Results for 'Daniel C. Bryant'

956 found
Order:
  1.  22
    Telling tales out of school — Portrayals of the medical student experience by physician-novelists.Daniel C. Bryant - 1996 - Journal of Medical Humanities 17 (4):237-254.
    Changes in medical and medical ethics education are being considered with little attention to the experience of the medical students involved. This study attempts to characterize and highlight certain aspects of that experience from a literary perspective. After a brief review of the history of traditional academic studies in the field, eight novels, written by physician-writers and featuring medical student protagonists, are analyzed. Several common themes of the student experience are identified in the novels, and are contrasted with themes found (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  50
    Daniel C. Dennett Autobiography Part 3.Daniel C. Dennett - 2008 - Philosophy Now 70:24-25.
  3. (1 other version)Brainstorms.Daniel C. Dennett - 1978 - MIT Press.
    This collection of 17 essays by the author offers a comprehensive theory of mind, encompassing traditional issues of consciousness and free will.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1094 citations  
  4. How to study human consciousness empirically or nothing comes to mind.Daniel C. Dennett - 1982 - Synthese 53 (2):159-80.
  5. Why You Can’t Make a Computer that Feels Pain.Daniel C. Dennett - 1978 - Synthese 38 (3):415-449.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  6. Philosophy as naive anthropology: Comment on Bennett and Hacker.Daniel C. Dennett - 2007 - In M. Bennett, D. C. Dennett, P. M. S. Hacker & J. R. & Searle (eds.), Neuroscience and Philosophy: Brain, Mind, and Language. Columbia University Press.
    Bennett and Hacker’s _Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience_ (Blackwell, 2003), a collaboration between a philosopher (Hacker) and a neuroscientist (Bennett), is an ambitious attempt to reformulate the research agenda of cognitive neuroscience by demonstrating that cognitive scientists and other theorists, myself among them, have been bewitching each other by misusing language in a systematically “incoherent” and conceptually “confused” way. In both style and substance, the book harks back to Oxford in the early 1960's, when Ordinary Language Philosophy ruled, and Ryle and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  7. Consciousness Explained.Daniel C. Dennett - 1991 - Penguin Books.
    Little, Brown, 1992 Review by Glenn Branch on Jul 5th 1999 Volume: 3, Number: 27.
  8. Kinds of Mind.Daniel C. Dennett - 2000 - Mind 109 (436):883-890.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   108 citations  
  9. Practical intelligence and the virtues.Daniel C. Russell - 2009 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This book develops an Aristotelian account of the virtue of practical intelligence or "phronesis"--an excellence of deliberating and making choices--which ...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   119 citations  
  10. Brain writing and mind reading.Daniel C. Dennett - 1975 - Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 7:403-15.
  11. (3 other versions)Content and Consciousness.Daniel C. Dennett - 1968 - New York: Routledge.
  12. Escape from the cartesian theater. Reply to commentaries on Time and the Observer: The Where and When of Consciousness in the Brain.Daniel C. Dennett & Marcel Kinsbourne - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):183-247.
    Damasio remarks, it "informs virtually all research on mind and brain, explicitly or implicitly." Indeed, serial information processing models generally run this risk (Kinsbourne, 1985). The commentaries provide a wealth of confirming instances of the seductive power of this idea. Our sternest critics Block, Farah, Libet, and Treisman) adopt fairly standard Cartesian positions; more interesting are those commentators who take themselves to be mainly in agreement with us, but who express reservations or offer support with arguments that betray a continuing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   272 citations  
  13. Mechanism and responsibility.Daniel C. Dennett - 1973 - In Ted Honderich (ed.), Essays on Freedom of Action. Boston,: Routledge. pp. 157--84.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  14. Embodiment and self-ownership: Daniel C. Russell.Daniel C. Russell - 2010 - Social Philosophy and Policy 27 (1):135-167.
