Results for 'Hechler’s theorem'

967 found
Order:
  1.  70
    Hechler's theorem for tall analytic p-ideals.Barnabás Farkas - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (2):729 - 736.
    We prove the following version of Hechler's classical theorem: For each partially ordered set (Q, ≤) with the property that every countable subset of Q has a strict upper bound in Q, there is a ccc forcing notion such that in the generic extension for each tall analytic P-ideal J (coded in the ground model) a cofinal subset of (J, ⊆*) is order isomorphic to (Q, ≤).
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  50
    Hechler’s theorem for the null ideal.Maxim R. Burke & Masaru Kada - 2004 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 43 (5):703-722.
    We prove the following theorem: For a partially ordered set Q such that every countable subset of Q has a strict upper bound, there is a forcing notion satisfying the countable chain condition such that, in the forcing extension, there is a basis of the null ideal of the real line which is order-isomorphic to Q with respect to set-inclusion. This is a variation of Hechler’s classical result in the theory of forcing. The corresponding theorem for the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  26
    A proof of Hechler's theorem on embedding \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document} $\aleph_1$\end{document}-directed sets cofinally into \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document} $(\omega^\omega,<^*)$\end{document}. [REVIEW]Maxim R. Burke - 1997 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 36 (6):399-403.
    We give a proof of Hechler's theorem that any \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document} $\aleph_1$\end{document}-directed partial order can be embedded via a ccc forcing notion cofinally into \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document} $\omega^\omega$\end{document} ordered by eventual dominance. The proof relies on the standard forcing relation rather than the variant introduced by Hechler.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  38
    More on simple forcing notions and forcings with ideals.M. Gitik & S. Shelah - 1993 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 59 (3):219-238.
    It is shown that cardinals below a real-valued measurable cardinal can be split into finitely many intervals so that the powers of cardinals from the same interval are the same. This generalizes a theorem of Prikry [9]. Suppose that the forcing with a κ-complete ideal over κ is isomorphic to the forcing of λ-Cohen or random reals. Then for some τ<κ, λτ2κ and λ2<κ implies that 2κ=2τ= cov. In particular, if 2κ<κ+ω, then λ=2κ. This answers a question from [3]. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  5.  8
    Gödel's Theorem in Focus.S. G. Shanker - 1987 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 182 (2):253-255.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  6. Bell’s Theorem: Two Neglected Solutions.Louis Vervoort - 2013 - Foundations of Physics 43 (6):769-791.
    Bell’s theorem admits several interpretations or ‘solutions’, the standard interpretation being ‘indeterminism’, a next one ‘nonlocality’. In this article two further solutions are investigated, termed here ‘superdeterminism’ and ‘supercorrelation’. The former is especially interesting for philosophical reasons, if only because it is always rejected on the basis of extra-physical arguments. The latter, supercorrelation, will be studied here by investigating model systems that can mimic it, namely spin lattices. It is shown that in these systems the Bell inequality can be (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  7.  57
    Goedel's theorem, the theory of everything, and the future of science and mathematics.Douglas S. Robertson - 2000 - Complexity 5 (5):22-27.
  8.  58
    Gleason's theorem has a constructive proof.Fred Richman - 2000 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 29 (4):425-431.
    Gleason's theorem for ������³ says that if f is a nonnegative function on the unit sphere with the property that f(x) + f(y) + f(z) is a fixed constant for each triple x, y, z of mutually orthogonal unit vectors, then f is a quadratic form. We examine the issues raised by discussions in this journal regarding the possibility of a constructive proof of Gleason's theorem in light of the recent publication of such a proof.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  9.  23
    Ehrenfest’s Theorem revisited.Henryk Stanisław Arodź - 2019 - Philosophical Problems in Science 66:73-94.
    Historically, Ehrenfest’s theorem is the first one which shows that classical physics can emerge from quantum physics as a kind of approximation. We recall the theorem in its original form, and we highlight its generalizations to the relativistic Dirac particle and to a particle with spin and izospin. We argue that apparent classicality of the macroscopic world can probably be explained within the framework of standard quantum mechanics.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10. Bell's theorem and the foundations of modern physics.F. Barone, A. O. Barut, E. Beltrametti, S. Bergia, R. A. Bertlmann, H. R. Brown, G. C. Ghirardi, D. M. Greenberger, D. Home & M. Jammer - 1991 - Foundations of Physics 21 (8).
