Results for ' sexualité, utopie, homosexualité, médecine, science, sexologie, Hirschfeld Magnus'

945 found
Order:
  1.  45
    La Ligue mondiale pour la réforme sexuelle : La science au service de l’émancipation sexuelle?Florence Tamagne - 2005 - Clio 22:101-121.
    Fondée en 1928 par Magnus Hirschfeld, la Ligue Mondiale pour la Réforme Sexuelle entendait rassembler médecins et « profanes » dans le but de diffuser dans l’opinion publique les acquis de la nouvelle « science sexuelle » et d’influencer les gouvernements dans un sens progressiste, sur des questions aussi variées que le contrôle des naissances, le mariage et le divorce, l’homosexualité, la prostitution ou l’eugénisme. Très vite pourtant, elle fut déchirée entre des tendances contradictoires, et dans l’incapacité de (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  2. The Construction of Sexual Knowledge: The Dictionnaire des sciences médicales (1812-1822). [REVIEW]Clyde Plumauzille - 2010 - Clio 31:111-132.
    Au XVIIIe siècle, les médecins modernes tentent d’appréhender et de fixer le plaisir sexuel dans l’ordre de la Nature à une époque charnière où les bouleversements révolutionnaires entraînent dans leur sillage une forte politisation et une redéfinition du sexuel. Les savoirs médicaux qui entendent alors être un instrument essentiel du diagnostic social, participent pleinement à cette dynamique et constituent des lieux d’investigation incontournables pour comprendre les multiples façons dont s’élaborent la sexualité et les « lois de son économie libidinale ». (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  30
    Magnus Hirschfeld, his biographies and the possibilities and boundaries of 'biography' as 'doing history'.Toni Brennan & Peter Hegarty - 2009 - History of the Human Sciences 22 (5):24-46.
    This article considers the two major biographies of sexologist Magnus Hirschfeld, MD (1868—1935), an early campaigner for ‘gay rights’ avant la lettre. Like him, his first biographer Charlotte Wolff (1897—1986) was a Jewish doctor who lived and worked in Weimar Republic Berlin and fled Germany when the Nazi regime came to power. When researching Hirschfeld’s biography (published in English in 1986) Wolff met a librarian and gay activist, Manfred Herzer, who would eventually be a cofounder of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  3
    Racism.Magnus Hirschfeld & Eden Paul - 1938 - V. Gollancz.
    Looks at European ideas about race and the alleged superiority of certain peoples, especially in Germany.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Per scientiam ad justitiam: Magnus Hirschfeld and the sexual politics of innate homosexuality.James D. Steakley - 1997 - In Vernon A. Rosario (ed.), Science and Homosexualities. New York: Routledge. pp. 133--54.
  6.  62
    Sylvie Chaperon, Les origines de la sexologie, 1850-1900.Nicole Edelman - 2010 - Clio 31:310-312.
    Le mot sexologie, la science de la sexualité, apparaît en France au début des années 1910. Il marque, de la part de ceux qui en usent, la volonté à la fois de lutter pour l’égalité des droits en matière de pratiques sexuelles et de rompre avec le savoir médical sur la sexualité. Dans son livre Les origines de la sexologie, 1850-1900, Sylvie Chaperon explore ce champ nouveau de l’histoire et se propose de démêler les fils qui, en ce domaine, enchevêtrent (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  61
    Fourier, le Nouveau Monde Amoureux et mai 1968. Politique des passions, égalité des sexes et science sociale.Michel Bozon - 2005 - Clio 22:123-149.
    Le Nouveau Monde Amoureux n’a été publié qu’en 1967, un siècle et demi après avoir été écrit par Fourier. Fourier y analyse la société de son temps, critiquant sévèrement le mariage monogame et l’asservissement des femmes. Il élabore un autre modèle théorique et politique de société, l’Harmonie, fondée sur la disparition du mariage monogame, la multiplication systématique des relations amoureuses de toutes natures, et une égalité absolue entre les sexes. A sa publication, l’ouvrage de Fourier est reçu avec enthousiasme, comme (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Inductions, Red Herrings, and the Best Explanation for the Mixed Record of Science.P. D. Magnus - 2010 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 61 (4):803-819.
