Results for 'Henkin semantics'

953 found
Order:
  1.  51
    On the semantics of the Henkin quantifier.Michał Krynicki & Alistair H. Lachlan - 1979 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 44 (2):184-200.
  2.  25
    Henkin on Nominalism and Higher-Order Logic.Diego Pinheiro Fernandes - 2022 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 26 (2).
    In this paper a proposal by Henkin of a nominalistic interpretation for second and higher-order logic is developed in detail and analysed. It was proposed as a response to Quine’s claim that second and higher-order logic not only are committed to the existence of sets, but also are committed to the existence of more sets than can ever be referred to in the language. Henkin’s interpretation is rarely cited in the debate on semantics and ontological commitments for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  65
    A simple Henkin-style completeness proof for Gödel 3-valued logic G3.Gemma Robles - 2014 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 23 (4):371-390.
    A simple Henkin-style completeness proof for Gödel 3-valued propositional logic G3 is provided. The idea is to endow G3 with an under-determined semantics of the type defined by Dunn. The key concept in u-semantics is that of “under-determined interpretation”. It is shown that consistent prime theories built upon G3 can be understood as u-interpretations. In order to prove this fact we follow Brady by defining G3 as an extension of Anderson and Belnap’s positive fragment of First Degree (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  4.  59
    Saul A. Kripke. Semantical analysis of modal logic II. Non-normal modal propositional calculi. The theory of models, Proceedings of the 1963 International Symposium at Berkeley, edited by J. W. Addison, Leon Henkin, and Alfred Tarski, Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics, North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam1965, pp. 206–220. - R. Routley and H. Montgomery. The inadequacy of Kripke's semantical analysis of D2 and D3. The journal of symbolic logic, vol. 33 , p. 568. [REVIEW]David Makinson - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (1):135.
    Reviews of the papers mentioned in the title.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Second-order logic: properties, semantics, and existential commitments.Bob Hale - 2019 - Synthese 196 (7):2643-2669.
    Quine’s most important charge against second-, and more generally, higher-order logic is that it carries massive existential commitments. The force of this charge does not depend upon Quine’s questionable assimilation of second-order logic to set theory. Even if we take second-order variables to range over properties, rather than sets, the charge remains in force, as long as properties are individuated purely extensionally. I argue that if we interpret them as ranging over properties more reasonably construed, in accordance with an abundant (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  6.  96
    Completeness: from Gödel to Henkin.Maria Manzano & Enrique Alonso - 2014 - History and Philosophy of Logic 35 (1):1-26.
    This paper focuses on the evolution of the notion of completeness in contemporary logic. We discuss the differences between the notions of completeness of a theory, the completeness of a calculus, and the completeness of a logic in the light of Gödel's and Tarski's crucial contributions.We place special emphasis on understanding the differences in how these concepts were used then and now, as well as on the role they play in logic. Nevertheless, we can still observe a certain ambiguity in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  7.  45
    Equilibrium semantics of languages of imperfect information.Merlijn Sevenster & Gabriel Sandu - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (5):618-631.
    In this paper, we introduce a new approach to independent quantifiers, as originally introduced in Informational independence as a semantic phenomenon by Hintikka and Sandu [9] under the header of independence-friendly languages. Unlike other approaches, which rely heavily on compositional methods, we shall analyze independent quantifiers via equilibriums in strategic games. In this approach, coined equilibrium semantics, the value of an IF sentence on a particular structure is determined by the expected utility of the existential player in any of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  8.  38
    Valuation Semantics for First-Order Logics of Evidence and Truth.H. Antunes, A. Rodrigues, W. Carnielli & M. E. Coniglio - 2022 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 51 (5):1141-1173.
    This paper introduces the logic _Q__L__E__T_ _F_, a quantified extension of the logic of evidence and truth _L__E__T_ _F_, together with a corresponding sound and complete first-order non-deterministic valuation semantics. _L__E__T_ _F_ is a paraconsistent and paracomplete sentential logic that extends the logic of first-degree entailment (_FDE_) with a classicality operator ∘ and a non-classicality operator ∙, dual to each other: while ∘_A_ entails that _A_ behaves classically, ∙_A_ follows from _A_’s violating some classically valid inferences. The semantics (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  9. Proof-theoretic semantic values for logical operators.Nissim Francez & Gilad Ben-avi - 2011 - Review of Symbolic Logic 4 (3):466-478.