    Many libertarians believe that self-ownership is a separate matter from ownership of extra-personal property. “No-proviso” libertarians hold that property ownership should be free of any “fair share” constraints, on the grounds that the inability of the very poor to control property leaves their self-ownership intact. By contrast, left-libertarians hold that while no one need compensate others for owning himself, still property owners must compensate others for owning extra-personal property. What would a “self” have to be for these claims to be (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15. Kinds of Minds.Daniel C. Dennett - 1996 - Basic Books.
  16.  17
    Archimedes.Daniel C. Lewis & E. J. Dijksterhuis - 1958 - American Journal of Philology 79 (2):221.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  17. Motivated thinking.Daniel C. Molden & E. Tory Higgins - 2005 - In K. Holyoak & B. Morrison (eds.), The Cambridge handbook of thinking and reasoning. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. pp. 295--317.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  18. Are we explaining consciousness yet?Daniel C. Dennett - 2001 - Cognition 79 (1):221-37.
    Theorists are converging from quite different quarters on a version of the global neuronal workspace model of consciousness, but there are residual confusions to be dissolved. In particular, theorists must resist the temptation to see global accessibility as the cause of consciousness (as if consciousness were some other, further condition); rather, it is consciousness. A useful metaphor for keeping this elusive idea in focus is that consciousness is rather like fame in the brain. It is not a privileged medium of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   121 citations  
  19. Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind.Daniel C. Dennett - 1988 - Journal of Philosophy 85 (7):384-389.
  20.  70
    Anosognosia in Alzheimer’s disease – The petrified self.Daniel C. Mograbi, Richard G. Brown & Robin G. Morris - 2009 - Consciousness and Cognition 18 (4):989-1003.
    This paper reviews the literature concerning the neural correlates of the self, the relationship between self and memory and the profile of memory impairments in Alzheimer’s disease and explores the relationship between the preservation of the self and anosognosia in this condition. It concludes that a potential explanation for anosognosia in AD is a lack of updating of personal information due to the memory impairments characteristic of this disease. We put forward the hypothesis that anosognosia is due in part to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  21. Beyond belief.Daniel C. Dennett - 1982 - In Andrew Woodfield (ed.), Thought And Object: Essays On Intentionality. New York: Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  22. Mother nature versus the walking encyclopedia.Daniel C. Dennett - 1991 - In William Ramsey, Stephen P. Stich & D. M. Rumelhart (eds.), Philosophy and Connectionist Theory. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum. pp. 21--30.
    In 1982, Feldman and Ballard published "Connectionist models and their properties" in Cognitive Science , helping to focus attention on a family of similarly inspired research strategies just then under way, by giving the family a name: "connectionism." Now, seven years later, the connectionist nation has swelled to include such subfamilies as "PDP" and "neural net models." Since the ideological foes of connectionism are keen to wipe it out in one fell swoop aimed at its "essence", it is worth noting (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  23. Cognitive penetration and the cognition–perception interface.Daniel C. Burnston - 2017 - Synthese 194 (9):3645-3668.
    I argue that discussions of cognitive penetration have been insufficiently clear about what distinguishes perception and cognition, and what kind of relationship between the two is supposed to be at stake in the debate. A strong reading, which is compatible with many characterizations of penetration, posits a highly specific and directed influence on perception. According to this view, which I call the “internal effect view” a cognitive state penetrates a perceptual process if the presence of the cognitive state causes a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  24. Toward a cognitive theory of consciousness.Daniel C. Dennett - 1978 - Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 9.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  25. The case for rorts.Daniel C. Dennett - 2000 - In Robert Brandom (ed.), Rorty and His Critics. Malden, Mass.: Wiley-Blackwell.
