The arts of action

Philosophers' Imprint 20 (14):1-27 (2020)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The theory and culture of the arts has largely focused on the arts of objects, and neglected the arts of action – the “process arts”. In the process arts, artists create artifacts to engender activity in their audience, for the sake of the audience’s aesthetic appreciation of their own activity. This includes appreciating their own deliberations, choices, reactions, and movements. The process arts include games, urban planning, improvised social dance, cooking, and social food rituals. In the traditional object arts, the central aesthetic properties occur in the artistic artifact itself. It is the painting that is beautiful; the novel that is dramatic. In the process arts, the aesthetic properties occur in the activity of the appreciator. It is the game player’s own decisions that are elegant, the rock climber’s own movement that is graceful, and the tango dancers’ rapport that is beautiful. The artifact’s role is to call forth and shape that activity, guiding it along aesthetic lines. I offer a theory of the process arts. Crucially, we must distinguish between the designed artifact and the prescribed focus of aesthetic appreciation. In the object arts, these are one and the same. The designed artifact is the painting, which is also the prescribed focus of appreciation. In the process arts, they are different. The designed artifact is the game, but the appreciator is prescribed to appreciate their own activity in playing the game. Next, I address the complex question of who the artist really is in a piece of process art — the designer or the active appreciator? Finally, I diagnose the lowly status of the process arts.

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

A Defense of Arts-Based Appreciation of Nature.Thomas Leddy - 2005 - Environmental Ethics 27 (3):299-315.
Landscapes of aesthetic education.Stuart Richmond - 2009 - Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Press. Edited by Celeste Snowber.
Hegel’s Account on Aesthetic Objectivity.Andrea Sakoparnig - 2018 - Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy 1:289-294.
Music and the aural arts.Andy Hamilton - 2007 - British Journal of Aesthetics 47 (1):46-63.
The aesthetic field.Arnold Berleant - 1970 - Springfield, Ill.,: Thomas.
Aesthetica and eudaimonia: Education for flourishing must include the arts.Laura D'Olimpio - 2022 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 56 (2):238-250.

Analytics

Added to PP
2020-05-18

Downloads
6,554 (#997)

6 months
635 (#1,978)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

C. Thi Nguyen
University of Utah

Citations of this work

Value Capture.Christopher Nguyen - 2024 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 27 (3).
Autonomy and aesthetic valuing.Nick Riggle - 2024 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research (I):391-409.
The opacity of play: a reply to commentators.C. Thi Nguyen - 2021 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 48 (3):448-475.

View all 14 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

The Grasshopper: Games, Life and Utopia.Bernard Suits & Thomas Hurka - 1978 - Peterborough, CA: Broadview Press.
Games and the art of agency.C. Thi Nguyen - 2019 - Philosophical Review 128 (4):423-462.
Autonomy and Aesthetic Engagement.C. Thi Nguyen - 2019 - Mind 129 (516):1127-1156.
The Practice of Everyday Life.Michel de Certeau - 1988 - University of California Press.
Being for Beauty: Aesthetic Agency and Value.Dominic Lopes - 2018 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.

View all 42 references / Add more references