Results for 'Personal obligation'

983 found
Order:
  1. The Irreducibility of Personal Obligation.Jacob Ross - 2010 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 39 (3):307 - 323.
    It is argued that claims about personal obligation (of the form "s ought to 0") cannot be reduced to claims about impersonal obligation (of the form "it ought to be the case that p"). The most common attempts at such a reduction are shown to have unacceptable implications in cases involving a plurality of agents. It is then argued that similar problems will face any attempt to reduce personal obligation to impersonal obligation.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  2. The Person, Obligation, and Value.Peter A. Bertocci - 1959 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 40 (2):141.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  48
    Caring Work, Personal Obligation and Collective Responsibility.Chris Provis & Sue Stack - 2004 - Nursing Ethics 11 (1):5-14.
    Studies of workers in health care and the care of older people disclose tensions that emerge partly from their conflicting obligations. They incur some obligations from the personal relationships they have with clients, but these can be at odds with organizational demands and resource constraints. One implication is the need for policies to recognize the importance of allowing workers some discretion in decison making. Another implication may be that sometimes care workers can meet their obligations to clients only by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  4. Agential Obligation as Non-Agential Personal Obligation plus Agency.Paul McNamara - 2004 - Journal of Applied Logic 2 (1):117-152.
    I explore various ways of integrating the framework for predeterminism, agency, and ability in[P.McNamara, Nordic J. Philos. Logic 5 (2)(2000) 135] with a framework for obligations. However,the agential obligation operator explored here is defined in terms of a non-agential yet personal obligation operator and a non-deontic (and non-normal) agency operator. This is contrary to the main current trend, which assumes statements of personal obligation always take agential complements. Instead, I take the basic form to be (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  5. You Can't Choose Your Family: Impartial Morality and Personal Obligations in Alias.Brendan Shea - 2014 - In Patricia Brace & Robert Arp (eds.), The Philosophy of J. J. Abrams. The University Press of Kentucky. pp. 173-189.
    In this essay, I critically examine the ways in which the characters of Alias attempt to balance their impartial moral obligations (e.g. duties toward humanity) and their personal obligations (e.g. duties toward one's children). I specifically examine three areas of conflict: (1) choices between saving loved ones and maximizing consequences, (2) choices to maintain or sever relationships with characters who are vicious or immoral, and (3) choices to seek or not seek revenge on the behalf of loved ones. I (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Personal Bonds: Directed Obligations without Rights.Adrienne M. Martin - 2021 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 102 (1):65-86.
    I argue for adopting a conception of obligation that is broader than the conception commonly adopted by moral philosophers. According to this broader conception, the crucial marks of an obligatory action are, first, that the reasons for the obliged party to perform the action include an exclusionary reason and, second, that the obliged party is the appropriate target of blaming reactive attitudes, if they inexcusably fail to perform the obligatory action. An obligation is directed if the exclusionary reason (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  7. Moral Obligation: Relational or Second-Personal?Janis David Schaab - 2023 - Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 9 (48).
    The Problem of Obligation is the problem of how to explain the features of moral obligations that distinguish them from other normative phenomena. Two recent accounts, the Second-Personal Account and the Relational Account, propose superficially similar solutions to this problem. Both regard obligations as based on the claims or legitimate demands that persons as such have on one another. However, unlike the Second-Personal Account, the Relational Account does not regard these claims as based in persons’ authority to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8. Second‐Personal Approaches to Moral Obligation.Janis David Schaab - 2023 - Philosophy Compass 18 (3):1 - 11.
    According to second‐personal approaches to moral obligation, the distinctive normative features of moral obligation can only be explained in terms of second‐personal relations, i.e. the distinctive way persons relate to each other as persons. But there are important disagreements between different groups of second‐personal approaches. Most notably, they disagree about the nature of second‐personal relations, which has consequences for the nature of the obligations that they purport to explain. This article aims to distinguish these (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  61
    Bipolar Obligations, Recognition Respect, and Second-Personal Morality.Jonas Vandieken - 2019 - The Journal of Ethics 23 (3):291-315.
    Any complete theory of “what we owe to each other” must be able to adequately accommodate directed or bipolar obligations, that is, those obligations that are owed to a particular individual and in virtue of which another individual stands to be wronged. Bipolar obligations receive their moral importance from their intimate connection to a particular form of recognition respect that we owe to each other: respect of another as a source of valid claims to whom in particular we owe certain (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  10.  61
    Person and Obligation.John F. Crosby - 2005 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 79 (1):91-119.