    The paper proposes a semantic value for the logical constants (connectives and quantifiers) within the framework of proof-theoretic semantics, basic meaning on the introduction rules of a meaning conferring natural deduction proof system. The semantic value is defined based on Fregecontributions” to sentential meanings as determined by the function-argument structure as induced by a type-logical grammar. In doing so, the paper proposes a novel proof-theoretic interpretation of the semantic types, traditionally interpreted in Henkin models. The compositionality of the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  10. Proof-Theoretic Semantics for Subsentential Phrases.Nissim Francez, Roy Dyckhoff & Gilad Ben-Avi - 2010 - Studia Logica 94 (3):381-401.
    The paper briefly surveys the sentential proof-theoretic semantics for fragment of English. Then, appealing to a version of Frege’s context-principle (specified to fit type-logical grammar), a method is presented for deriving proof-theoretic meanings for sub-sentential phrases, down to lexical units (words). The sentential meaning is decomposed according to the function-argument structure as determined by the type-logical grammar. In doing so, the paper presents a novel proof-theoretic interpretation of simple type, replacing Montague’s model-theoretic type interpretation (in arbitrary Henkin models). (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  11.  45
    Semantical study of some systems of vagueness logic.A. Arruda & E. Alves - 1979 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 8 (3):139-144.
    In [1] we have characterized four types vagueness related to negation, and constructed the corresponding propositional calculi adequate to formalize each type of vagueness. The calculi obtained were named V0; V1; V2 and C1 . The relations among these calculi and the classical propositional calculus C0 can be represented in the following diagram, where the arrows indicate that a system is a proper subsystem of the other V0 V1 C0 V2 C1 6 1 PP PP PP PiP 1 PP PP (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  34
    Multi-Dimensional Semantics for Modal Logics.Maarten Marx - 1996 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 37 (1):25-34.
    We show that every modal logic (with arbitrary many modalities of arbitrary arity) can be seen as a multi-dimensional modal logic in the sense of Venema. This result shows that we can give every modal logic a uniform "concrete" semantics, as advocated by Henkin et al. This can also be obtained using the unravelling method described by de Rijke. The advantage of our construction is that the obtained class of frames is easily seen to be elementary and that (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  73
    Craig's interpolation theorem for the intuitionistic logic and its extensions—A semantical approach.Hiroakira Ono - 1986 - Studia Logica 45 (1):19-33.
    A semantical proof of Craig's interpolation theorem for the intuitionistic predicate logic and some intermediate prepositional logics will be given. Our proof is an extension of Henkin's method developed in [4]. It will clarify the relation between the interpolation theorem and Robinson's consistency theorem for these logics and will enable us to give a uniform way of proving the interpolation theorem for them.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  27
    Interpolation in Algebraizable Logics Semantics for Non-Normal Multi-Modal Logic.Judit X. Madarász - 1998 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 8 (1):67-105.
    ABSTRACT The two main directions pursued in the present paper are the following. The first direction was started by Pigozzi in 1969. In [Mak 91] and [Mak 79] Maksimova proved that a normal modal logic has the Craig interpolation property iff the corresponding class of algebras has the superamalgamation property. In this paper we extend Maksimova's theorem to normal multi-modal logics with arbitrarily many, not necessarily unary modalities, and to not necessarily normal multi-modal logics with modalities of ranks smaller than (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15.  66
    A new semantics for intuitionistic predicate logic.Yuichi Komori - 1986 - Studia Logica 45 (1):9 - 17.
    The main part of the proof of Kripke's completeness theorem for intuitionistic logic is Henkin's construction. We introduce a new Kripke-type semantics with semilattice structures for intuitionistic logic. The completeness theorem for this semantics can he proved without Henkin's construction.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16. Plausibility Revision in Higher-Order Logic With an Application in Two-Dimensional Semantics.Erich Rast - 2010 - In Arrazola Xabier & Maria Ponte, LogKCA-10 - Proceedings of the Second ILCLI International Workshop on Logic and Philosophy of Knowledge. ILCLI.
    In this article, a qualitative notion of subjective plausibility and its revision based on a preorder relation are implemented in higher-order logic. This notion of plausibility is used for modeling pragmatic aspects of communication on top of traditional two-dimensional semantic representations.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17.  47
    Computational complexity of the semantics of some natural language constructions.Marcin Mostowski & Dominika Wojtyniak - 2004 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 127 (1-3):219--227.