  11.  90
    Bell’s Theorem and the Issue of Determinism and Indeterminism.Michael Esfeld - 2015 - Foundations of Physics 45 (5):471-482.
    The paper considers the claim that quantum theories with a deterministic dynamics of objects in ordinary space-time, such as Bohmian mechanics, contradict the assumption that the measurement settings can be freely chosen in the EPR experiment. That assumption is one of the premises of Bell’s theorem. I first argue that only a premise to the effect that what determines the choice of the measurement settings is independent of what determines the past state of the measured system is needed for (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  12.  48
    Ramsey's Theorem for Pairs and Provably Recursive Functions.Alexander Kreuzer & Ulrich Kohlenbach - 2009 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 50 (4):427-444.
    This paper addresses the strength of Ramsey's theorem for pairs ($RT^2_2$) over a weak base theory from the perspective of 'proof mining'. Let $RT^{2-}_2$ denote Ramsey's theorem for pairs where the coloring is given by an explicit term involving only numeric variables. We add this principle to a weak base theory that includes weak König's Lemma and a substantial amount of $\Sigma^0_1$-induction (enough to prove the totality of all primitive recursive functions but not of all primitive recursive functionals). (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  13. Löb's theorem as a limitation on mechanism.Michael Detlefsen - 2002 - Minds and Machines 12 (3):353-381.
    We argue that Löb's Theorem implies a limitation on mechanism. Specifically, we argue, via an application of a generalized version of Löb's Theorem, that any particular device known by an observer to be mechanical cannot be used as an epistemic authority (of a particular type) by that observer: either the belief-set of such an authority is not mechanizable or, if it is, there is no identifiable formal system of which the observer can know (or truly believe) it to (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14. Bell’s Theorem without Inequalities and without Unspeakable Information.Adán Cabello - 2005 - Foundations of Physics 35 (11):1927-1934.
    A proof of Bell’s theorem without inequalities is presented in which distant local setups do not need to be aligned, since the required perfect correlations are achieved for any local rotation of the local setups.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  65
    Ramsey's Theorem and Cone Avoidance.Damir D. Dzhafarov & Carl G. Jockusch - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (2):557-578.
    It was shown by Cholak, Jockusch, and Slaman that every computable 2-coloring of pairs admits an infinite low₂ homogeneous set H. We answer a question of the same authors by showing that H may be chosen to satisfy in addition $C\,\not \leqslant _T \,H$, where C is a given noncomputable set. This is shown by analyzing a new and simplified proof of Seetapun's cone avoidance theorem for Ramsey's theorem. We then extend the result to show that every computable (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  16.  29
    Hindman's theorem: An ultrafilter argument in second order arithmetic.Henry Towsner - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (1):353 - 360.
    Hindman's Theorem is a prototypical example of a combinatorial theorem with a proof that uses the topology of the ultrafilters. We show how the methods of this proof, including topological arguments about ultrafilters, can be translated into second order arithmetic.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17.  79
    Vaught's theorem on axiomatizability by a scheme.Albert Visser - 2012 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 18 (3):382-402.
    In his 1967 paper Vaught used an ingenious argument to show that every recursively enumerable first order theory that directly interprets the weak system VS of set theory is axiomatizable by a scheme. In this paper we establish a strengthening of Vaught's theorem by weakening the hypothesis of direct interpretability of VS to direct interpretability of the finitely axiomatized fragment VS2 of VS. This improvement significantly increases the scope of the original result, since VS is essentially undecidable, but VS2 (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  18.  30
    The Birth of Social Choice Theory from the Spirit of Mathematical Logic: Arrow’s Theorem in the Framework of Model Theory.Daniel Eckert & Frederik S. Herzberg - 2018 - Studia Logica 106 (5):893-911.
