Results for 'Ilkka Knuuttila'

445 found
Order:
  1.  43
    Knowledge and Inquiry: Essays on Jaakko Hintikka’s Epistemology and Philosophy of Science.Matti Sintonen (ed.) - 1997 - Brill | Rodopi.
    Contents: Matti SINTONEN: From the Science of Logic to the Logic of Science. I: HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVES. Zev BECHLER: Hintikka on Plenitude in Aristotle. Marja-Liisa KAKKURI-KNUUTTILA: What Can the Sciences of Man Learn from Aristotle? Martin KUSCH: Theories of Questions in German-Speaking Philosophy Around the Turn of the Century. Nils-Eric SAHLIN: 'HE IS NO GOOD FOR MY WORK': On the Philosophical Relations between Ramsey and Wittgenstein. II: FORMAL TOOLS: INDUCTION, OBSERVATION AND IDENTIFIABILITY. Theo A.F. KUIPERS: The Carnap-Hintikka Programme in Inductive (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  2. Models, Representation, and Mediation.Tarja Knuuttila - 2005 - Philosophy of Science 72 (5):1260-1271.
    Representation has been one of the main themes in the recent discussion of models. Several authors have argued for a pragmatic approach to representation that takes users and their interpretations into account. It appears to me, however, that this emphasis on representation places excessive limitations on our view of models and their epistemic value. Models should rather be thought of as epistemic artifacts through which we gain knowledge in diverse ways. Approaching models this way stresses their materiality and media-specificity. Focusing (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   138 citations  
  3. Modelling and representing: An artefactual approach to model-based representation.Tarja Knuuttila - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (2):262-271.
    The recent discussion on scientific representation has focused on models and their relationship to the real world. It has been assumed that models give us knowledge because they represent their supposed real target systems. However, here agreement among philosophers of science has tended to end as they have presented widely different views on how representation should be understood. I will argue that the traditional representational approach is too limiting as regards the epistemic value of modelling given the focus on the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   137 citations  
  4. Scientific and "radical" ethnomethodology: From incompatible paradigms to ethnomethodological sociology.Ilkka Arminen - 2008 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 38 (2):167-191.
    Ethnomethodology has been torn between scientific and "radical" aspirations insofar as it moves discoursive practices from resources to the topic of the study. Scientific ethnomethodology, such as conversation analysis, studies discoursive praxis as its topic and resource. Standard scientific criteria are accepted to assess the merits of its findings. "Radical" ethnomethodology addresses mundane reasoning exclusively as its topic without recourse to standardized science. I will show that insofar as "radical" ethnomethodology succeeds in bracketing everyday resources, it loses its phenomenon with (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  5.  39
    Evaluation of theories.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2007 - In Theo A. F. Kuipers (ed.), General philosophy of science. London: North Holland. pp. 175--217.
  6. Truth-Seeking by Abduction.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2018 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer.
    This book examines the philosophical conception of abductive reasoning as developed by Charles S. Peirce, the founder of American pragmatism. It explores the historical and systematic connections of Peirce's original ideas and debates about their interpretations. Abduction is understood in a broad sense which covers the discovery and pursuit of hypotheses and inference to the best explanation. The analysis presents fresh insights into this notion of reasoning, which derives from effects to causes or from surprising observations to explanatory theories. The (...)
  7. How do models give us knowledge? The case of Carnot’s ideal heat engine.Tarja Knuuttila & Mieke Boon - 2011 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 1 (3):309-334.
    Our concern is in explaining how and why models give us useful knowledge. We argue that if we are to understand how models function in the actual scientific practice the representational approach to models proves either misleading or too minimal. We propose turning from the representational approach to the artefactual, which implies also a new unit of analysis: the activity of modelling. Modelling, we suggest, could be approached as a specific practice in which concrete artefacts, i.e., models, are constructed with (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  8. Optimistic realism about scientific progress.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2017 - Synthese 194 (9):3291-3309.