    Kyle Stanford has recently claimed to offer a new challenge to scientific realism. Taking his inspiration from the familiar Pessimistic Induction (PI), Stanford proposes a New Induction (NI). Contra Anjan Chakravartty’s suggestion that the NI is a ‘red herring’, I argue that it reveals something deep and important about science. The Problem of Unconceived Alternatives, which lies at the heart of the NI, yields a richer anti-realism than the PI. It explains why science falls short when it falls short, and (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  9. The scope of inductive risk.P. D. Magnus - 2022 - Metaphilosophy 53 (1):17-24.
    The Argument from Inductive Risk (AIR) is taken to show that values are inevitably involved in making judgements or forming beliefs. After reviewing this conclusion, I pose cases which are prima facie counterexamples: the unreflective application of conventions, use of black-boxed instruments, reliance on opaque algorithms, and unskilled observation reports. These cases are counterexamples to the AIR posed in ethical terms as a matter of personal values. Nevertheless, it need not be understood in those terms. The values which load a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10. Science, Values, and the Priority of Evidence.P. D. Magnus - 2018 - Logos and Episteme 9 (4):413-431.
    It is now commonly held that values play a role in scientific judgment, but many arguments for that conclusion are limited. First, many arguments do not show that values are, strictly speaking, indispensable. The role of values could in principle be filled by a random or arbitrary decision. Second, many arguments concern scientific theories and concepts which have obvious practical consequences, thus suggesting or at least leaving open the possibility that abstruse sciences without such a connection could be value-free. Third, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  11. Underdetermination and the Claims of Science.P. D. Magnus - 2003 - Dissertation, University of California, San Diego
    The underdetermination of theory by evidence is supposed to be a reason to rethink science. It is not. Many authors claim that underdetermination has momentous consequences for the status of scientific claims, but such claims are hidden in an umbra of obscurity and a penumbra of equivocation. So many various phenomena pass for `underdetermination' that it's tempting to think that it is no unified phenomenon at all, so I begin by providing a framework within which all these worries can be (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  12. Distributed Cognition and the Task of Science.P. D. Magnus - 2007 - Social Studies of Science 37 (2):297--310.
    This paper gives a characterization of distributed cognition (d-cog) and explores ways that the framework might be applied in studies of science. I argue that a system can only be given a d-cog description if it is thought of as performing a task. Turning our attention to science, we can try to give a global d-cog account of science or local d-cog accounts of particular scientific projects. Several accounts of science can be seen as global d-cog accounts: Robert Merton's sociology (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  13. Science and Rationality for One and All.P. D. Magnus - 2014 - Ergo 1 (5):129-138.
    It seems obvious that a community of one thousand scientists working together to make discoveries and solve puzzles should arrange itself differently than would one thousand scientist-hermits working independently. Because of limited time, resources, and attention, an independent scientist can explore only some of the possible approaches to a problem. Working alone, each hermit would explore the most promising approaches. They would needlessly duplicate the work of others and would be unlikely to develop approaches which look unpromising but really have (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  14.  41
    Ethical Reasoning Concerning the Feeding of Severely Demented Patients: an International Perspective.A. Norberg, M. Hirschfeld, B. Davidson, A. Davis, S. Lauri, J. Y. Lin, L. Phillips, E. Pittman, R. Vander Laan & L. Ziv - 1994 - Nursing Ethics 1 (1):3-13.
    Structured interviews were held with 149 registered nurses in seven countries in America, Asia, Australia and Europe concerning the feeding of severely demented patients who do not accept food. The most common reasons for nurses being willing to change their decision to feed or not to feed were an order from the medical head, a request from the patient's husband and/or the staff meeting. There was a connection between the willingness to feed and the ranking of ethical principles. Nurses who (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  15.  66
    New waves in philosophy of science.P. D. Magnus & Jacob Busch (eds.) - 2009 - New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    Introduction 1 P. D. Magnus and Jacob Busch 1. Form-driven vs. Content-driven Arguments for Realism 8 Juha Saatsi 2. Optimism about the Pessimistic Induction 29 Sherrilyn Roush 3. Metaphysics between the Sciences and Philosophies of Science 59 Anjan Chakravartty 4. Nominalism and Inductive Generalizations 78 Jessica Pfeifer 5. Models and Scientific Representations 94 Otávio Bueno 6. The Identical Rivals Response to Underdetermination 112 Gregory Frost-Arnold and P. D. Magnus 7. Scientific Representation and the Semiotics of Pictures 131 Laura (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  16. Background theories and total science.P. D. Magnus - 2005 - Philosophy of Science 72 (5):1064-1075.
