Results for 'cardinal functions'

972 found
Order:
  1.  40
    Cardinal functions on ultra products of Boolean algebras.Douglas Peterson - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (1):43-59.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2. Applications of large cardinals to borel functions.Harvey Friedman - manuscript
    The space CS(R) has a unique “Borel structure” in the following sense. Note that there is a natural mapping from R¥ onto CS(R}; namely, taking ranges. We can combine this with any Borel bijection from R onto R¥ in order to get a “preferred” surjection F:R ® CS(R).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  31
    Consecutive Singular Cardinals and the Continuum Function.Arthur W. Apter & Brent Cody - 2013 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 54 (2):125-136.
    We show that from a supercompact cardinal $\kappa$, there is a forcing extension $V[G]$ that has a symmetric inner model $N$ in which $\mathrm {ZF}+\lnot\mathrm {AC}$ holds, $\kappa$ and $\kappa^{+}$ are both singular, and the continuum function at $\kappa$ can be precisely controlled, in the sense that the final model contains a sequence of distinct subsets of $\kappa$ of length equal to any predetermined ordinal. We also show that the above situation can be collapsed to obtain a model of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4. Geometric cardinal invariants, maximal functions and a measure theoretic pigeonhole principle.Juris Steprāns - 2005 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (4):517-525.
    It is shown to be consistent with set theory that every set of reals of size ℵ1 is null yet there are ℵ1 planes in Euclidean 3-space whose union is not null. Similar results will be obtained for other geometric objects. The proof relies on results from harmonic analysis about the boundedness of certain harmonic functions and a measure theoretic pigeonhole principle.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  21
    Strongly compact cardinals and the continuum function.Arthur W. Apter, Stamatis Dimopoulos & Toshimichi Usuba - 2021 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 172 (9):103013.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  57
    Characterization and Cardinality of Universal Functions.Karl S. Menger - 1971 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 36 (3):548-549.
  7.  19
    Questions on cardinal invariants of Boolean algebras.Mario Jardón Santos - 2023 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 62 (7):947-963.
    In the book Cardinal Invariants on Boolean Algebras by J. Donald Monk many such cardinal functions are defined and studied. Among them several are generalizations of well known cardinal characteristics of the continuum. Alongside a long list of open problems is given. Focusing on half a dozen of those cardinal invariants some of those problems are given an answer here, which in most of the cases is a definitive one. Most of them can be divided (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  3
    Separating Many Localisation Cardinals on the Generalised Baire Space.Tristan van der Vlugt - 2024 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 89 (3):1212-1231.
    Given a cofinal cardinal function $h\in {}^{\kappa }\kappa $ for $\kappa $ inaccessible, we consider the dominating h-localisation number, that is, the least cardinality of a dominating set of h-slaloms such that every $\kappa $ -real is localised by a slalom in the dominating set. It was proved in [3] that the dominating localisation numbers can be consistently different for two functions h (the identity function and the power function). We will construct a $\kappa ^+$ -sized family of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  17
    Complex Cardinal Numerals and the Strong Minimalist Thesis.Anna Maria Di Sciullo - 2022 - Philosophies 7 (4):81.
    Different analyses of complex cardinal numerals have been proposed in Generative Grammar. This article provides an analysis of these expressions based on the Strong Minimalist Thesis, according to which the derivations of linguistic expressions are generated by a simple combinatorial operation, applying in accord with principles external to the language faculty. The proposed derivations account for the asymmetrical structure of additive and multiplicative complexes and for the instructions they provide to the external systems for their interpretation. They harmonize with (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  41
    (1 other version)Higher dimensional cardinal characteristics for sets of functions.Corey Bacal Switzer - 2022 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 173 (1):103031.
  11.  35
    On two topological cardinal invariants of an order-theoretic flavour.Santi Spadaro - 2012 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 163 (12):1865-1871.