    Scientific realists use the “no miracle argument” to show that the empirical and pragmatic success of science is an indicator of the ability of scientific theories to give true or truthlike representations of unobservable reality. While antirealists define scientific progress in terms of empirical success or practical problem-solving, realists characterize progress by using some truth-related criteria. This paper defends the definition of scientific progress as increasing truthlikeness or verisimilitude. Antirealists have tried to rebut realism with the “pessimistic metainduction”, but critical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  9. Isolating Representations Versus Credible Constructions? Economic Modelling in Theory and Practice.Tarja Knuuttila - 2009 - Erkenntnis 70 (1):59-80.
    This paper examines two recent approaches to the nature and functioning of economic models: models as isolating representations and models as credible constructions. The isolationist view conceives of economic models as surrogate systems that isolate some of the causal mechanisms or tendencies of their respective target systems, while the constructionist approach treats them rather like pure constructions or fictional entities that nevertheless license different kinds of inferences. I will argue that whereas the isolationist view is still tied to the representationalist (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  10. A parser as an epistemic artifact: A material view on models.Tarja Knuuttila & Atro Voutilainen - 2003 - Philosophy of Science 70 (5):1484-1495.
    The purpose of this paper is to suggest that models in scientific practice can be conceived of as epistemic artifacts. Approaching models this way accommodates many such things that working scientists themselves call models but that the semantic conception of models does not duly recognize as such. That models are epistemic artifacts implies, firstly, that they cannot be understood apart from purposeful human activity; secondly, that they are somehow materialized inhabitants of the intersubjective field of that activity; and thirdly, that (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  11. Synthetic Modeling and Mechanistic Account: Material Recombination and Beyond.Tarja Knuuttila & Andrea Loettgers - 2013 - Philosophy of Science 80 (5):874-885.
    Recently, Bechtel and Abrahamsen have argued that mathematical models study the dynamics of mechanisms by recomposing the components and their operations into an appropriately organized system. We will study this claim through the practice of combinational modeling in circadian clock research. In combinational modeling, experiments on model organisms and mathematical/computational models are combined with a new type of model—a synthetic model. We argue that the strategy of recomposition is more complicated than what Bechtel and Abrahamsen indicate. Moreover, synthetic modeling as (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  12. Critical scientific realism.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1999 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This book comes to the rescue of scientific realism, showing that reports of its death have been greatly exaggerated. Philosophical realism holds that the aim of a particular discourse is to make true statements about its subject matter. Ilkka Niiniluoto surveys different kinds of realism in various areas of philosophy and then sets out his own critical realist philosophy of science.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   217 citations  
  13.  48
    Truth-Seeking by Abduction.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2004 - Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 11:57-82.
    In a seminar with the title “Deduction and Induction in the Sciences”, it is intriguing to ask the following questions: Is there a third type of inference besides deduction and induction? Does this third type of inference play a significant role within scientific inquiry? A positive answer to both of these questions was advocated by Charles S. Peirce throughout his career, even though his opinions changed in important ways during the fifty years between 1865 and 1914. Peirce called the third (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  14. Scientific progress as increasing verisimilitude.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2014 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 46:73-77.
    According to the foundationalist picture, shared by many rationalists and positivist empiricists, science makes cognitive progress by accumulating justified truths. Fallibilists, who point out that complete certainty cannot be achieved in empirical science, can still argue that even successions of false theories may progress toward the truth. This proposal was supported by Karl Popper with his notion of truthlikeness or verisimilitude. Popper’s own technical definition failed, but the idea that scientific progress means increasing truthlikeness can be expressed by defining degrees (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  15.  15
    The Role of al-Madāʾinī’s Students in the Transmission of His Material.Ilkka Lindstedt - 2014 - Der Islam: Journal of the History and Culture of the Middle East 91 (2):295-340.