    Background theories in science are used both to prove and to disprove that theory choice is underdetermined by data. The alleged proof appeals to the fact that experiments to decide between theories typically require auxiliary assumptions from other theories. If this generates a kind of underdetermination, it shows that standards of scientific inference are fallible and must be appropriately contextualized. The alleged disproof appeals to the possibility of suitable background theories to show that no theory choice can be timelessly or (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  17. Friends with benefits! Distributed cognition hooks up cognitive and social conceptions of science.P. D. Magnus & Ron McClamrock - 2015 - Philosophical Psychology 28 (8):1114-1127.
    One approach to science treats science as a cognitive accomplishment of individuals and defines a scientific community as an aggregate of individual inquirers. Another treats science as a fundamentally collective endeavor and defines a scientist as a member of a scientific community. Distributed cognition has been offered as a framework that could be used to reconcile these two approaches. Adam Toon has recently asked if the cognitive and the social can be friends at last. He answers that they probably cannot, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18. Scientific enquiry and natural kinds: from planets to mallards.P. Magnus - 2012 - New York, NY: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    Some scientific categories seem to correspond to genuine features of the world and are indispensable for successful science in some domain; in short, they are natural kinds. This book gives a general account of what it is to be a natural kind and puts the account to work illuminating numerous specific examples.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  19. Realist Ennui and the Base Rate Fallacy.P. D. Magnus & Craig Callender - 2004 - Philosophy of Science 71 (3):320-338.
    The no-miracles argument and the pessimistic induction are arguably the main considerations for and against scientific realism. Recently these arguments have been accused of embodying a familiar, seductive fallacy. In each case, we are tricked by a base rate fallacy, one much-discussed in the psychological literature. In this paper we consider this accusation and use it as an explanation for why the two most prominent `wholesale' arguments in the literature seem irresolvable. Framed probabilistically, we can see very clearly why realists (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   125 citations  
  20.  42
    (1 other version)Perception, Imagery, Memory and Consciousness.Magnus Johnsson - 2022 - Filozofia i Nauka 10:229-244.
    I propose and discuss some principles that I believe are substantial for perception, various kinds of memory, expectations and the capacity for imagination in the mammal brain, as well as for the design of a biologically inspired artificial cognitive architecture. I also suggest why these same principles could explain our ability to represent novel concepts and imagine non-existing and perhaps impossible objects, while there are still limits to what we can imagine and think about. Some ideas regarding how these principles (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  66
    Philosophy of Science in the Twenty‐First Century.P. D. Magnus - 2013 - Metaphilosophy 44 (1-2):48-52.
    Philosophy of science in the past half century can be seen as a reaction against logical empiricism's focus on modern logic as the format in which debates should be expressed and on physics as the canonical science. These reactions have resulted in a fragmentation of the field. Although this provides ways forward for disparate philosophies of various sciences, it threatens the very possibility of general philosophy of science. The debate that most obviously continues to be conducted at the general level—the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  41
    Writing the history of the relations between medicine, gender and the body in the 20th century.Delphine Gardey - 2013 - Clio 37:143-162.