    Noetherian type and Noetherian π-type are two cardinal functions which were introduced by Peregudov in 1997, capturing some properties studied earlier by the Russian School. Their behavior has been shown to be akin to that of the cellularity, that is the supremum of the sizes of pairwise disjoint non-empty open sets in a topological space. Building on that analogy, we study the Noetherian π-type of κ-Suslin Lines, and we are able to determine it for every κ up to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  18
    The Cardinal Principles of the National Entity of Japan: A Rhetoric of Ideological Pronouncement.Takeshi Suzuki - 2001 - Argumentation 15 (3):251-266.
    One manifestation of argumentation is in critical discussions where people genuinely strive cooperatively to achieve critical decisions. Hence, argumentation can be recognized as the process of advancing, supporting, modifying, and criticizing claims so that appropriate decision makers may grant or deny adherence. This audience-centered definition holds the assumption that the participants must willingly engage in public debate and discussion, and their arguments must function to open a critical space and keep it open. This essay investigates `ideological pronouncement,' a kind of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  45
    Remarks on continuum cardinals on Boolean algebras.J. Donald Monk - 2012 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 58 (3):159-167.
    We give some results concerning various generalized continuum cardinals. The results answer some natural questions which have arisen in preparing a new edition of 5. To make the paper self-contained we define all of the cardinal functions that enter into the theorems here. There are many problems concerning these new functions, and we formulate some of the more important ones.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14. Singular cardinals and the pcf theory.Thomas Jech - 1995 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 1 (4):408-424.
    §1. Introduction. Among the most remarkable discoveries in set theory in the last quarter century is the rich structure of the arithmetic of singular cardinals, and its deep relationship to large cardinals. The problem of finding a complete set of rules describing the behavior of the continuum function 2ℵα for singular ℵα's, known as the Singular Cardinals Problem, has been attacked by many different techniques, involving forcing, large cardinals, inner models, and various combinatorial methods. The work on the singular cardinals (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  15.  30
    Large cardinals and iteration trees of height ω.Alessandro Andretta - 1991 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 54 (1):1-15.
    In this paper we continue the line of work initiated in “Building iteration trees”. It is shown that the existence of a certain kind of iteration tree of height ω is equivalent to the existence of a cardinal δ that is Woodin with respect to functions in the next admissible.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16. Decomposing baire functions.J. Cichoń, M. Morayne, J. Pawlikowski & S. Solecki - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (4):1273 - 1283.
    We discuss in the paper the following problem: Given a function in a given Baire class, into "how many" (in terms of cardinal numbers) functions of lower classes can it be decomposed? The decomposition is understood here in the sense of the set-theoretical union.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  17. Unfoldable cardinals and the GCH.Joel Hamkins - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (3):1186-1198.
    Unfoldable cardinals are preserved by fast function forcing and the Laver-like preparations that fast functions support. These iterations show, by set-forcing over any model of ZFC, that any given unfoldable cardinal κ can be made indestructible by the forcing to add any number of Cohen subsets to κ.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  18.  6
    No Decreasing Sequence of Cardinals in the Hierarchy of Choice Principles.Eleftherios Tachtsis - 2024 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 65 (3):311-331.
    In set theory without the axiom of choice (AC), we study the relative strength of the principle “No decreasing sequence of cardinals,” that is, “There is no function f on ω such that |f(n+1)|<|f(n)| for all n∈ω” (NDS) with regard to its position in the hierarchy of weak choice principles. We establish the following results: (1) The Boolean prime ideal theorem plus countable choice does not imply NDS in ZF; (2) “Every non-well-orderable set has a well-orderable partition into denumerable sets” (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  56
    Easton’s theorem in the presence of Woodin cardinals.Brent Cody - 2013 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 52 (5-6):569-591.
    Under the assumption that δ is a Woodin cardinal and GCH holds, I show that if F is any class function from the regular cardinals to the cardinals such that (1) ${\kappa < {\rm cf}(F(\kappa))}$ , (2) ${\kappa < \lambda}$ implies ${F(\kappa) \leq F(\lambda)}$ , and (3) δ is closed under F, then there is a cofinality-preserving forcing extension in which 2 γ = F(γ) for each regular cardinal γ < δ, and in which δ remains Woodin. Unlike (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  20.  40
    Some Problems in Singular Cardinals Combinatorics.Matthew Foreman - 2005 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 46 (3):309-322.