    Name der Zeitschrift: Der Islam Jahrgang: 91 Heft: 2 Seiten: 295-340.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16. Representation of the body as a basis of personal knowledge: A neuro-sychological perspective on Polanyi's subjective dimension of knowing.Ilkka Virtanen - 2011 - Appraisal 8 (3).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  27
    Biodiversity, microbes and human well-being.Ilkka Hanski - 2014 - Ethics in Science and Environmental Politics 14 (1):19-25.
  18.  26
    Concepts, Beliefs, and Their Constellations.Ilkka Kärrylä - 2022 - Contributions to the History of Concepts 17 (1):62-83.
    The article argues that all disciplines examining human thought could use certain shared analytical categories. This would not mean eradicating all differences between various approaches such as intellectual history and discourse analysis, but acknowledging that they are examining partly the same basic entities. The article argues that ideational entities in human thought could be understood as concepts, beliefs, and their constellations. The article discusses the views of scholars who have theorized similar categories and shows how these can be studied through (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Believing and doing : ritual action enhances religious belief.Ilkka Pyysiinen - 2011 - In Armin W. Geertz & Jeppe Sinding Jensen (eds.), Religious narrative, cognition, and culture: image and word in the mind of narrative. Oakville, CT: Equinox.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Defending abduction.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1999 - Philosophy of Science 66 (3):451.
    Charles S. Peirce argued that, besides deduction and induction, there is a third mode of inference which he called " hypothesis " or " abduction." He characterized abduction as reasoning " from effect to cause," and as " the operation of adopting an explanatory hypothesis." Peirce ' s ideas about abduction, which are related also to historically earlier accounts of heuristic reasoning, have been seen as providing a logic of scientific discovery. Alternatively, abduction is interpreted as giving reasons for pursuing (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  21. Is Science Progressive?Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1987 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (2):272-276.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  22.  43
    Abduction, tomography, and other inverse problems.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (1):135-139.
    Charles S. Peirce introduced in the late 19th century the notion of abduction as inference from effects to causes, or from observational data to explanatory theories. Abductive reasoning has become a major theme in contemporary logic, philosophy of science, and artificial intelligence. This paper argues that the new growing branch of applied mathematics called inverse problems deals successfully with various kinds of abductive inference within a variety of scientific disciplines. The fundamental theorem about the inverse reconstruction of plane functions from (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  23.  24
    On the Philosophy of Applied Social Sciences.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2013 - In Hanne Andersen, Dennis Dieks, Wenceslao J. Gonzalez, Thomas Uebel & Gregory Wheeler (eds.), New Challenges to Philosophy of Science. Springer Verlag. pp. 265--274.
  24. 'God'as ultimate reality in religion and in science.Ilkka Pyysiäinen - 1999 - Ultimate Reality and Meaning 22 (2):106-123.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25. (1 other version)The Logic of Being.Simo Knuuttila & Jaakko Hintikka - 1989 - Studia Logica 48 (1):133-133.
  26.  43
    Synthetic Biology as an Engineering Science? Analogical Reasoning, Synthetic Modeling, and Integration.Tarja Knuuttila & Andrea Loettgers - 2013 - In Hanne Andersen, Dennis Dieks, Wenceslao J. Gonzalez, Thomas Uebel & Gregory Wheeler (eds.), New Challenges to Philosophy of Science. Springer Verlag. pp. 163--177.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  62
    European dimensions of Finnish culture: A survey of international and European orientation of Finnish intellectuals.Ilkka Heiskanen, Ritva Mitchell & Pasi Saukkonen - 1994 - World Futures 39 (1):25-46.
    (1994). European dimensions of Finnish culture: A survey of international and European orientation of Finnish intellectuals. World Futures: Vol. 39, The Evolution of European Identity: Surveys of the Growing Edge A Report by the European Culture Impact Research Consortium (EUROCIRCON), pp. 25-46.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  16
    Does meditation swamp working memory?Pyysiainen Ilkka - 2006 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 29 (6).