    In the course of his polemic against Kant’s moral philosophy, Scheler was led to depreciate moral obligation and its place in the existence of persons. This depreciation is part of a larger anti-authoritarian strain in his personalism. I attempt to retrieve certain truths about moral obligation that tend to get lost in Scheler: moral obligation is not merely “medicinal” but has a place at the highest levels of moral life; the freedom of persons is lived in an (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  50
    Second-Personal Reasons and Special Obligations.Jörg Https://Orcidorg Löschke - 2014 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 14 (3):293-308.
    The paper discusses the second-personal account of moral obligation as put forward by Stephen Darwall. It argues that on such an account, an important part of our moral practice cannot be explained, namely special obligations that are grounded in special relationships between persons. After highlighting the problem, the paper discusses several strategies to accommodate such special obligations that are implicit in some of Darwall’s texts, most importantly a disentanglement strategy and a reductionist strategy. It argues that neither one (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  65
    Second-Personal Reasons and Moral Obligations.Wenwen Fan - 2014 - Journal of Value Inquiry 48 (1):69-86.
    Stephan Darwall (2006, 2010) claims that a conceptual connection exists between moral obligation and what he calls ‘second-personal reasons.’ In particular, he (2006) claims that, “moral obligation is an irreducibly second-personal concept. That an action would violate a moral obligation is…a second-personal reason not to do it.” A second-personal reason, according to him (2006), is “a distinctive kind of (normative) reason for acting,” a reason made on one’s will and purportedly given by an (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  13. Personal and impersonal obligation.Jacob Ross - unknown
    How are claims about what people ought to do related to claims about what ought to be the case? That is, how are claims about of personal obligation, of the form s ought to ?, related to claims about impersonal obligation, of the form it ought to be the case that p? Many philosophers have held that the former type of claim can be reduced to the latter. In particular, they have held a view known as the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14.  46
    Personal consent and moral obligation.Edward Walter - 1981 - Journal of Value Inquiry 15 (1):19-33.
    Contemporary philosophy distinguishes two kinds of rationality: minimal rationality (mnr), Which makes us aware of concepts and their implications, And maximal rationality (mxr), Which introduces normative principles to develop an internally consistent way of life. Contemporary philosophers generally adhere to mnr. I contend that john rawls' use of the social contract mechanism in "a theory of justice" is an attempt to uphold mnr. However, When his theory runs into difficulty, He utilizes mxr. At no point, Does he justify the shift.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Persons as obligated: A values-realizing psychology in light of Bakhtin, Macmurray, and Levinas.B. Hodges - 2006 - In Paul C. Vitz & Susan M. Felch (eds.), The self: beyond the postmodern crisis. Wilmington, De.: ISI Books. pp. 63--82.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Obligation Without Rule: Bartleby, Agamben, and the Second-Person Standpoint.Bryan Lueck - 2018 - Comparative and Continental Philosophy (2):1-13.
    In Herman Melville’s Bartleby, the Scrivener, the narrator finds himself involved in a moral relation with the title character whose sense he finds difficult to articulate. I argue that we can make sense of this relation, up to a certain point, in terms of the influential account of obligation that Stephen Darwall advances in The Second-Person Standpoint. But I also argue that there is a dimension of moral sense in the relation that is not captured by Darwall’s account, or (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Close Personal Relationships with People and Artifacts? Loneliness, Agent-Relative Obligations, and Artificially Intelligent Companions.John Symons & Oluwaseun Damilola Sanwoolu - 2025 - Philosophy and Technology 38 (1):1-20.
    This paper explores the limitations of artificial intelligence (AI) in fulfilling the obligations inherent in close personal relationships, particularly in the context of loneliness. While AI technologies may offer some of the goods that we associate with close personal relationships, they lack the capacity for genuine commitment and individualized care that characterize human interactions. The finitude of human existence—our cognitive, emotional, and temporal limitations— and our capacity to make judgments concerning distinct kinds of value imbues human relationships with (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  25
    Practising the ethics of person‐centred care balancing ethical conviction and moral obligations.Inger Ekman - 2022 - Nursing Philosophy 23 (3):e12382.
    Person‐centred care is founded on ethics as a basis for organizing care. In spite of healthcare systems claiming that they have implemented person‐centred care, patients report less satisfaction with care. These contrasting results require clarification of how to practice person‐centred ethics using Paul Ricoeur's ‘Little ethics’, summarized as: ‘aiming for the good life, with and for others in just institutions’. In this ethic Kantian morality is at once subordinate and complementary to Aristotelian ethics because the ethical goal needs to be (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  19.  16
    Ethical and Legal Obligations for Research Involving Pregnant Persons in a Post- Dobbs Context.Richard M. Weinmeyer, Seema K. Shah & Michelle L. McGowan - 2023 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 51 (3):504-510.