    This paper attempts to present and organize several problems in the theory of Singular Cardinals. The most famous problems in the area (bounds for the ℶ-function at singular cardinals) are well known to all mathematicians with even a rudimentary interest in set theory. However, it is less well known that the combinatorics of singular cardinals is a thriving area with results and problems that do not depend on a solution of the Singular Cardinals Hypothesis. We present here an annotated collection (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  21.  28
    The large cardinals between supercompact and almost-huge.Norman Lewis Perlmutter - 2015 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 54 (3-4):257-289.
    I analyze the hierarchy of large cardinals between a supercompact cardinal and an almost-huge cardinal. Many of these cardinals are defined by modifying the definition of a high-jump cardinal. A high-jump cardinal is defined as the critical point of an elementary embedding j:V→M\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${j: V \to M}$$\end{document} such that M is closed under sequences of length sup{j|f:κ→κ}\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\sup\{{j\,|\,f: \kappa \to \kappa}\}}$$\end{document}. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  22.  36
    Muchnik Degrees and Cardinal Characteristics.Benoit Monin & André Nies - 2021 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 86 (2):471-498.
    A mass problem is a set of functions$\omega \to \omega $. For mass problems${\mathcal {C}}, {\mathcal {D}}$, one says that${\mathcal {C}}$is Muchnik reducible to${\mathcal {D}}$if each function in${\mathcal {C}}$is computed by a function in${\mathcal {D}}$. In this paper we study some highness properties of Turing oracles, which we view as mass problems. We compare them with respect to Muchnik reducibility and its uniform strengthening, Medvedev reducibility.For$p \in [0,1]$let${\mathcal {D}}(p)$be the mass problem of infinite bit sequencesy(i.e.,$\{0,1\}$-valued functions) such that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Choice-Based Cardinal Utility. A Tribute to Patrick Suppes.Jean Baccelli & Philippe Mongin - 2016 - Journal of Economic Methodology 23 (3):268-288.
    We reexamine some of the classic problems connected with the use of cardinal utility functions in decision theory, and discuss Patrick Suppes's contributions to this field in light of a reinterpretation we propose for these problems. We analytically decompose the doctrine of ordinalism, which only accepts ordinal utility functions, and distinguish between several doctrines of cardinalism, depending on what components of ordinalism they specifically reject. We identify Suppes's doctrine with the major deviation from ordinalism that conceives of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24.  35
    The cardinal coefficients of the Ideal $${{\mathcal {I}}_{f}}$$.Noboru Osuga & Shizuo Kamo - 2008 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 47 (7-8):653-671.
    In 2002, Yorioka introduced the σ-ideal ${{\mathcal {I}}_f}$ for strictly increasing functions f from ω into ω to analyze the cofinality of the strong measure zero ideal. For each f, we study the cardinal coefficients (the additivity, covering number, uniformity and cofinality) of ${{\mathcal {I}}_f}$.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25.  52
    Indestructibility properties of remarkable cardinals.Yong Cheng & Victoria Gitman - 2015 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 54 (7-8):961-984.
    Remarkable cardinals were introduced by Schindler, who showed that the existence of a remarkable cardinal is equiconsistent with the assertion that the theory of L\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${L}$$\end{document} is absolute for proper forcing :176–184, 2000). Here, we study the indestructibility properties of remarkable cardinals. We show that if κ is remarkable, then there is a forcing extension in which the remarkability of κ becomes indestructible by all <κ-closed ≤κ-distributive forcing and all two-step iterations (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  44
    Cardinal Invariants and the Collapse of the Continuum by Sacks Forcing.Miroslav Repický - 2008 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 73 (2):711 - 727.
    We study cardinal invariants of systems of meager hereditary families of subsets of ω connected with the collapse of the continuum by Sacks forcing S and we obtain a cardinal invariant yω such that S collapses the continuum to yω and y ≤ yω ≤ b. Applying the Baumgartner-Dordal theorem on preservation of eventually narrow sequences we obtain the consistency of y = yω < b. We define two relations $\leq _{0}^{\ast}$ and $\leq _{1}^{\ast}$ on the set $(^{\omega}\omega)_{{\rm (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  40
    An integrated axiomatic approach to the existence of ordinal and cardinal utility functions.Robert Jarrow - 1987 - Theory and Decision 22 (2):99-110.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  44
    The least weakly compact cardinal can be unfoldable, weakly measurable and nearly $${\theta}$$ θ -supercompact.Brent Cody, Moti Gitik, Joel David Hamkins & Jason A. Schanker - 2015 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 54 (5-6):491-510.