  29.  12
    No evidence of a specific adaptation.Pyysiainen Ilkka - 2006 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 29 (5):484.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  34
    Science — A House Built on Sand?Ilkka Kieseppä & Friedrich Stadler - 1999 - Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 7:279-301.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  58
    Religion is neither costly nor beneficial.Ilkka Pyysiäinen - 2004 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (6):746-746.
    Some forms of religion may in some cases alleviate existential anxieties and help maintain morality; yet religion can also persist without serving any such functions. Atran & Norenzayan (A&N) are unclear about the importance of these functions for a theory of the recurrence of religious beliefs and behaviors.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  16
    Theoretical concepts and hypothetico-inductive inference.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1973 - Boston,: D. Reidel Pub. Co.. Edited by Raimo Tuomela.
    Conceptual change and its connection to the development of new seien tific theories has reeently beeome an intensively discussed topic in philo sophieal literature. Even if the inductive aspects related to conceptual change have already been discussed to some extent, there has so far existed no systematic treatment of inductive change due to conceptual enrichment. This is what we attempt to accomplish in this work, al though most of our technical results are restricted to the framework of monadic languages. We (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  33.  27
    Sequential order and sequence structure: the case of incommensurable studies on mobile phone calls.Ilkka Arminen - 2005 - Discourse Studies 7 (6):649-662.
    Two recent conversation analytical studies draw contrary conclusions from seemingly very similar materials. Hutchby and Barnett ‘show that, far from revolutionizing the organization of telephone conversation, mobile phone talk retains many of the norms associated with landline phone talk’. Arminen and Leinonen, however, state that landline and mobile calls differ systematically from each other. These incommensurate findings raise the question of why the comparisons between landline and mobile call openings have not been able to determine whether social and communicative practices (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  34.  50
    (1 other version)Measuring the Success of Science.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1990 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990:435 - 445.
    This paper discusses alternative ways of defining and measuring institutional, pragmatic, empirical, and cognitive success in science. Four realist measures of epistemic credit are compared: posterior probability, confirmation (corroboration), expected verisimilitude, and probable verisimilitude. Laudan's non-realist concept of the empirical problem-solving effectiveness of a theory is found to be similar to Hempel's notion of systematic power. It is argued that such truth-independent concepts alone are insufficient and inadequate to characterize cognitive success. But if they are used as truth-dependent epistemic utilities, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  35. Survey article. Verisimilitude: the third period.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1998 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49 (1):1-29.
    The modern history of verisimilitude can be divided into three periods. The first began in 1960, when Karl Popper proposed his qualitative definition of what it is for one theory to be more truthlike than another theory, and lasted until 1974, when David Miller and Pavel Trichý published their refutation of Popper's definition. The second period started immediately with the attempt to explicate truthlikeness by means of relations of similarity or resemblance between states of affairs (or their linguistic representations); the (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  36.  88
    Modalities in Medieval Philosophy.Simo Knuuttila - 1993 - New York: Routledge.
    Originally published in 1993, Modalities in Medieval Philosophy looks at the idea of modality as multiplicity of reference with respect to alternative domains. The book examines how this emerged in early medieval discussions and addresses how it was originally influenced by the theological conception of God acting by choice. After a discussion of ancient modal paradigms, the author traces the interplay of old and new modal views in medieval logic and semantics, philosophy and theology. A detailed account is given of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  37.  38
    Some Consequences of the Pragmatist Approach to Representation.Tarja Knuuttila - 2010 - In M. Dorato M. Suàrez (ed.), Epsa Epistemology and Methodology of Science. Springer. pp. 139--148.
  38. The productive tension : mechanisms vs. templates in modeling the phenomena.Tarja Knuuttila & Andrea Loettgers - 2011 - In Paul Humphreys & Cyrille Imbert (eds.), Models, Simulations, and Representations. New York: Routledge.