    Rendant compte des travaux récents dans le champ de l’étude sociales des sciences (Social Studies of Knowledge), de la critique féministe des sciences et des cultural studies, cet article revient sur leurs apports et sur la façon dont ils lisent l’histoire des transformations biomédicales (très) contemporaines, notamment dans les domaines de la reproduction et de la sexualité. Les SSK, en particulier, proposent une lecture complexe et riche des relations humains/techniques et de la façon dont les relations sociales et de genre (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  24
    Relations médecine – sciences dans l'individualisation des maladies nerveuses à la Salpêtrière à la fin du xixe siècle.Jean-Gaël Barbara - 2010 - Revue d'Histoire des Sciences 63 (2):369-407.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  16
    Nil utilius, nil praestantius. Über Geschichte, Wesen und Bedeutung des akademischen Lebens in Daniel Hermanns Gedicht De vita literata sive scholastica.Magnus Frisch - 2017 - In Vogt-Spira Gregor & Jönsson Arne (eds.), A. Jönsson / G. Vogt-Spira (Hgg.), The Classical Tradition in the Baltic Region. Perceptions and Adaptations of Greece and Rome (Spudasmata; Bd. 171). Olms. pp. 55-75..
    The Protestant Prussian humanist Daniel Hermann (1543-1601) wrote the occasional poem De vita literata sive scholastica which he performed publicly at the newly established Academy of Straßburg probably in 1567 on behalf of the Academys headmaster when he was still a student himself. In this poem he praises and characterizes the academic life as the most useful and most excellent occupation in the world. He shows that scholarship and science guide the thoughts and the feelings of the students, investigate what (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  11
    There & back.Magnus Pyke - 1978 - London: J. Murray.
  26.  16
    Using Implementation Science to Enact Specific Ethical Norms: The Case of Code Status Policy.Emily Shearer & David Magnus - 2020 - American Journal of Bioethics 20 (4):6-7.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  52
    Biological and cultural bases of human inference.Riccardo Viale, Daniel Andler & Lawrence A. Hirschfeld (eds.) - 2006 - Mahwah, N.J.: Lawerence Erlbaum.
    Biological and Cultural Bases of Human Inference addresses the interface between social science and cognitive science. In this volume, Viale and colleagues explore which human social cognitive powers evolve naturally and which are influenced by culture. Updating the debate between innatism and culturalism regarding human cognitive abilities, this book represents a much-needed articulation of these diverse bases of cognition. Chapters throughout the book provide social science and philosophical reflections, in addition to the perspective of evolutionary theory and the central assumptions (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28. The cognitive foundations of cultural stability and diversity.Dan Sperber & Lawrence A. Hirschfeld - 2004 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 8 (1):40-46.
  29. Generative AI and photographic transparency.P. D. Magnus - forthcoming - AI and Society:1-6.
    There is a history of thinking that photographs provide a special kind of access to the objects depicted in them, beyond the access that would be provided by a painting or drawing. What is included in the photograph does not depend on the photographer’s beliefs about what is in front of the camera. This feature leads Kendall Walton to argue that photographs literally allow us to see the objects which appear in them. Current generative algorithms produce images in response to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30. John Stuart Mill on Taxonomy and Natural Kinds.P. D. Magnus - 2015 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 5 (2):269-280.
    The accepted narrative treats John Stuart Mill’s Kinds as the historical prototype for our natural kinds, but Mill actually employs two separate notions: Kinds and natural groups. Considering these, along with the accounts of Mill’s nineteenth-century interlocutors, forces us to recognize two distinct questions. First, what marks a natural kind as worthy of inclusion in taxonomy? Second, what exists in the world that makes a category meet that criterion? Mill’s two notions offer separate answers to the two questions: natural groups (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  31. What Scientists Know Is Not a Function of What Scientists Know.P. D. Magnus - 2013 - Philosophy of Science 80 (5):840-849.
    There are two senses of ‘what scientists know’: An individual sense (the separate opinions of individual scientists) and a collective sense (the state of the discipline). The latter is what matters for policy and planning, but it is not something that can be directly observed or reported. A function can be defined to map individual judgments onto an aggregate judgment. I argue that such a function cannot effectively capture community opinion, especially in cases that matter to us.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  32. What’s New about the New Induction?P. D. Magnus - 2006 - Synthese 148 (2):295-301.
    The problem of underdetermination is thought to hold important lessons for philosophy of science. Yet, as Kyle Stanford has recently argued, typical treatments of it offer only restatements of familiar philosophical problems. Following suggestions in Duhem and Sklar, Stanford calls for a New Induction from the history of science. It will provide proof, he thinks, of “the kind of underdetermination that the history of science reveals to be a distinctive and genuine threat to even our best scientific theories” (Stanford 2001, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  33. The Interview: Data Collection in Descriptive Phenomenological Human Scientific Research.Magnus Englander - 2012 - Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (1):13-35.