    In light of a history of categorical exclusion, it is critical that pregnant people are included in research to help improve the knowledge base and interventions needed to address public health. Yet the volatile legal landscape around reproductive rights in the United States threatens to undue recent progress made toward the greater inclusion of pregnant people in research. We offer ethical and practical guidance for researchers, sponsors, and institutional review boards to take specific steps to minimize legal risks and ensure (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  21
    Respect for Persons, the Pleasure-Principle, and Obligation.J. O. Wisdom - 1961 - Atti Del XII Congresso Internazionale di Filosofia 7:473-479.
  21. Book Reviews-Moral Status: Obligations to Persons and Other Living Things.Mary Anne Warren & David Boonin - 1999 - Bioethics 13 (1):81-83.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Moral Status: Obligations to Persons and Other Living Things.Mary Anne Warren - 1997 - Oxford, GB: Clarendon Press.
    Mary Anne Warren investigates a theoretical question that is at the centre of practical and professional ethics: what are the criteria for having moral status? That is: what does it take to be an entity towards which people have moral considerations? Warren argues that no single property will do as a sole criterion, and puts forward seven basic principles which establish moral status. She then applies these principles to three controversial moral issues: voluntary euthanasia, abortion, and the status of non-human (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  23.  38
    Toward Meeting the Obligation of Respect for Persons in Pragmatic Clinical Trials.Stephanie R. Morain, Stephanie A. Kraft, Benjamin S. Wilfond, Amy Mcguire, Neal W. Dickert, Andrew Garland & Jeremy Sugarman - 2022 - Hastings Center Report 52 (3):9-17.
    Hastings Center Report, Volume 52, Issue 3, Page 9-17, May–June 2022.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24. Two moral essays: Draft for a statement of human obligations, and, Human personality.Simone Weil - 1981 - Wallingford, Pennsylvania: Pendle Hill Publications.
    Draft for a statement of human obligations -- Human personality.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  61
    Impossible obligations and the non-identity problem.Robert Noggle - 2019 - Philosophical Studies 176 (9):2371-2390.
    In a common example of the non-identity problem, a person deliberately conceives a child who she knows will have incurable blindness but a life well worth living. Although Wilma’s decision seems wrong, it is difficult to say why. This paper develops and defends a version of the “indirect strategy” for solving the NIP. This strategy rests on the idea that it is wrong to deliberately make it impossible to fulfill an obligation; consequently, it is wrong for Wilma to create (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  26. Moral obligation, accountability, and second-personal reasons. [REVIEW]Jada Twedt Strabbing - 2010 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81 (1):237-245.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  82
    Two Accounts of Our Obligations to Respect Persons.Bart Gruzalski - 1982 - Tulane Studies in Philosophy 31:77-89.
  28. Moral Status: Obligations to Persons and Other Living Things.Lawrence Johnson - 1999 - Environmental Values 8.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. The moral obligations of trust.Paul Faulkner - 2014 - Philosophical Explorations 17 (3):332-345.
    Moral obligation, Darwall argues, is irreducibly second personal. So too, McMyler argues, is the reason for belief supplied by testimony and which supports trust. In this paper, I follow Darwall in arguing that the testimony is not second personal ?all the way down?. However, I go on to argue, this shows that trust is not fully second personal, which in turn shows that moral obligation is equally not second personal ?all the way down?
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  30.  14
    Personal Metaphors as Motivational Resources: Boosting Anticipated Incentives and Feelings of Vitality Through a Personal Motto-Goal.Thomas H. Dyllick, Oliver Dickhäuser & Dagmar Stahlberg - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    Motto-goals describe a desired mind-set and provide a person with a guiding principle of how to approach a personal goal or obligation. We propose that motto-goals can be conceptionalized as individually created metaphors and that the figurative, metaphorical language and the characteristics of the formation process make them effective in changing the perception of unpleasant personal obligations as more inherently enjoyable and raise vitality levels. To test whether a newly devised minimalistic motto-goal intervention can make goal striving (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  17
    Book Review: Moral status: obligations for persons and other living things. [REVIEW]Liam Clarke - 1998 - Nursing Ethics 5 (4):377-378.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  34
    On Obligations to Future Generations.Bruce R. Reichenbach - 1992 - Public Affairs Quarterly 6 (2):207-225.