    We prove from suitable large cardinal hypotheses that the least weakly compact cardinal can be unfoldable, weakly measurable and even nearly θ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\theta}$$\end{document}-supercompact, for any desired θ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\theta}$$\end{document}. In addition, we prove several global results showing how the entire class of weakly compactcardinals, a proper class, can be made to coincide with the class of unfoldable cardinals, with the class of weakly measurable (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29.  18
    On constructions with 2-cardinals.Piotr Koszmider - 2017 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 56 (7-8):849-876.
    We propose developing the theory of consequences of morasses relevant in mathematical applications in the language alternative to the usual one, replacing commonly used structures by families of sets originating with Velleman’s neat simplified morasses called 2-cardinals. The theory of related trees, gaps, colorings of pairs and forcing notions is reformulated and sketched from a unifying point of view with the focus on the applicability to constructions of mathematical structures like Boolean algebras, Banach spaces or compact spaces. The paper is (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30. Frege’s Cardinals as Concept-correlates.Gregory Landini - 2006 - Erkenntnis 65 (2):207-243.
    In his "Grundgesetze", Frege hints that prior to his theory that cardinal numbers are objects he had an "almost completed" manuscript on cardinals. Taking this early theory to have been an account of cardinals as second-level functions, this paper works out the significance of the fact that Frege's cardinal numbers is a theory of concept-correlates. Frege held that, where n > 2, there is a one—one correlation between each n-level function and an n—1 level function, and a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31.  28
    Removing Laver functions from supercompactness arguments.Arthur W. Apter - 2005 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 51 (2):154.
    We show how the use of a Laver function in the proof of the consistency, relative to the existence of a supercompact cardinal, of both the Proper Forcing Axiom and the Semiproper Forcing Axiom can be eliminated via the use of lottery sums of the appropriate partial orderings.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  32.  44
    Calculus on strong partition cardinals.James M. Henle - 2006 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 52 (6):585-594.
    In [1] it was shown that if κ is a strong partition cardinal, then every function from [κ ]κ to [κ ]κ is continuous almost everywhere. In this investigation, we explore whether such functions are differentiable or integrable in any sense. Some of them are.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  25
    Power function on stationary classes.Moti Gitik & Carmi Merimovich - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 140 (1):75-103.
    We show that under certain large cardinal requirements there is a generic extension in which the power function behaves differently on different stationary classes. We achieve this by doing an Easton support iteration of the Radin on extenders forcing.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  91
    Greatly Erdős cardinals with some generalizations to the Chang and Ramsey properties.I. Sharpe & P. D. Welch - 2011 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (11):863-902.
    • We define a notion of order of indiscernibility type of a structure by analogy with Mitchell order on measures; we use this to define a hierarchy of strong axioms of infinity defined through normal filters, the α-weakly Erdős hierarchy. The filters in this hierarchy can be seen to be generated by sets of ordinals where these indiscernibility orders on structures dominate the canonical functions.• The limit axiom of this is that of greatly Erdős and we use it to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  35.  49
    Patterns of compact cardinals.Arthur W. Apter - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 89 (2-3):101-115.
    We show relative to strong hypotheses that patterns of compact cardinals in the universe, where a compact cardinal is one which is either strongly compact or supercompact, can be virtually arbitrary. Specifically, we prove if V “ZFC + Ω is the least inaccessible limit of measurable limits of supercompact cardinals + ƒ : Ω → 2 is a function”, then there is a partial ordering P V so that for , There is a proper class of compact cardinals + (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  36.  47
    Collapsing functions.Ernest Schimmerling & Boban Velickovic - 2004 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 50 (1):3-8.