  39.  49
    Igor Douven, The Art of Abduction.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2024 - Journal of Philosophy 121 (3):175-179.
  40. The Relevance of Dialectical Skills to Philosophical Inquiry in Aristotle.Marja-Liisa Kakkuri-Knuuttila - 2005 - Rhizai. A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science 1:31-74.
    In spite of numerous outstanding recent contributions on Aristotle’s dialectic, it seems that our picture of dialectic in the Topics is not yet clear enough to settle the questions concerning the purpose and utility of dialectic. Thegoalofthispaperisamore modest one, simply to clarify our notion of dialectic and the skills involved. Thisinvestigation will allow us to draw some conclusions concerning their relevance to Aristotle’s philosophical inquiry.The paper formulates and systematizes the rules for dialectica ldisputations in Topics Book I and III so (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  41.  37
    On a K-Dimensional System of Inductive Logic.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1976 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1976:425 - 447.
  42.  43
    Truthlikeness.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1987 - Dordrecht: Reidel.
    The modern discussion on the concept of truthlikeness was started in 1960. In his influential Word and Object, W. V. O. Quine argued that Charles Peirce's definition of truth as the limit of inquiry is faulty for the reason that the notion 'nearer than' is only "defined for numbers and not for theories". In his contribution to the 1960 International Congress for Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science at Stan­ ford, Karl Popper defended the opposite view by defining a compara­tive (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  43. LSP-Research, Philosophy of Science, and the Question-Theoretical Approach -- some Tentative Suggestions.Marja-Liisa Kakkuri-Knuuttila & Martin Kusch - 1991 - In Hartmut Schröder (ed.), Subject-Oriented Texts: Language for Special Purposes and Text Theory. De Gruyter. pp. 167--198.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Degrees of truthlikeness: From singular sentences to generalisations.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1979 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 30 (4):371-376.
  45. Dretske on laws of nature.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 45 (3):431-439.
    In a recent article [4], Fred I. Dretske has proposed a new analysis of natural laws. Dretske rejects the more or less standard view which says that laws are universal truths with a special function or status in science. As an alternative account, he suggests that laws are expressed by singular statements describing the relationship between universal properties and magnitudes: the statement It is a law that F's are G's3.is to be analysed as F-ness ↦ G-ness.I shall argue, however, that (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  46. Possible Worlds of History.Ilkka Lähteenmäki - 2018 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 12 (1):164-182.
    _ Source: _Page Count 19 The theory of possible worlds has been minimally employed in the field of theory and philosophy of history, even though it has found a place as a tool in other areas of philosophy. Discussion has mostly focused on arguments concerning counterfactual history’s status as either useful or harmful. The theory of possible worlds can, however be used also to analyze historical writing. The concept of textual possible worlds offers an interesting framework to work with for (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Natural Necessity in John Buridan.Simo Knuuttila - 1989 - In Stefano Caroti (ed.), Studies in medieval natural philosophy. [Firenze]: L.S. Olschki.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48. Theories, approximations, and idealizations.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1990 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 16:9-57.
  49. L’effet de réel revisited.Sirkka Knuuttila - 2008 - Sign Systems Studies 36 (1):113-135.
    This article addresses Barthes’s development from a structuralist semiotician towards an affectively responding reader in terms of ‘postrational’ subjectivity. In light of his whole oeuvre, Barthes anticipates the understanding of emotion as an integral part of cognition presented in contemporary social neuroscience. To illustrate Barthes’s growing awareness of the importance of this epistemological move, the article starts from his textual ‘reality effect’ as a critical vehicle of realist representation. It then shifts to his attempt at conceptualising an affective reading which (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  87
    Mahdollisuus.Ilkka Niiniluoto, Tuomas Tahko & Teemu Toppinen (eds.) - 2016 - Helsinki: Philosophical Society of Finland.
    Proceedings of the 2016 "one word" colloquium of the The Philosophical Society of Finland. The word was "Possibility".
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 445