    In this article, interviewing from a descriptive, phenomenological, human scientific perspective is examined. Methodological issues are raised in relation to evaluative criteria as well as reflective matters that concern the phenomenological researcher. The data collection issues covered are 1) the selection of participants, 2) the number of participants in a study, 3) the interviewer and the questions, and 4) data collection procedures. Certain conclusions were drawn indicating that phenomenological research methods cannot be evaluated on the basis of an empiricist theory (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  34.  43
    Ecosemiotic Analysis of Species Reintroduction: the Case of European Mink (Mustela lutreola) in Estonia.Riin Magnus & Nelly Mäekivi - 2023 - Biosemiotics 16 (2):239-258.
    Species conservation activities are gaining more attention in the context of environmental degradation. This article proposes to tackle different semiotic aspects of reintroduction as one possible way of furthering species conservation. More specifically, we aim to bring forth the strength of ecosemiotic perspective when dealing with such a complex matter with many different human and non-human subjects. We concentrate on animal agency, search and function tone, semiotic fitting and changes in umwelten when analysing the reintroduction process from the perspective of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35. Scurvy and the ontology of natural kinds.P. D. Magnus - 2023 - Philosophy of Science 80 (5):1031-1039.
    Some philosophers understand natural kinds to be the categories which are constraints on enquiry. In order to elaborate the metaphysics appropriate to such an account, I consider the complicated history of scurvy, citrus, and vitamin C. It may be tempting to understand these categories in a shallow way (as mere property clusters) or in a deep way (as fundamental properties). Neither approach is adequate, and the case instead calls for middle-range ontology: starting from categories which we identify in the world (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  40
    PROBabilities from EXemplars (PROBEX): a “lazy” algorithm for probabilistic inference from generic knowledge.Peter Juslin & Magnus Persson - 2002 - Cognitive Science 26 (5):563-607.
    PROBEX (PROBabilities from EXemplars), a model of probabilistic inference and probability judgment based on generic knowledge is presented. Its properties are that: (a) it provides an exemplar model satisfying bounded rationality; (b) it is a “lazy” algorithm that presumes no pre‐computed abstractions; (c) it implements a hybrid‐representation, similarity‐graded probability. We investigate the ecological rationality of PROBEX and find that it compares favorably with Take‐The‐Best and multiple regression (Gigerenzer, Todd, & the ABC Research Group, 1999). PROBEX is fitted to the point (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  37. Reckoning the shape of everything: Underdetermination and cosmotopology.P. D. Magnus - 2005 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 56 (3):541-557.
    This paper offers a general characterization of underdetermination and gives a prima facie case for the underdetermination of the topology of the universe. A survey of several philosophical approaches to the problem fails to resolve the issue: the case involves the possibility of massive reduplication, but Strawson on massive reduplication provides no help here; it is not obvious that any of the rival theories are to be preferred on grounds of simplicity; and the usual talk of empirically equivalent theories misses (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  38. Success, Truth and the Galilean Strategy.P. D. Magnus - 2003 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 54 (3):465-474.
    Philip Kitcher develops the Galilean Strategy to defend realism against its many opponents. I explore the structure of the Galilean Strategy and consider it specifically as an instrument against constructive empiricism. Kitcher claims that the Galilean Strategy underwrites an inference from success to truth. We should resist that conclusion, I argue, but the Galilean Strategy should lead us by other routes to believe in many things about which the empiricist would rather remain agnostic. 1 Target: empiricism 2 The Galilean Strategy (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  39. Underdetermination and the problem of identical rivals.P. D. Magnus - 2003 - Philosophy of Science 70 (5):1256-1264.
    If two theory formulations are merely different expressions of the same theory, then any problem of choosing between them cannot be due to the underdetermination of theories by data. So one might suspect that we need to be able to tell distinct theories from mere alternate formulations before we can say anything substantive about underdetermination, that we need to solve the problem of identical rivals before addressing the problem of underdetermination. Here I consider two possible solutions: Quine proposes that we (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  40. Critique and cognitive capacities: Towards an action-oriented model.Magnus Hörnqvist - 2021 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 48 (1):62-85.