    I argue that "obligation" is a referential notion, flowing from actual or potential relationships. Applied to future persons, our relationship with them is established by virtue of the significant effects that our acts will have on them, and this in turn provides the basis of our obligation to them. Referential problems arise particularly in the types of cases where alternative acts bring different people into existence, for here there is no clear referent of the obligation. In such (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  33.  23
    Dining and obligation in Valerius maximus: The case of the sacra mensae.Jack Lennon - 2015 - Classical Quarterly 65 (2):719-731.
    The phrase sacra mensae appears in only a select number of instances from the first century a.d. onwards. This paper seeks to demonstrate that references to sacra mensae are not coincidental, and that they were employed deliberately by authors such as Valerius Maximus and, after him, Quintilian, Tacitus and Seneca, based on an assumed shared understanding of their significance on the part of Roman audiences. Although it appears across a variety of literary works and in a range of contexts, the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  21
    “That world is not for me”: Constructing a personal sense of opposition against school obligations.Claudia L. Saucedo Ramos Ramos - 2001 - Outlines. Critical Practice Studies 3 (2):61-76.
    This study contributes to the contemporary discussion on school drop-out. Based on ethnographic materials I analyze the life contexts of working-class families in Mexico. Two case-stories from these materials on school drop-outs are presented and analyzed here. These two young people constructed narrative self-understandings and orientations about their lives and school drop-out in which they describe their experiences of school as a way to participate in "multiple worlds" across different social contexts in search of more rewarding life options than school. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  60
    Moral Status: Obligations to Persons and Other Living Things.A. J. Mckay - 1998 - Journal of Medical Ethics 24 (5):354-355.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  96
    Political Authority and Political Obligation.Stephen Perry - 2013 - In Perry Stephen R. (ed.), Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law: Volume 2. Oxford University Press. pp. 1-74.
    Legitimate political authority is often said to involve a “right to rule,” which is most plausibly understood as a Hohfeldian moral power on the part of the state to impose obligations on its subjects (or otherwise to change their normative situation). Many writers have taken the state’s moral power (if and when it exists) to be a correlate, in some sense, of an obligation on the part of the state’s subjects to obey its directives. Thus legitimate political authority is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  37.  68
    Our obligation to the dead.Bob Brecher - 2002 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 19 (2):109-190.
    Can we have a real obligation to the dead, just as we do to the living, or is such a notion merely sentimental or metaphorical? Starting with the example of making a promise, I try to show that we can, since the dead, as well as the living, can have interests, not least because the notion of a person is, in part, a moral construction. ‘The dead’, then, are not merely dead, but particular dead persons, members of something like (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  38. Praise, blame, obligation, and DWE: Toward a framework for classical supererogation and kin.Paul McNamara - 2011 - Journal of Applied Logic 9 (2):153-170.
    Continuing prior work by the author, a simple classical system for personal obligation is integrated with a fairly rich system for aretaic (agent-evaluative) appraisal. I then explore various relationships between definable aretaic statuses such as praiseworthiness and blameworthiness and deontic statuses such as obligatoriness and impermissibility. I focus on partitions of the normative statuses generated ("normative positions" but without explicit representation of agency). In addition to being able to model and explore fundamental questions in ethical theory about the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  39. Getting Obligations Right: Autonomy and Shared Decision Making.Jonathan Lewis - 2020 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 37 (1):118-140.
    Shared Decision Making (‘SDM’) is one of the most significant developments in Western health care practices in recent years. Whereas traditional models of care operate on the basis of the physician as the primary medical decision maker, SDM requires patients to be supported to consider options in order to achieve informed preferences by mutually sharing the best available evidence. According to its proponents, SDM is the right way to interpret the clinician-patient relationship because it fulfils the ethical imperative of respecting (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  40.  46
    Lay obligations in professional relations.Martin Benjamin - 1985 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 10 (1):85-103.
    Little has been written recently about the obligations of lay people in professional relationships. Yet the Code of Medical Ethics adopted by the American Medical Association in 1847 included an extensive statement on ‘Obligations of patients to their physicians’. After critically examining the philosophical foundations of this statement, I provide an alternative account of lay obligations in professional relationships. Based on a hypothetical social contract and included in a full specification of professional as well as lay obligations, this account requires (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  20
    Pandemics and Beyond: Considerations When Personal Risk and Professional Obligations Converge.Douglas S. Diekema, Joan S. Roberts, Mithya Lewis-Newby & Daniel J. Benedetti - 2021 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 32 (1):20-34.