    Arrow’s axiomatic foundation of social choice theory can be understood as an application of Tarski’s methodology of the deductive sciences—which is closely related to the latter’s foundational contribution to model theory. In this note we show in a model-theoretic framework how Arrow’s use of von Neumann and Morgenstern’s concept of winning coalitions allows to exploit the algebraic structures involved in preference aggregation; this approach entails an alternative indirect ultrafilter proof for Arrow’s dictatorship result. This link also connects Arrow’s seminal result (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  22
    Haag’s Theorem, Apparent Inconsistency, and the Empirical Adequacy of Quantum Field Theory.Michael E. Miller - 2018 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 69 (3):801-820.
    Haag’s theorem has been interpreted as establishing that quantum field theory cannot consistently represent interacting fields. Earman and Fraser have clarified how it is possible to give mathematically consistent calculations in scattering theory despite the theorem. However, their analysis does not fully address the worry raised by the result. In particular, I argue that their approach fails to be a complete explanation of why Haag’s theorem does not undermine claims about the empirical adequacy of particular quantum field (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  20.  24
    Fermi liquid behavior and Luttinger's theorem close to a diverging scattering length.S. Gaudio, J. Jackiewicz & K. S. Bedell - 2009 - Philosophical Magazine 89 (22-24):1823-1830.
  21.  81
    Bell’s Theorem, Realism, and Locality.Peter Lewis - 2019 - In Alberto Cordero (ed.), Philosophers Look at Quantum Mechanics. Springer Verlag.
    According to a recent paper by Tim Maudlin, Bell’s theorem has nothing to tell us about realism or the descriptive completeness of quantum mechanics. What it shows is that quantum mechanics is non-local, no more and no less. What I intend to do in this paper is to challenge Maudlin’s assertion about the import of Bell’s proof. There is much that I agree with in the paper; in particular, it does us the valuable service of demonstrating that Einstein’s objections (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22.  27
    A Symmetric Form of Godel's Theorem.S. C. Kleene - 1951 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 16 (2):147-147.
  23.  22
    Cantor’s Theorem May Fail for Finitary Partitions.Guozhen Shen - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-18.
    A partition is finitary if all its members are finite. For a set A, $\mathscr {B}(A)$ denotes the set of all finitary partitions of A. It is shown consistent with $\mathsf {ZF}$ (without the axiom of choice) that there exist an infinite set A and a surjection from A onto $\mathscr {B}(A)$. On the other hand, we prove in $\mathsf {ZF}$ some theorems concerning $\mathscr {B}(A)$ for infinite sets A, among which are the following: (1) If there is a finitary (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24. Bell’s Theorem, Quantum Probabilities, and Superdeterminism.Eddy Keming Chen - 2022 - In Eleanor Knox & Alastair Wilson (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Physics. London, UK: Routledge.
    In this short survey article, I discuss Bell’s theorem and some strategies that attempt to avoid the conclusion of non-locality. I focus on two that intersect with the philosophy of probability: (1) quantum probabilities and (2) superdeterminism. The issues they raised not only apply to a wide class of no-go theorems about quantum mechanics but are also of general philosophical interest.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  25.  86
    Arrow’s theorem and theory choice.Davide Rizza - 2014 - Synthese 191 (8):1847-1856.
    In a recent paper (Okasha, Mind 120:83–115, 2011), Samir Okasha uses Arrow’s theorem to raise a challenge for the rationality of theory choice. He argues that, as soon as one accepts the plausibility of the assumptions leading to Arrow’s theorem, one is compelled to conclude that there are no adequate theory choice algorithms. Okasha offers a partial way out of this predicament by diagnosing the source of Arrow’s theorem and using his diagnosis to deploy an approach that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  26. Arrow's theorem in judgment aggregation.Franz Dietrich & Christian List - 2007 - Social Choice and Welfare 29 (1):19-33.