    We define what it means for a function on ω1 to be a collapsing function for λ and show that if there exists a collapsing function for +, then there is no precipitous ideal on ω1. We show that a collapsing function for ω2 can be added by forcing. We define what it means to be a weakly ω1-Erdös cardinal and show that in L[E], there is a collapsing function for λ iff λ is less than the least weakly (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  37.  26
    Karl S. Menger. Characterization and cardinality of universal functions. IEEE transactions on electronic computers, vol. EC-14 , pp. 720–721. [REVIEW]Edgar N. Gilbert - 1971 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 36 (3):548-549.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  22
    Coding with canonical functions.Paul B. Larson & Saharon Shelah - 2017 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 63 (5):334-341.
    A function f from ω1 to the ordinals is called a canonical function for an ordinal α if f represents α in any generic ultrapower induced by forcing with math formula. We introduce here a method for coding sets of ordinals using canonical functions from ω1 to ω1. Combining this approach with arguments from, we show, assuming the Continuum Hypothesis, that for each cardinal κ there is a forcing construction preserving cardinalities and cofinalities forcing that every subset of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  39
    Ordinal Or Cardinal Utility: A Note.Robert Wutscher & Walter E. Block - 2014 - Studia Humana 3 (1):27-37.
    Modern microeconomic theory is based on a foundation of ordinal preference relations. Good textbooks stress that cardinal utility functions are artificial constructions of convenience, and that economics does not attribute any meaning to “utils.” However, we argue that despite this official position, in practice mainstream economists rely on techniques that assume the validity of cardinal utility. Doing so has turned mainstream economic theorizing into an exercise of reductionism of objects down to the preferences of ‘ideal type’ subjects.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  22
    Factorials of infinite cardinals in zf part I: Zf results.Guozhen Shen & Jiachen Yuan - 2020 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 85 (1):224-243.
    For a set x, let ${\cal S}\left$ be the set of all permutations of x. We prove in ZF several results concerning this notion, among which are the following: For all sets x such that ${\cal S}\left$ is Dedekind infinite, $\left| {{{\cal S}_{{\rm{fin}}}}\left} \right| < \left| {{\cal S}\left} \right|$ and there are no finite-to-one functions from ${\cal S}\left$ into ${{\cal S}_{{\rm{fin}}}}\left$, where ${{\cal S}_{{\rm{fin}}}}\left$ denotes the set of all permutations of x which move only finitely many elements. For all (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  41.  26
    More definable combinatorics around the first and second uncountable cardinals.William Chan, Stephen Jackson & Nam Trang - 2023 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 23 (3).
    Assume [Formula: see text]. If [Formula: see text] is an ordinal and X is a set of ordinals, then [Formula: see text] is the collection of order-preserving functions [Formula: see text] which have uniform cofinality [Formula: see text] and discontinuous everywhere. The weak partition properties on [Formula: see text] and [Formula: see text] yield partition measures on [Formula: see text] when [Formula: see text] and [Formula: see text] when [Formula: see text]. The following almost everywhere continuity properties for (...) on partition spaces with respect to these partition measures will be shown. For every [Formula: see text] and function [Formula: see text], there is a club [Formula: see text] and a [Formula: see text] so that for all [Formula: see text], if [Formula: see text] and [Formula: see text], then [Formula: see text]. For every [Formula: see text] and function [Formula: see text], there is an [Formula: see text]-club [Formula: see text] and a [Formula: see text] so that for all [Formula: see text], if [Formula: see text] and [Formula: see text], then [Formula: see text]. The previous two continuity results will be used to distinguish the cardinalities of some important subsets of [Formula: see text]. [Formula: see text]. [Formula: see text]. [Formula: see text]. It will also be shown that [Formula: see text] has the Jónsson property: For every [Formula: see text], there is an [Formula: see text] with [Formula: see text] so that [Formula: see text]. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Some Remarks on Normal Measures and Measurable Cardinals.Arthur W. Apter - 2001 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 47 (1):35-44.
