Positive Retributivism: C. L. TEN

Social Philosophy and Policy 7 (2):194-208 (1990)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

One dark and rainy night, Yuso sexually assaults and tortures Zelan. In escaping from the scene of his crime, he falls heavily and becomes an impotent paraplegic. Instead of treating his fate as divine retribution for his wicked acts, Yuso sees it as sheer bad luck. He shows no remorse for what he has done, and vainly hopes that he will recover his powers, which he now treats as involuntarily hoarded resources to be used on less rainy days. In the presence of others, he pretends that he has turned over a new leaf. He asks for religious and educational books, hoping to make up for his poor education and deprived social background. But he immediately discards them when he is alone in favor of the pornographic magazines which he has bribed a nurse to smuggle in for him. His deception and various obscene acts committed in the hospital are exposed; by the time he comes up for trial, everyone knows that he is still a lustful, sadistic, and unrepentant man. Most retributivists have a sufficient justification for punishing Yuso independently of the social consequences of his punishment. Two features of the case might cause some difficulties. First, Yuso has already experienced considerable suffering and deprivation both before and after his crime, and retributivists might disagree about the relevance of the suffering to his punishment. Secondly, Yuso is unrepentant, and it is unlikely that punishment will change him. This might, as we shall see, create a problem for those who think that the justifying aim of punishment is the moral reform of the offender.

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive

    This entry is not archived by us. If you are the author and have permission from the publisher, we recommend that you archive it. Many publishers automatically grant permission to authors to archive pre-prints. By uploading a copy of your work, you will enable us to better index it, making it easier to find.

    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 106,951

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Compassion: The Basic Social Emotion.Martha Nussbaum - 1996 - Social Philosophy and Policy 13 (1):27.
Nozick's Revenge.Nigel Walker - 1995 - Philosophy 70 (274):581 - 586.
Punishment and Bad Upbringing.Peter Chau - 2018 - Criminal Justice Ethics 37 (2):103-121.
Montesquieu's philosophy of punishment.D. Carrithers - 1998 - History of Political Thought 19 (2):213-240.
A Critical Assessment of Odera Oruka’s Theory of Punishment.Jacinta Mwende Maweu - 2012 - Thought and Practice: A Journal of the Philosophical Association of Kenya 4 (2):97-108.
Care under the Influence.Joseph J. Fins & Samantha F. Knowlton - 2017 - Hastings Center Report 47 (1):8-9.
Retributive Justice.Gertrude Ezorsky - 1972 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 1 (3):365 - 368.

Analytics

Added to PP
2010-08-31

Downloads
155 (#156,536)

6 months
24 (#137,095)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

Retributivism and Resources.Jesper Ryberg - 2013 - Utilitas 25 (1):66-79.
Communication, Expression, and the Justification of Punishment.Andy Engen - 2014 - Athens Journal of Humanities and Arts 1 (4):299-307.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Punishment and Responsibility.H. L. A. Hart - 1968 - Philosophy 45 (172):162-162.
Trials and Punishments.John Cottingham & R. A. Duff - 1987 - Philosophical Quarterly 37 (149):448.
Desert.Jeffrie G. Murphy & George Sher - 1990 - Philosophical Review 99 (2):280.
The justification of general deterrence.Daniel M. Farrell - 1985 - Philosophical Review 94 (3):367-394.

View all 14 references / Add more references