    We consider an example of a sentence which according to Hintikka's claim essentially requires for its logical form a Henkin quantifier. We show that if Hintikka is right then recognizing the truth value of the sentence in finite models is an NP-complete problem. We discuss also possible conclusions from this observation.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  18.  48
    Quantificational modal logic with sequential Kripke semantics.Stefano Borgo - 2005 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 15 (2):137-188.
    We introduce quantificational modal operators as dynamic modalities with (extensions of) Henkin quantifiers as indices. The adoption of matrices of indices (with action identifiers, variables and/or quantified variables as entries) gives an expressive formalism which is here motivated with examples from the area of multi-agent systems. We study the formal properties of the resulting logic which, formally speaking, does not satisfy the normality condition. However, the logic admits a semantics in terms of (an extension of) Kripke structures. As (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19. Ramsey Equivalence.Neil Dewar - 2019 - Erkenntnis 84 (1):77-99.
    In the literature over the Ramsey-sentence approach to structural realism, there is often debate over whether structural realists can legitimately restrict the range of the second-order quantifiers, in order to avoid the Newman problem. In this paper, I argue that even if they are allowed to, it won’t help: even if the Ramsey sentence is interpreted using such restricted quantifiers, it is still an implausible candidate to capture a theory’s structural content. To do so, I use the following observation: if (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  20.  56
    Forcing, Downward Löwenheim-Skolem and Omitting Types Theorems, Institutionally.Daniel Găină - 2014 - Logica Universalis 8 (3-4):469-498.
    In the context of proliferation of many logical systems in the area of mathematical logic and computer science, we present a generalization of forcing in institution-independent model theory which is used to prove two abstract results: Downward Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem and Omitting Types Theorem . We instantiate these general results to many first-order logics, which are, roughly speaking, logics whose sentences can be constructed from atomic formulas by means of Boolean connectives and classical first-order quantifiers. These include first-order logic , logic (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21. Arnoud Bayart's Modal Completeness Theorems — Translated with an Introduction and Commentary.M. J. Cresswell - 2015 - Logique Et Analyse 229 (1):89-142.
    In 1958 Arnould Bayart, 1911-1998, produced a semantics for first and second-order S5 modal logic, and in 1959 a completeness proof for first-order S5, and what he calls a 'quasi-completeness' proof for second-order S5. The 1959 paper is the first completeness proof for modal predicate logic based on the Henkin construction of maximal consistent sets, and indeed may be the easier application of the Henkin method even to propositional modal logic. The semantics is in terms of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  36
    Duality and Completeness for US-Logics.Fabio Bellissima & Saverio Cittadini - 1998 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 39 (2):231-242.
    The semantics of e-models for tense logics with binary operators for `until' and `since' (US-logics) was introduced by Bellissima and Bucalo in 1995. In this paper we show the adequacy of these semantics by proving a general Henkin-style completeness theorem. Moreover, we show that for these semantics there holds a Stone-like duality theorem with the algebraic structures that naturally arise from US-logics.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  17
    Cumulative Habilitation Script.Christoph Benzmüller - 2006 - Saarland University, Germany.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  31
    Combining and Automating Classical and Non-Classical Logics in Classical Higher-Order Logic.Christoph Benzmüller - 2011 - Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence) 62 (1-2):103-128.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25. On the Referential Indeterminacy of Logical and Mathematical Concepts.Otávio Bueno - 2005 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 34 (1):65 - 79.
    Hartry Field has recently examined the question whether our logical and mathematical concepts are referentially indeterminate. In his view, (1) certain logical notions, such as second-order quantification, are indeterminate, but (2) important mathematical notions, such as the notion of finiteness, are not (they are determinate). In this paper, I assess Field's analysis, and argue that claims (1) and (2) turn out to be inconsistent. After all, given that the notion of finiteness can only be adequately characterized in pure secondorder logic, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  54
    First-Order Definability of Transition Structures.Antje Rumberg & Alberto Zanardo - 2019 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 28 (3):459-488.
    The transition semantics presented in Rumberg (J Log Lang Inf 25(1):77–108, 2016a) constitutes a fine-grained framework for modeling the interrelation of modality and time in branching time structures. In that framework, sentences of the transition language L_t are evaluated on transition structures at pairs consisting of a moment and a set of transitions. In this paper, we provide a class of first-order definable Kripke structures that preserves L_t-validity w.r.t. transition structures. As a consequence, for a certain fragment of L_t, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  27.  94
    A Gabbay-Rule Free Axiomatization of T x W Validity.Maria Concetta Di Maio & Alberto Zanardo - 1998 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 27 (5):435 - 487.