    With each novel infectious disease outbreak, there is scholarly attention to healthcare providers’ obligation to assume personal risk while they care for infected patients. While most agree that healthcare providers have a duty to assume some degree of risk, the extent of this obligation remains uncertain. Furthermore, these analyses rarely examine healthcare institutions’ obligations during these outbreaks. As a result, there is little practical guidance for healthcare institutions that are forced to weigh whether or when to exclude (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  80
    Mary Anne Warren, Moral Status: Obligations to Persons and Other Living Things:Moral Status: Obligations to Persons and Other Living Things.Bart Gruzalski - 2000 - Ethics 110 (3):645-649.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  46
    Liberal Loyalty: Freedom, Obligation, and the State.Anna Stilz - 2009 - Princeton University Press.
    Many political theorists today deny that citizenship can be defended on liberal grounds alone. Cosmopolitans claim that loyalty to a particular state is incompatible with universal liberal principles, which hold that we have equal duties of justice to persons everywhere, while nationalist theorists justify civic obligations only by reaching beyond liberal principles and invoking the importance of national culture. In Liberal Loyalty, Anna Stilz challenges both views by defending a distinctively liberal understanding of citizenship. Drawing on Kant, Rousseau, and Habermas, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  44.  23
    From Personal Life to Private Law.John Gardner - 2018 - Oxford University Press.
    The book examines the philosophical foundations of private law, arguing that the foremost preoccupations of the law of obligations are grounded in and pervade the personal lives of individuals.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  45. Obligations to Artworks as Duties of Love.Anthony Cross - 2017 - Estetika: The European Journal of Aesthetics 54 (1):85-101.
    It is uncontroversial that our engagement with artworks is constrained by obligations; most commonly, these consist in obligations to other persons, such as artists, audiences, and owners of artworks. A more controversial claim is that we have genuine obligations to artworks themselves. I defend a qualified version of this claim. However, I argue that such obligations do not derive from the supposed moral rights of artworks – for no such rights exist. Rather, I argue that these obligations are instances of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  46.  8
    Relationships, Obligations, Normativity, and Depth: A Response to Kellenberger.Robin Attfield - 2013 - Theoretical and Applied Ethics 2 (1):51-66.
    This paper supplies a critique of James Kellenberger’s thesis that relationships are deeper than principles because principles derive from and are determined by relationships. Relationships are admittedly sometimes normative, but it is implausible that an acceptable general theory of normativity can be based on this fact. The first section concerns Kellenberger’s initial thesis, which derives normativity from actual relationships. The following two sections concern his revised thesis, disclosed two-thirds of the way through his article, that normativity is conferred by proper (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Moral status. Obligations to persons and other living things, by Mary Anne Warren (oxford university press, 1997).Richard Joyce - unknown
    Warren’s goal is to present a ‘multi-criterial’ account of moral status—she eschews any view that holds ‘X has moral status iff X has N’ (where ‘N’ might be life, or personhood, or sentience, for example). Moral status, she asserts, is a more complex affair: it comes in degrees and there are a variety of sufficient conditions. The first part of the book (roughly three quarters of it) is devoted to outlining some standard ‘uni-lateral’ accounts, criticising them in so far as (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Obligations of Gratitude and Correlative Rights.Tony Manela - forthcoming - Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics 5.
    This article investigates a puzzle about gratitude—the proper response, in a beneficiary, to an act of benevolence from a benefactor. The puzzle arises from three platitudes about gratitude: 1) the beneficiary has certain obligations of gratitude; 2) these obligations are owed to the benefactor; and 3) the benefactor has no right to the fulfillment of these obligations. These platitudes suggest that gratitude is a counterexample to the “correlativity thesis” in the moral domain: the claim that strict moral obligations correlate to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  49.  39
    Obligations and preferences in knowing and not knowing: the importance of context.Lisa Dive & Ainsley Janelle Newson - 2020 - Journal of Medical Ethics 46 (5):306-307.
    In healthcare broadly, and especially in genetic (and now genomic) medicine, there is an ongoing debate about whether patients have a right not to know (RNTK) information about their own health. The extensive literature on this topic is characterised by a range of different understandings of what it means to have a RNTK,1–9 and how this purported right relates to patient autonomy. Ben Davies considers whether obligations not to place avoidable burdens on a publicly funded healthcare system might form the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  74
    The Obligation to Know: Information and the Burdens of Citizenship.Steve Vanderheiden - 2016 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 19 (2):297-311.
    Contemporary persons are daily confronted with enormous quantities of information, some of which reveal causal connections between their actions and harm that is visited upon distant others. Given their limited cognitive and information processing capacities, persons cannot reasonably be expected to respond to every cry for help or call to action, but neither can they defensibly refuse to hear and reflect upon any of them. Persons have a limited obligation to know, I argue, which requires that they inform themselves (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
1 — 50 / 983