    In response to recent work on the aggregation of individual judgments on logically connected propositions into collective judgments, it is often asked whether judgment aggregation is a special case of Arrowian preference aggregation. We argue for the converse claim. After proving two impossibility theorems on judgment aggregation (using "systematicity" and "independence" conditions, respectively), we construct an embedding of preference aggregation into judgment aggregation and prove Arrow’s theorem (stated for strict preferences) as a corollary of our second result. Although we (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  27.  40
    On consistent subsets of large sets of satisfiable sentences.Stephen H. Hechler - 2001 - Studia Logica 69 (3):339-349.
    We extend some results of Adam Kolany to show that large sets of satisfiable sentences generally contain equally large subsets of mutually consistent sentences. In particular, this is always true for sets of uncountable cofinality, and remains true for sets of denumerable cofinality if we put appropriate bounding conditions on the sentences. The results apply to both the propositional and the predicate calculus. To obtain these results, we use delta sets for regular cardinals, and, for singular cardinals, a generalization of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Bell's theorem and Bayes' theorem.A. J. M. Garrett - 1990 - Foundations of Physics 20 (12):1475-1512.
    Bell's theorem is expounded as an analysis in Bayesian probabilistic inference. Assume that the result of a spin measurement on a spin-1/2 particle is governed by a variable internal to the particle (local, “hidden”), and examine pairs of particles having zero combined angular momentum so that their internal variables are correlated: knowing something about the internal variable of one tells us something about that of the other. By measuring the spin of one particle, we infer something about its internal (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29. Arrow's Theorem.Michael Morreau - 2014 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: N/A.
    Kenneth Arrow’s “impossibility” theorem—or “general possibility” theorem, as he called it—answers a very basic question in the theory of collective decision-making. Say there are some alternatives to choose among. They could be policies, public projects, candidates in an election, distributions of income and labour requirements among the members of a society, or just about anything else. There are some people whose preferences will inform this choice, and the question is: which procedures are there for deriving, from what is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  30. Arrow's theorem, ultrafilters, and reverse mathematics.Benedict Eastaugh - forthcoming - Review of Symbolic Logic.
    This paper initiates the reverse mathematics of social choice theory, studying Arrow's impossibility theorem and related results including Fishburn's possibility theorem and the Kirman–Sondermann theorem within the framework of reverse mathematics. We formalise fundamental notions of social choice theory in second-order arithmetic, yielding a definition of countable society which is tractable in RCA0. We then show that the Kirman–Sondermann analysis of social welfare functions can be carried out in RCA0. This approach yields a proof of Arrow's (...) in RCA0, and thus in PRA, since Arrow's theorem can be formalised as a Π01 sentence. Finally we show that Fishburn's possibility theorem for countable societies is equivalent to ACA0 over RCA0. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  33
    Godel's theorem in retrospect.Martin Tabakov - 1984 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 13 (3):132-134.
    G¨odel’s a theorem concerns an arithmetical statement and the truth of this statement does not depend on self-reference; nevertheless its interpretation is of tremendous interest. G¨odel’s theorem allows one to conclude that formal arithmetic is not axiomatizable. But there is another very interesting logico-philosophical result: the possibility of a statement to exist such that it is improvable in the object-theory and at the same time its truth is provable in the metatheory. It seems that in the real history (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  28
    Łoś's theorem and the axiom of choice.Eleftherios Tachtsis - 2019 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 65 (3):280-292.
    In set theory without the Axiom of Choice (), we investigate the problem of the placement of Łoś's Theorem () in the hierarchy of weak choice principles, and answer several open questions from the book Consequences of the Axiom of Choice by Howard and Rubin, as well as an open question by Brunner. We prove a number of results summarised in § 3.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Szemerédi’s theorem: An exploration of impurity, explanation, and content.Patrick J. Ryan - 2023 - Review of Symbolic Logic 16 (3):700-739.