    The semantical structures called T x W frames were introduced in (Thomason, 1984) for the Ockhamist temporal-modal language, $[Unrepresented Character]_{o}$ , which consists of the usual propositional language augmented with the Priorean operators P and F and with a possibility operator ◇. However, these structures are also suitable for interpreting an extended language, $[Unrepresented Character]_{so}$ , containing a further possibility operator $\lozenge^{s}$ which expresses synchronism among possibly incompatible histories and which can thus be thought of as a cross-history 'simultaneity' operator. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  28. Variable Binding Term Operators.John Corcoran, William Hatcher & John Herring - 1972 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 18 (12):177-182.
    Chapin reviewed this 1972 ZEITSCHRIFT paper that proves the completeness theorem for the logic of variable-binding-term operators created by Corcoran and his student John Herring in the 1971 LOGIQUE ET ANALYSE paper in which the theorem was conjectured. This leveraging proof extends completeness of ordinary first-order logic to the extension with vbtos. Newton da Costa independently proved the same theorem about the same time using a Henkin-type proof. This 1972 paper builds on the 1971 “Notes on a Semantic Analysis (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  29.  25
    The Logic of Epistemology and the Epistemology of Logic: Selected Essays.Jaakko Hintikka, Kaarlo Jaakko Juhani Hintikka & Merrill B. P. Hintikka (eds.) - 1989 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer Verlag.
    somewhat like Henkin's nonstandard interpretation of higher-order logics, while the right semantics [or logical modalities is an analogue to the standard of type theory in Henkin's sense. interpretation Another possibility would be to follow W.V. Quine's advice to give up logi­ cal modalities as being beyond repair. Or we could also try to develop a logic of conceptual possibility, restricting the range of our "possible worlds" to those compatible with the transcendental presuppositions of our own conceptual sys­ (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  30. Quantifying over propositions in relevance logic: nonaxiomatisability of primary interpretations of ∀ p and ∃ p.Philip Kremer - 1993 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 58 (1):334-349.
    A typical approach to semantics for relevance (and other) logics: specify a class of algebraic structures and take amodelto be one of these structures, α, together with some function or relation which associates with every formulaAa subset ofα. (This is the approach of, among others, Urquhart, Routley and Meyer and Fine.) In some cases there are restrictions on the class of subsets of α with which a formula can be associated: for example, in the semantics of Routley and (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  31.  50
    Temporal Logic: Mathematical Foundations and Computational Aspects.Dov M. Gabbay, Ian Hodkinson & Mark A. Reynolds - 1994 - Oxford University Press on Demand.
    This much-needed book provides a thorough account of temporal logic, one of the most important areas of logic in computer science today. The book begins with a solid introduction to semantical and axiomatic approaches to temporal logic. It goes on to cover predicate temporal logic, meta-languages, general theories of axiomatization, many dimensional systems, propositional quantifiers, expressive power, Henkin dimension, temporalization of other logics, and decidability results. With its inclusion of cutting-edge results and unifying methodologies, this book is an indispensable (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  32. Intensional models for the theory of types.Reinhard Muskens - 2007 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 72 (1):98-118.
    In this paper we define intensional models for the classical theory of types, thus arriving at an intensional type logic ITL. Intensional models generalize Henkin's general models and have a natural definition. As a class they do not validate the axiom of Extensionality. We give a cut-free sequent calculus for type theory and show completeness of this calculus with respect to the class of intensional models via a model existence theorem. After this we turn our attention to applications. Firstly, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  33. Higher-order automated theorem proving.Michael Kohlhase - unknown
    The history of building automated theorem provers for higher-order logic is almost as old as the field of deduction systems itself. The first successful attempts to mechanize and implement higher-order logic were those of Huet [13] and Jensen and Pietrzykowski [17]. They combine the resolution principle for higher-order logic (first studied in [1]) with higher-order unification. The unification problem in typed λ-calculi is much more complex than that for first-order terms, since it has to take the theory of αβη-equality into (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  34.  27
    On the completeness and the decidability of strictly monadic second‐order logic.Kento Takagi & Ryo Kashima - 2020 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 66 (4):438-447.