    In response to an impasse, articulated in the late 1980s, the cognitive capacities of ordinary people assumed central place in contemporary critical social theory. The participants’ perspective gained precedence over scientific standards branded as external. The notion of cognition, however, went unchallenged. This article continues the move away from external standards, and discusses two models of critique, which differ based on their underlying notions of cognition. The representational model builds on cognitive content, misrecognition and normativity; three features which are illustrated (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  53
    Phenomenological psychology and qualitative research.Magnus Englander & James Morley - 2021 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 22 (1):25-53.
    This article presents the tradition of phenomenologically founded psychological research that was originally initiated by Amedeo Giorgi. This data analysis method is inseparable from the broader project of establishing an autonomous phenomenologically based human scientific psychology. After recounting the history of the method from the 1960’s to the present, we explain the rationale for why we view data collection as a process that should be adaptable to the unique mode of appearance of each particular phenomenon being researched. The substance of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42.  41
    Citizen Science and Gamification.Karola V. Kreitmair & David C. Magnus - 2019 - Hastings Center Report 49 (2):40-46.
    According to the mainstream conception of research involving human participants, researchers have been trained scientists acting within institutions and have been the individuals doing the studying, while participants, who are nonscientist members of the public, have been the individuals being studied. The relationship between the public and scientists is evolving, however, giving rise to several new concepts, including crowdsourcing and citizen science. In addition, the practice of gamification has been applied to research protocols. The role of gamified, crowdsourced citizen scientist (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  43. (1 other version)Peirce: Underdetermination, agnosticism, and related mistakes.P. D. Magnus - 2005 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 48 (1):26 – 37.
    There are two ways that we might respond to the underdetermination of theory by data. One response, which we can call the agnostic response, is to suspend judgment: "Where scientific standards cannot guide us, we should believe nothing". Another response, which we can call the fideist response, is to believe whatever we would like to believe: "If science cannot speak to the question, then we may believe anything without science ever contradicting us". C.S. Peirce recognized these options and suggested evading (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  44.  38
    Empathy and Ethics.Magnus Englander & Susi Ferrarello (eds.) - 2022 - Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
    The authors offer a phenomenological reflection on the problem of the interconnection between empathy and ethics; essential reading for professionals and scholars of philosophy, psychiatry, health science, psychology, and sociology.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45. Demonstrative Induction and the Skeleton of Inference.P. D. Magnus - 2008 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 22 (3):303-315.
    It has been common wisdom for centuries that scientific inference cannot be deductive; if it is inference at all, it must be a distinctive kind of inductive inference. According to demonstrative theories of induction, however, important scientific inferences are not inductive in the sense of requiring ampliative inference rules at all. Rather, they are deductive inferences with sufficiently strong premises. General considerations about inferences suffice to show that there is no difference in justification between an inference construed demonstratively or ampliatively. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  46.  57
    Theory, practice, and epistemology in the development of species concepts.David Magnus - 1996 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 27 (4):521-545.
  47.  15
    Goethe as a Scientist.Rudolf Magnus & Heinz Norden - 1952 - Philosophy of Science 19 (3):243-243.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  48.  17
    Hybrid Natures — Ecosemiotic and Zoosemiotic Perspectives.Nelly Mäekivi & Riin Magnus - 2020 - Biosemiotics 13 (1):1-7.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  33
    The Modeling of Nature: Philosophy of Science and Philosophy of Nature in Synthesis by William A. Wallace. [REVIEW]David Magnus & Monique Bourque - 1998 - Isis 89:372-373.
  50. What Kind of Is-Ought Gap is There and What Kind Ought There Be?P. D. Magnus & Jon Mandle - 2017 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 14 (4):373-393.
    Some philosophers think that there is a gap between is and ought which necessarily makes normative enquiry a different kind of thing than empirical science. This position gains support from our ability to explicate our inferential practices in a way that makes it impermissible to move from descriptive premises to a normative conclusion. But we can also explicate them in a way that allows such moves. So there is no categorical answer as to whether there is or is not a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 945