    In this paper I argue for an association between impurity and explanatory power in contemporary mathematics. This proposal is defended against the ancient and influential idea that purity and explanation go hand-in-hand (Aristotle, Bolzano) and recent suggestions that purity/impurity ascriptions and explanatory power are more or less distinct (Section 1). This is done by analyzing a central and deep result of additive number theory, Szemerédi’s theorem, and various of its proofs (Section 2). In particular, I focus upon the radically (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34.  12
    An extension of May's Theorem to three alternatives: axiomatizing Minimax voting.Wesley H. Holliday & Eric Pacuit - manuscript
    May's Theorem [K. O. May, Econometrica 20 (1952) 680-684] characterizes majority voting on two alternatives as the unique preferential voting method satisfying several simple axioms. Here we show that by adding some desirable axioms to May's axioms, we can uniquely determine how to vote on three alternatives. In particular, we add two axioms stating that the voting method should mitigate spoiler effects and avoid the so-called strong no show paradox. We prove a theorem stating that any preferential voting (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Bell's Theorem And The Counterfactual Definition Of Locality.Osvaldo Pessoa Jr - 2010 - Manuscrito 33 (1):351-363.
    This paper proposes a solution to the problem of non-locality associated with Bell’s theorem, within the counterfactual approach to the problem. Our proposal is that a counterfactual definition of locality can be maintained, if a subsidiary hypothesis be rejected, “locality involving two counterfactuals”. This amounts to the acceptance of locality in the actual world, and a denial that locality is always valid in counterfactual worlds. This also introduces a metaphysical asymmetry between the factual and counterfactual worlds. This distinction is (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  32
    Dugundji’s Theorem Revisited.Marcelo E. Coniglio & Newton M. Peron - 2014 - Logica Universalis 8 (3-4):407-422.
    In 1940 Dugundji proved that no system between S1 and S5 can be characterized by finite matrices. Dugundji’s result forced the development of alternative semantics, in particular Kripke’s relational semantics. The success of this semantics allowed the creation of a huge family of modal systems. With few adaptations, this semantics can characterize almost the totality of the modal systems developed in the last five decades. This semantics however has some limits. Two results of incompleteness showed that not every modal logic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  37. Tharp’s theorems of metaphysics and the notion of necessary truth.Jordan Stein - 2017 - Synthese 194 (4).
    Leslie Tharp proves three theorems concerning epistemic and metaphysical modality for conventional modal predicate logic: every truth is a priori equivalent to a necessary truth, every truth is necessarily equivalent to an a priori truth, and every truth is a priori equivalent to a contingent truth. Lloyd Humberstone has shown that these theorems also hold in the modal system Actuality Modal Logic, the logic that results from the addition of the actuality operator to conventional modal logic. We show that Tharp’s (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  23
    Laue's Theorem Revisited: Energy-Momentum Tensors, Symmetries, and the Habitat of Globally Conserved Quantities.Domenico Giulini - 2018 - International Journal of Geometric Methods in Modern Physics 15 (10).
    The energy-momentum tensor for a particular matter component summarises its local energy-momentum distribution in terms of densities and current densities. We re-investigate under what conditions these local distributions can be integrated to meaningful global quantities. This leads us directly to a classic theorem by Max von Laue concerning integrals of components of the energy-momentum tensor, whose statement and proof we recall. In the first half of this paper we do this within the realm of Special Relativity and in the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  9
    (1 other version)Bell's Theorem without Inequalities.Daniel M. Greenberger, Michael A. Horne, Abner Shimony & Anton Zeilenger - 1990 - American Journal of Physics 58 (12):1131--1143.
  40.  62
    Tarski's theorem and liar-like paradoxes.Ming Hsiung - 2014 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 22 (1):24-38.
    Tarski's theorem essentially says that the Liar paradox is paradoxical in the minimal reflexive frame. We generalise this result to the Liar-like paradox $\lambda^\alpha$ for all ordinal $\alpha\geq 1$. The main result is that for any positive integer $n = 2^i(2j+1)$, the paradox $\lambda^n$ is paradoxical in a frame iff this frame contains at least a cycle the depth of which is not divisible by $2^{i+1}$; and for any ordinal $\alpha \geq \omega$, the paradox $\lambda^\alpha$ is paradoxical in a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  41. Herbrand's Theorem for a Modal Logic.Melvin Fitting - unknown
    Herbrand’s theorem is a central fact about classical logic, [9, 10]. It provides a constructive method for associating, with each first-order formula X, a sequence of formulas X1, X2, X3, . . . , so that X has a first-order proof if and only if some Xi is a tautology. Herbrand’s theorem serves as a constructive alternative to..