    Regarding strictly monadic second‐order logic (SMSOL), which is the fragment of monadic second‐order logic in which all predicate constants are unary and there are no function symbols, we show that a standard deductive system with full comprehension is sound and complete with respect to standard semantics. This result is achieved by showing that in the case of SMSOL, the truth value of any formula in a faithful identity‐standard Henkin structure is preserved when the structure is “standardized”; that is, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  43
    Predicate logics without the structure rules.Yuichi Komori - 1986 - Studia Logica 45 (4):393 - 404.
    In our previous paper [5], we have studied Kripke-type semantics for propositional logics without the contraction rule. In this paper, we will extend our argument to predicate logics without the structure rules. Similarly to the propositional case, we can not carry out Henkin's construction in the predicate case. Besides, there exists a difficulty that the rules of inference () and () are not always valid in our semantics. So, we have to introduce a notion of normal models.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  36. On the Innocence and Determinacy of Plural Quantification.Salvatore Florio & Øystein Linnebo - 2016 - Noûs 50 (3):565–583.
    Plural logic is widely assumed to have two important virtues: ontological innocence and determinacy. It is claimed to be innocent in the sense that it incurs no ontological commitments beyond those already incurred by the first-order quantifiers. It is claimed to be determinate in the sense that it is immune to the threat of non-standard interpretations that confronts higher-order logics on their more traditional, set-based semantics. We challenge both claims. Our challenge is based on a Henkin-style semantics (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  37.  98
    A partial functions version of church's simple theory of types.William M. Farmer - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (3):1269-1291.
    Church's simple theory of types is a system of higher-order logic in which functions are assumed to be total. We present in this paper a version of Church's system called PF in which functions may be partial. The semantics of PF, which is based on Henkin's general-models semantics, allows terms to be nondenoting but requires formulas to always denote a standard truth value. We prove that PF is complete with respect to its semantics. The reasoning mechanism (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  38. The Object Theory Logic of Intention.Dale L. Jacquette - 1983 - Dissertation, Brown University
    Alexius Meinong's Gegenstandstheorie is subject to a formal semantic paradox. The theory of defective objects originally developed by Meinong in response to Ernst Mally's paradox about self-referential thought is rejected as a general solution to paradox in the object theory. The intentionality thesis is also refuted by the counter-example of the unapprehended mountain. It is argued that despite these difficulties, an object theory is required in order to make intuitively correct sense of ontological commitment. ;A version of Meinong's theory is (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  26
    Mathematics of Modality.Robert Goldblatt - 1993 - Center for the Study of Language and Information Publications.
    Modal logic is the study of modalities - expressions that qualify assertions about the truth of statements - like the ordinary language phrases necessarily, possibly, it is known/believed/ought to be, etc., and computationally or mathematically motivated expressions like provably, at the next state, or after the computation terminates. The study of modalities dates from antiquity, but has been most actively pursued in the last three decades, since the introduction of the methods of Kripke semantics, and now impacts on a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  40. Pure Extensions, Proof Rules, and Hybrid Axiomatics.Patrick Blackburn & Balder Ten Cate - 2006 - Studia Logica 84 (2):277-322.
    In this paper we argue that hybrid logic is the deductive setting most natural for Kripke semantics. We do so by investigating hybrid axiomatics for a variety of systems, ranging from the basic hybrid language (a decidable system with the same complexity as orthodox propositional modal logic) to the strong Priorean language (which offers full first-order expressivity).We show that hybrid logic offers a genuinely first-order perspective on Kripke semantics: it is possible to define base logics which extend automatically (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  41. Program verification within and without logic.Hajnal Andreka, Istvan Nemeti & Ildiko Sain - 1979 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 8 (3):124-128.
    Theorem 1 states a negative result about the classical semantics j= ! of program schemes. Theorem 2 investigates the reason for this. We conclude that Theorem 2 justies the Henkin-type semantics j= for which the opposite of the present Theorem 1 was proved in [1]{[3] and also in a dierent form in part III of [5]. The strongest positive result on j= is Corollary 6 in [3].
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  42
    Identity, Equality, Nameability and Completeness.María Manzano & Manuel Crescencio Moreno - 2017 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 46 (3/4).
    This article is an extended promenade strolling along the winding roads of identity, equality, nameability and completeness, looking for places where they converge. We have distinguished between identity and equality; the first is a binary relation between objects while the second is a symbolic relation between terms. Owing to the central role the notion of identity plays in logic, you can be interested either in how to define it using other logical concepts or in the opposite scheme. In the first (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  43.  87
    Proofs and Countermodels in Non-Classical Logics.Sara Negri - 2014 - Logica Universalis 8 (1):25-60.