    We prove two theorems which in a certain sense show that the number of normal measures a measurable cardinal κ can carry is independent of a given fixed behavior of the continuum function on any set having measure 1 with respect to every normal measure over κ . First, starting with a model V ⊨ “ZFC + GCH + o = δ*” for δ* ≤ κ+ any finite or infinite cardinal, we force and construct an inner model N (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  27
    Chain conditions of products, and weakly compact cardinals.Assaf Rinot - 2014 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 20 (3):293-314,.
    The history of productivity of the κ-chain condition in partial orders, topological spaces, or Boolean algebras is surveyed, and its connection to the set-theoretic notion of a weakly compact cardinal is highlighted. Then, it is proved that for every regular cardinal κ > א1, the principle □ is equivalent to the existence of a certain strong coloring c : [κ]2 → κ for which the family of fibers T is a nonspecial κ-Aronszajn tree. The theorem follows from an (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  44. Applications of Large Cardinals to Graph Theory.Harvey M. Friedman - unknown
    Since then we have been engaged in the development of such results of greater relevance to mathematical practice. In January, 1997 we presented some new results of this kind involving what we call “jump free” classes of finite functions. This Jump Free Theorem is treated in section 2.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  21
    A weird relation between two cardinals.Lorenz Halbeisen - 2018 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 57 (5-6):593-599.
    For a set M, let \\) denote the set of all finite sequences which can be formed with elements of M, and let \ denote the set of all 2-element subsets of M. Furthermore, for a set A, let Open image in new window denote the cardinality of A. It will be shown that the following statement is consistent with Zermelo–Fraenkel Set Theory \: There exists a set M such that Open image in new window and no function Open image (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46.  43
    Superatomic Boolean algebras constructed from strongly unbounded functions.Juan Carlos Martínez & Lajos Soukup - 2011 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 57 (5):456-469.
    Using Koszmider's strongly unbounded functions, we show the following consistency result: Suppose that κ, λ are infinite cardinals such that κ++ + ≤ λ, κ<κ = κ and 2κ = κ+, and η is an ordinal with κ+ ≤ η < κ++ and cf = κ+. Then, in some cardinal-preserving generic extension there is a superatomic Boolean algebra equation image such that equation image, equation image for every α < η and equation image. Especially, equation image and equation (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  62
    The Idea of an Exact Number: Children's Understanding of Cardinality and Equinumerosity.Barbara W. Sarnecka & Charles E. Wright - 2013 - Cognitive Science 37 (8):1493-1506.
    Understanding what numbers are means knowing several things. It means knowing how counting relates to numbers (called the cardinal principle or cardinality); it means knowing that each number is generated by adding one to the previous number (called the successor function or succession), and it means knowing that all and only sets whose members can be placed in one-to-one correspondence have the same number of items (called exact equality or equinumerosity). A previous study (Sarnecka & Carey, 2008) linked children's (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  48.  43
    No decreasing sequence of cardinals.Paul Howard & Eleftherios Tachtsis - 2016 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 55 (3-4):415-429.
    In set theory without the Axiom of Choice, we investigate the set-theoretic strength of the principle NDS which states that there is no function f on the set ω of natural numbers such that for everyn ∈ ω, f ≺ f, where for sets x and y, x ≺ y means that there is a one-to-one map g : x → y, but no one-to-one map h : y → x. It is a long standing open problem whether NDS implies (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49.  68
    Reviving a Cardinal Value.Carmen Cozma - 2010 - Cultura 7 (1):139-149.
    In the context of today.s moral and ecological crisis, and the accelerated advance of information and communication technologies, when human beings intensively experience their own fragility, a major question is that of well-being. That raises the issue of moral health, which represents, in an axiological and normative sense, a basis for the human being to find proper opportunities for remaking and protecting the beingness' equilibrium in face of a variety of risks in a society of excesses. We consider that a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  69
    (1 other version)A very discontinuous borel function.Juris Steprāns - 1993 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 58 (4):1268 - 1283.
    It is shown to be consistent that the reals are covered by ℵ1 meagre sets yet there is a Baire class 1 function which cannot be covered by fewer than ℵ2 continuous functions. A new cardinal invariant is introduced which corresponds to the least number of continuous functions required to cover a given function. This is characterized combinatorially. A forcing notion similar to, but not equivalent to, superperfect forcing is introduced.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 972