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  61
    von Neumann’s Theorem Revisited.Pablo Acuña - 2021 - Foundations of Physics 51 (3):1-29.
    According to a popular narrative, in 1932 von Neumann introduced a theorem that intended to be a proof of the impossibility of hidden variables in quantum mechanics. However, the narrative goes, Bell later spotted a flaw that allegedly shows its irrelevance. Bell’s widely accepted criticism has been challenged by Bub and Dieks: they claim that the proof shows that viable hidden variables theories cannot be theories in Hilbert space. Bub’s and Dieks’ reassessment has been in turn challenged by Mermin (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  43. Bell's Theorem Begs the Question.Joy Christian - manuscript
    I demonstrate that Bell's theorem is based on circular reasoning and thus a fundamentally flawed argument. It unjustifiably assumes the additivity of expectation values for dispersion-free states of contextual hidden variable theories for non-commuting observables involved in Bell-test experiments, which is tautologous to assuming the bounds of ±2 on the Bell-CHSH sum of expectation values. Its premises thus assume in a different guise the bounds of ±2 it sets out to prove. Once this oversight is ameliorated from Bell's argument (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  32
    Godel's Theorem in Focus.Stuart Shanker (ed.) - 1987 - Routledge.
    A layman's guide to the mechanics of Gödel's proof together with a lucid discussion of the issues which it raises. Includes an essay discussing the significance of Gödel's work in the light of Wittgenstein's criticisms.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  45.  81
    (1 other version)Godel's theorem and mechanism.David Coder - 1969 - Philosophy 44 (September):234-7.
    In “Minds, Machines, and Gödel”, J. R. Lucas claims that Goedel's incompleteness theorem constitutes a proof “that Mechanism is false, that is, that minds cannot be explained as machines”. He claims further that “if the proof of the falsity of mechanism is valid, it is of the greatest consequence for the whole of philosophy”. It seems to me that both of these claims are exaggerated. It is true that no minds can be explained as machines. But it is not (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  46.  41
    Arrow's Theorem with a fixed feasible alternative.John A. Weymark, Aanund Hylland & Allan F. Gibbard - unknown
    Arrow's Theorem, in its social choice function formulation, assumes that all nonempty finite subsets of the universal set of alternatives is potentially a feasible set. We demonstrate that the axioms in Arrow's Theorem, with weak Pareto strengthened to strong Pareto, are consistent if it is assumed that there is a prespecified alternative which is in every feasible set. We further show that if the collection of feasible sets consists of all subsets of alternatives containing a prespecified list of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  15
    Another extension of Van de Wiele's theorem.Robert S. Lubarsky - 1988 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 38 (3):301-306.
  48.  91
    Montague’s Theorem and Modal Logic.Johannes Stern - 2014 - Erkenntnis 79 (3):551-570.
    In the present piece we defend predicate approaches to modality, that is approaches that conceive of modal notions as predicates applicable to names of sentences or propositions, against the challenges raised by Montague’s theorem. Montague’s theorem is often taken to show that the most intuitive modal principles lead to paradox if we conceive of the modal notion as a predicate. Following Schweizer (J Philos Logic 21:1–31, 1992) and others we show this interpretation of Montague’s theorem to be (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49.  74
    Ramsey’s theorem and König’s Lemma.T. E. Forster & J. K. Truss - 2007 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 46 (1):37-42.
    We consider the relation between versions of Ramsey’s Theorem and König’s Infinity Lemma, in the absence of the axiom of choice.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  50. Making Sense of Bell’s Theorem and Quantum Nonlocality.Stephen Boughn - 2017 - Foundations of Physics 47 (5):640-657.
    Bell’s theorem has fascinated physicists and philosophers since his 1964 paper, which was written in response to the 1935 paper of Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen. Bell’s theorem and its many extensions have led to the claim that quantum mechanics and by inference nature herself are nonlocal in the sense that a measurement on a system by an observer at one location has an immediate effect on a distant entangled system. Einstein was repulsed by such “spooky action at a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
1 — 50 / 967