    Proofs and countermodels are the two sides of completeness proofs, but, in general, failure to find one does not automatically give the other. The limitation is encountered also for decidable non-classical logics in traditional completeness proofs based on Henkin’s method of maximal consistent sets of formulas. A method is presented that makes it possible to establish completeness in a direct way: For any given sequent either a proof in the given logical system or a countermodel in the corresponding frame (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  44. Generalized Logic: A Philosophical Perspective with Linguistic Applications.Gila Sher - 1989 - Dissertation, Columbia University
    The question motivating my investigation is: Are the basic philosophical principles underlying the "core" system of contemporary logic exhausted by the standard version? In particular, is the accepted narrow construal of the notion "logical term" justified? ;As a point of comparison I refer to systems of 1st-order logic with generalized quantifiers developed by mathematicians and linguists . Based on an analysis of the Tarskian conception of the role of logic I show that the standard division of terms into logical and (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  27
    Fibring Modal First-Order Logics: Completeness Preservation.Amilcar Sernadas, Cristina Sernadas & Alberto Zanardo - 2002 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 10 (4):413-451.
    Fibring is defined as a mechanism for combining logics with a first-order base, at both the semantic and deductive levels. A completeness theorem is established for a wide class of such logics, using a variation of the Henkin method that takes advantage of the presence of equality and inequality in the logic. As a corollary, completeness is shown to be preserved when fibring logics in that class. A modal first-order logic is obtained as a fibring where neither the Barcan (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  29
    Existence of Certain Finite Relation Algebras Implies Failure of Omitting Types for L n.Tarek Sayed Ahmed - 2020 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 61 (4):503-519.
    Fix 2 < n < ω. Let CA n denote the class of cylindric algebras of dimension n, and let RCA n denote the variety of representable CA n ’s. Let L n denote first-order logic restricted to the first n variables. Roughly, CA n, an instance of Boolean algebras with operators, is the algebraic counterpart of the syntax of L n, namely, its proof theory, while RCA n algebraically and geometrically represents the Tarskian semantics of L n. Unlike (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Quantified Multimodal Logics in Simple Type Theory.Christoph Benzmüller & Lawrence C. Paulson - 2013 - Logica Universalis 7 (1):7-20.
    We present an embedding of quantified multimodal logics into simple type theory and prove its soundness and completeness. A correspondence between QKπ models for quantified multimodal logics and Henkin models is established and exploited. Our embedding supports the application of off-the-shelf higher-order theorem provers for reasoning within and about quantified multimodal logics. Moreover, it provides a starting point for further logic embeddings and their combinations in simple type theory.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  48.  28
    Lewisian Naturalness and a new Sceptical Challenge.Matej Drobňák - 2022 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 31 (1):3-28.
    The criterion of naturalness represents David Lewis’s attempt to answer some of the sceptical arguments in (meta-) semantics by comparing the naturalness of meaning candidates. Recently, the criterion has been challenged by a new sceptical argument. Williams argues that the criterion cannot rule out the candidates which are not permuted versions of an intended interpretation. He presents such a candidate – the arithmetical interpretation (a specific instantiation of The criterion of naturalness represents David Lewis’s attempt to answer some of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  62
    Topological Representation of the Lambda-Calculus.Steve Awodey - 2000 - Mathematical Structures in Computer Science 10 (1):81-96.
    The [lambda]-calculus can be represented topologically by assigning certain spaces to the types and certain continuous maps to the terms. Using a recent result from category theory, the usual calculus of [lambda]-conversion is shown to be deductively complete with respect to such topological semantics. It is also shown to be functionally complete, in the sense that there is always a ‘minimal’ topological model in which every continuous function is [lambda]-definable. These results subsume earlier ones using cartesian closed categories, as (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50. Subformula and separation properties in natural deduction via small Kripke models: Subformula and separation properties.Peter Milne - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (2):175-227.
    Various natural deduction formulations of classical, minimal, intuitionist, and intermediate propositional and first-order logics are presented and investigated with respect to satisfaction of the separation and subformula properties. The technique employed is, for the most part, semantic, based on general versions of the Lindenbaum and Lindenbaum–Henkin constructions. Careful attention is paid to which properties of theories result in the presence of which rules of inference, and to restrictions on the sets of formulas to which the rules may be employed, (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
1 — 50 / 953