    In the late 1960s, I created a joke dictionary of philosophers' names that circulated in samizdat form, picking up new entries as it went. The first few editions were on Ditto masters, in those pre-photocopy days. The 7th edition, entitled The Philosophical Lexicon , was the first properly copyrighted version, published for the benefit of the American Philosophical Association in 1978, and the 8th edition (brought out in 1987), is still available from the APA. I continue to receive submissions of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  26.  81
    Happiness for humans.Daniel C. Russell - 2012 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    1. Happiness, then and now -- Happiness, eudaimonia, and practical reasoning -- Happiness as eudaimonia -- Happiness and virtuous activity -- New directions from old debates -- 2. Happiness then: the sufficiency debate -- Aristotle's case against the sufficiency thesis -- 3. Happiness now: rethinking the self -- Socrates' case for the sufficiency thesis -- Epictetus and the stoic self -- The Stoics' case for the sufficiency thesis -- The embodied conception of the self -- The embodied conception and psychological (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  27. Real patterns.Daniel C. Dennett - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy 88 (1):27-51.
    Are there really beliefs? Or are we learning (from neuroscience and psychology, presumably) that, strictly speaking, beliefs are figments of our imagination, items in a superceded ontology? Philosophers generally regard such ontological questions as admitting just two possible answers: either beliefs exist or they don't. There is no such state as quasi-existence; there are no stable doctrines of semi-realism. Beliefs must either be vindicated along with the viruses or banished along with the banshees. A bracing conviction prevails, then, to the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   643 citations  
  28. Artificial Life as Philosophy.Daniel C. Dennett - unknown
    There are two likely paths for philosophers to follow in their encounters with Artificial Life: they can see it as a new way of doing philosophy, or simply as a new object worthy of philosophical attention using traditional methods. Is Artificial Life best seen as a new philosophical method or a new phenomenon? There is a case to be made for each alternative, but I urge philosophers to take the leap and consider the first to be the more important and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  29. Facing backwards on the problem of consciousness.Daniel C. Dennett - 1996 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 3 (1):4-6.
    The strategy of divide and conquer is usually an excellent one, but it all depends on how you do the carving. Chalmer's attempt to sort the "easy" problems of consciousness from the "really hard" problem is not, I think, a useful contribution to research, but a major misdirector of attention, an illusion-generator. How could this be? Let me describe two somewhat similar strategic proposals, and compare them to Chalmers' recommendation.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  30. Atheism and evolution.Daniel C. Dennett - 2006 - In Michael Martin (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Atheism. Cambridge University Press. pp. 135--148.
  31. Are Dreams Experiences?Daniel C. Dennett - 1976 - Philosophical Review 85 (2):151.
  32.  96
    Interface problems in the explanation of action.Daniel C. Burnston - 2017 - Philosophical Explorations 20 (2):242-258.
    When doing mental ontology, we must ask how to individuate distinct categories of mental states, and then, given that individuation, ask how states from distinct categories interact. One promising proposal for how to individuate cognitive from sensorimotor states is in terms of their representational form. On these views, cognitive representations are propositional in structure, while sensorimotor representations have an internal structure that maps to the perceptual and kinematic dimensions involved in an action context. This way of thinking has resulted in (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  33. Beliefs about beliefs [P&W, SR&B].Daniel C. Dennett - 1978 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1 (4):568-570.
  34. Intentional systems.Daniel C. Dennett - 1971 - Journal of Philosophy 68 (February):87-106.
  35. (1 other version)How to protect human dignity from science.Daniel C. Dennett - 2008 - In Adam Schulman (ed.), Human dignity and bioethics: essays commissioned by the President's Council on Bioethics. Washington, D.C.: [President's Council on Bioethics.
    for the Bioethics Commission, August 16, 2006.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  36. The abilities of men and machines.Daniel C. Dennett - 1978 - In Brainstorms. MIT Press.
  37. That “Ought” Does Not Imply “Right”: Why It Matters for Virtue Ethics.Daniel C. Russell - 2008 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 46 (2):299-315.
    Virtue ethicists sometimes say that a right action is what a virtuous person would do, characteristically, in the circumstances. But some have objected recently that right action cannot be defined as what a virtuous person would do in the circumstances because there are circumstances in which a right action is possible but in which no virtuous person would be found. This objection moves from the premise that a given person ought to do an action that no virtuous person would do, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  38. Why not the whole iguana?Daniel C. Dennett - 1978 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1 (1):103-104.
