer any substitution instance ofα,(10) fromα, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  38.  25
    A resolution calculus for MinSAT.Chu-Min Li, Fan Xiao & Felip Manyà - 2021 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 29 (1):28-44.
    The logical calculus for SAT are not valid for MaxSAT and MinSAT because they preserve satisfiability but not the number of unsatisfied clauses. To overcome this drawback, a MaxSAT resolution rule preserving the number of unsatisfied clauses was defined in the literature. This rule is complete for MaxSAT when it is applied following a certain strategy. In this paper we first prove that the MaxSAT resolution rule also provides a complete calculus for MinSAT if it is applied following the strategy (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  42
    A syntactical approach to modality.Paul Schweizer - 1992 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 21 (1):1 - 31.
    The systems T N and T M show that necessity can be consistently construed as a predicate of syntactical objects, if the expressive/deductive power of the system is deliberately engineered to reflect the power of the original object language operator. The system T N relies on salient limitations on the expressive power of the language L N through the construction of a quotational hierarchy, while the system T Mrelies on limiting the scope of the modal axioms schemas to the sublanguage (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  40.  64
    Paraconsistency in classical logic.Gabriele Pulcini & Achille C. Varzi - 2018 - Synthese 195 (12):5485-5496.
    Classical propositional logic can be characterized, indirectly, by means of a complementary formal system whose theorems are exactly those formulas that are not classical tautologies, i.e., contradictions and truth-functional contingencies. Since a formula is contingent if and only if its negation is also contingent, the system in question is paraconsistent. Hence classical propositional logic itself admits of a paraconsistent characterization, albeit “in the negative”. More generally, any decidable logic with a syntactically incomplete proof theory allows for a paraconsistent characterization (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41.  53
    On the proof-theoretic strength of monotone induction in explicit mathematics.Thomas Glaß, Michael Rathjen & Andreas Schlüter - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 85 (1):1-46.
    We characterize the proof-theoretic strength of systems of explicit mathematics with a general principle asserting the existence of least fixed points for monotone inductive definitions, in terms of certain systems of analysis and set theory. In the case of analysis, these are systems which contain the Σ12-axiom of choice and Π12-comprehension for formulas without set parameters. In the case of set theory, these are systems containing the Kripke-Platek axioms for a recursively inaccessible universe together with the existence of a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  42.  24
    Infinitary generalizations of deligne’s completeness theorem.Christian Espíndola - 2020 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 85 (3):1147-1162.
    Given a regular cardinal $\kappa $ such that $\kappa ^{<\kappa }=\kappa $, we study a class of toposes with enough points, the $\kappa $ -separable toposes. These are equivalent to sheaf toposes over a site with $\kappa $ -small limits that has at most $\kappa $ many objects and morphisms, the topology being generated by at most $\kappa $ many covering families, and that satisfy a further exactness property T. We prove that these toposes have enough $\kappa $ -points, that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  33
    A generalized notion of weak interpretability and the corresponding modal logic.Giorgie Dzhaparidze - 1993 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 61 (1-2):113-160.
    Dzhaparidze, G., A generalized notion of weak interpretability and the corresponding modal logic, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 61 113-160. A tree Tr of theories T1,...,Tn is called tolerant, if there are consistent extensions T+1,...,T+n of T1,...,Tn, where each T+i interprets its successors in the tree Tr. We consider a propositional language with the following modal formation rule: if Tr is a tree of formulas, then Tr is a formula, and axiomatically define in this language the decidable logics (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  44.  8
    Isaac Newton’s ‘Of Quadrature by Ordinates’.Naoki Osada - 2013 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 67 (4):457-476.
    In Of Quadrature by Ordinates (1695), Isaac Newton tried two methods for obtaining the Newton–Cotes formulae. The first method is extrapolation and the second one is the method of undetermined coefficients using the quadrature of monomials. The first method provides \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$n$$\end{document}-ordinate Newton–Cotes formulae only for cases in which \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$n=3,4$$\end{document} and 5. However this method provides another important formulae if the ratios of errors (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  29
    Classification of Weak De Morgan Algebras.Michiro Kondo - 1995 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 36 (3):396-406.
    In this paper we shall first show that for every weak DeMorgan algebra $L$ of order $n$ , there is a quotient weak DeMorgan algebra $L{\sim}$ which is embeddable in the finite WDM-$n$ algebra $\Omega $. We then demonstrate that the finite WDM-$n$ algebra $\Omega $ is functionally free for the class $CL$ of WDM-$n$ algebras. That is, we show that any formulas $f$ and $g$ are identically equal in each algebra in $CL$ if and only if they are (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  49
    Paraconsistency, paracompleteness, Gentzen systems, and trivalent semantics.Arnon Avron - 2014 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 24 (1-2):12-34.
    A quasi-canonical Gentzen-type system is a Gentzen-type system in which each logical rule introduces either a formula of the form , or of the form , and all the active formulas of its premises belong to the set . In this paper we investigate quasi-canonical systems in which exactly one of the two classical rules for negation is included, turning the induced logic into either a paraconsistent logic or a paracomplete logic, but not both. We provide a constructive coherence (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  47. Logic of vague concepts.E. S. Orlowska - 1982 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 11 (3-4):115-126.
    This paper contains a logic enabling us to reason in the presence of vague- ness phenomena. We consider an epistemological vagueness of concepts caused by the unavailability of total information about a continuous world which we describe in observational terms. Lack of information is manifested by the existence of borderline cases for concepts. Since we are unable to perceive concepts exactly, we cannot establish a sharp boundary between an extension of a concept and its complement. Some results for reasoning about (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  57
    A More Unified Approach to Free Logics.Edi Pavlović & Norbert Gratzl - 2020 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 50 (1):117-148.
    Free logics is a family of first-order logics which came about as a result of examining the existence assumptions of classical logic. What those assumptions are varies, but the central ones are that the domain of interpretation is not empty, every name denotes exactly one object in the domain and the quantifiers have existential import. Free logics usually reject the claim that names need to denote in, and of the systems considered in this paper, the positive free logic concedes that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  49.  87
    The bounded proper forcing axiom.Martin Goldstern & Saharon Shelah - 1995 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 60 (1):58-73.
    The bounded proper forcing axiom BPFA is the statement that for any family of ℵ 1 many maximal antichains of a proper forcing notion, each of size ℵ 1 , there is a directed set meeting all these antichains. A regular cardinal κ is called Σ 1 -reflecting, if for any regular cardinal χ, for all formulas $\varphi, "H(\chi) \models`\varphi'"$ implies " $\exists\delta . We investigate several algebraic consequences of BPFA, and we show that the consistency strength of the (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  50.  65
    (1 other version)Identical Twins, Deduction Theorems, and Pattern Functions: Exploring the Implicative BCSK Fragment of S5.Lloyd Humberstone - 2006 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 35 (5):435-487.
    We recapitulate (Section 1) some basic details of the system of implicative BCSK logic, which has two primitive binary implicational connectives, and which can be viewed as a certain fragment of the modal logic S5. From this modal perspective we review (Section 2) some results according to which the pure sublogic in either of these connectives (i.e., each considered without the other) is an exact replica of the material implication fragment of classical propositional logic. In Sections 3 and 5 (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
1 — 50 / 954