  39. Making sense of ourselves.Daniel C. Dennett - 1981 - Philosophical Topics 12 (1):63-81.
  40.  50
    Passing the buck to biology.Daniel C. Dennett - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):19-19.
  41. Conditions of personhood.Daniel C. Dennett - 1976 - In Amélie Rorty (ed.), The Identities of Persons. University of California Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   193 citations  
  42. (2 other versions)Elbow Room: The Varieties of Free Will Worth Wanting.Daniel C. Dennett - 1986 - Mind 95 (377):127-129.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   183 citations  
  43.  53
    Revolution, no! Reform, si!Daniel C. Dennett - 1998 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (5):636-637.
    Van Gelder's hard line against representations is not supported or supportable, and his soft line in favor of dynamical systems thinking as a supplement to representational models of cognition is good advice, but not revolutionary, as he seems to think.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  44. (1 other version)Skinner skinned.Daniel C. Dennett - 1978 - In Daniel Clement Dennett (ed.), Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Bradford Books. pp. 53--70.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  45.  55
    Brief non-symbolic, approximate number practice enhances subsequent exact symbolic arithmetic in children.Daniel C. Hyde, Saeeda Khanum & Elizabeth S. Spelke - 2014 - Cognition 131 (1):92-107.
  46. Intentional systems in cognitive ethology: The 'panglossian paradigm' defended.Daniel C. Dennett - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):343-90.
    Ethologists and others studying animal behavior in a spirit are in need of a descriptive language and method that are neither anachronistically bound by behaviorist scruples nor prematurely committed to particular Just such an interim descriptive method can be found in intentional system theory. The use of intentional system theory is illustrated with the case of the apparently communicative behavior of vervet monkeys. A way of using the theory to generate data - including usable, testable data - is sketched. The (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   599 citations  
  47.  88
    A contextualist approach to functional localization in the brain.Daniel C. Burnston - 2016 - Biology and Philosophy 31 (4):527-550.
    Functional localization has historically been one of the primary goals of neuroscience. There is still debate, however, about whether it is possible, and if so what kind of theories succeed at localization. I argue for a contextualist approach to localization. Most theorists assume that widespread contextual variability in function is fundamentally incompatible with functional decomposition in the brain, because contextualist accounts will fail to be generalizable and projectable. I argue that this assumption is misplaced. A properly articulated contextualism can ground (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  48. Time and the observer: The where and when of consciousness in the brain.Daniel C. Dennett & Marcel Kinsbourne - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):183-201.
    _Behavioral and Brain Sciences_ , 15, 183-247, 1992. Reprinted in _The Philosopher's Annual_ , Grim, Mar and Williams, eds., vol. XV-1992, 1994, pp. 23-68; Noel Sheehy and Tony Chapman, eds., _Cognitive Science_ , Vol. I, Elgar, 1995, pp.210-274.
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   378 citations  
  49.  97
    Anti-Intellectualism for the Learning and Employment of Skill.Daniel C. Burnston - 2020 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 12 (3):507-526.
    I draw on empirical results from perceptual and motor learning to argue for an anti-intellectualist position on skill. Anti-intellectualists claim that skill or know-how is non-propositional. Recent proponents of the view have stressed the flexible but fine-grained nature of skilled control as supporting their position. However, they have left the nature of the mental representations underlying such control undertheorized. This leaves open several possible strategies for the intellectualist, particularly with regard to skill learning. Propositional knowledge may structure the inputs to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50.  74
    Granny versus mother nature - no contest.Daniel C. Dennett - 1996 - Mind and Language 11 (3):263-269.
    Fodor's doubts about neo‐Darwinism are driven by something other than familiarity with evolutionary biology, so they should be set aside. His claim that a theory of intentionality cannot be constructed on an evolutionary foundation because there is no representation in the process of natural selection reveals that he has been blind to the chief beauty of Darwin's vision: its capacity to explain not just how the living can come, gradually, from the non‐living, but also how meaning can come, by incremental (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
1 — 50 / 956