Results for 'evil as privation'

974 found
Order:
  1.  12
    Evil as Privation: Its True Meaning and Import.Pierce Alexander Marks - 2025 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 97:1-28.
    Many contemporary philosophers have presumed that the doctrine of evil as privation simply means that there can be no evils that count as positive realities. However, this interpretation is naive, and does not cohere well with the Christian theological tradition, especially the work of Augustine, who is widely regarded as the touchstone proponent of the doctrine. The goal of this paper is to clarify the more nuanced, teleological meaning of the doctrine of “evil as privation,” as (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  34
    Evil as Privation in Neoplatonism. Simplicius and Philoponus in Defense of Matter.R. Loredana Cardullo - 2017 - Peitho 8 (1):391-408.
    The aim of this paper is to highlight the decisive contribution of Simplicius and Philoponus to the resolution of the problem of evil in Neoplatonism. A correct and faithful interpretation of the problem, which also had to agree with Plato’s texts, became particularly needed after Plotinus had identified evil with matter, threatening, thus, the dualistic position, which was absent in Plato. The first rectification was made by Proclus with the notion of parhypostasis, i.e., “parasitic” or “collateral” existence, which (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Evil as Privation and Leibniz's Rejection of Empty Space.Stephen Puryear - 2016 - In Wenchao Li (ed.), "Für Unser Glück oder das Glück Anderer": Vortrage des X. Internationalen Leibniz-Kongresses, v. III. Georg Olms. pp. 481-489.
    I argue that Leibniz's treatment of void or empty space in the appendix to his fourth letter to Clarke conflicts with the way he elsewhere treats (metaphysical) evil, insofar as he allows that God has created a world with the one kind of privation (evil), while insisting that God would not have created a world with the other kind of privation (void). I consider three respects in which the moral case might be thought to differ relevantly (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  66
    Aristotle on Evil as Privation.Jonathan J. Sanford - 2017 - International Philosophical Quarterly 57 (2):195-209.
    The notion that evil is not simply a privation but a privation of a due good has roots in Aristotle’s Metaphysics and implications for other areas of his thought. In making this case, I begin with a description of the standard view of Aristotle’s place in the development of the privation theory of evil and contend that the standard view does not do justice to Aristotle’s theory of evil. I then provide an interpretation of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5. Evil as Such Is a Privation.Patrick Lee - 2007 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 81 (3):469-488.
    I reply to an article in the ACPA Proceedings of 2001 by John Crosby in which he challenged the position that evil as such is a privation. Each of his arguments attempts to present a counterexample to the privation position. His first argument, claiming that annihilation is evil but not a privation, fails to consider that a privation need not be contemporaneous with the subject suffering the privation. Contrary to his second argument, I (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  6.  9
    Evil as privative: a McCabian defence.Anastasia Phillipa Scrutton - 2024 - International Journal of Philosophy and Theology 85 (1):23-40.
    Not all theists who are members of the Abrahamic faiths will sign up to a particular metaphysics of evil: some may be sceptical theists, and others may be uninterested in metaphysical questions altogether. In this paper, I argue that theists in the Abrahamic faiths who are interested in metaphysics and who are not sceptical theists should endorse a privative account of evil. This is because a privative view of evil is the only metaphysic of evil that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Evil as Nothing.Marilyn McCord Adams - 2012 - Modern Schoolman 89 (3-4):131-145.
    Anselm inherited a Platonizing approach to philosophy from Augustine and Boethius. But he characteristically reworked what he found in their texts by questioning and disputing it into something more rigorous. In this paper, I compare and contrast Anselm’s treatment of the trope ‘evil is nothing, not a being’ withBoethius’s use of it in The Consolation of Philosophy. In the first section, I expose a fallacious argument form common to them both: paradigm Fness is identical with paradigm Gness; X participates (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8. Heidegger and the Critique of the Understanding of Evil as Privatio Boni.Richard M. Capobianco - 1991 - Philosophy and Theology 5 (3):175-185.
    Despite the efforts of such notable thinkers as Sartre, Camus, and Ricoeur to affirm philosophically the being of evil, a systematic critique of the traditional metaphysical understanding of evil as privation of being has not yet been fully worked out. The task of this paper is to sketch out just such a critique and to suggest a more adequate philosophical reflection on the being of evil by turning to the thought of Heidegger. Part 1 examines Heidegger’s (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  9. The privation theory of evil and the evil-god challenge.John M. Collins - 2024 - Religious Studies:1-19.
    Can the best arguments for a privation theory of evil be parodied, with equal plausibility, as arguments for a privation theory of good? The privation theory of evil claims that evil has no positive existence, and it is but a privation of good. The privation theory of good claims the opposite. I approach this topic as one element in the so-called evil-God Challenge. Stephen Law has argued that the epistemic support for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  43
    Evil, Privation, Depression and Dread.Mark Ian Thomas Robson - 2013 - New Blackfriars 94 (1053):552-564.
    In this essay I examine the idea that evil is to be understood as a kind of absence or a privation. I put forward two arguments against this idea. The first claims that if evil is an absence it becomes causally powerless, which seems strongly contradicted by experience and revelation. The other argument says that the idea that evil is an absence cannot do justice to the evil of depression. Depression is a set of feelings (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11. On the Privation Theory of Evil.Parker Haratine - 2023 - TheoLogica: An International Journal for Philosophy of Religion and Philosophical Theology 7 (2).
    Augustine’s privation theory of evil maintains that something is evil in virtue of a privation, a lack of something which ought to be present in a particular nature. While it is not evil for a human to lack wings, it is indeed evil for a human to lack rationality according to the end of a rational nature. Much of the literature on the privation theory focuses on whether it can successfully defend against counterexamples (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12. The public and private in Saudi Arabia: restrictions on the powers of committees for ordering the good and forbidding the evil.Frank E. Vogel - 2003 - Social Research: An International Quarterly 70 (3):749-768.
    My paper will explore boundaries and rights, the public and the private, as to the enforcement of religious legal rules in societies self-consciously founded on Islamic law. I employ as my case-study legal and social controversies aroused by the Saudi Hay’at al-amr bi-al-ma`ruf wa-al-nahy `an al-munkar, the government agency charged with “ordering the good and forbidding the evil.” The paper will first lay out some of the laws fixing the powers of the Hay’at, including various statutes issued by the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  34
    Corruptio boni: An alternative to the privation theory of evil.Christophe de Ray - 2024 - Ratio 37 (2-3):191-203.
    The classic ‘privation theory’ of evil defines evil as an absence (or ‘privation’) of a good that ought to obtain. Despite its historical importance, privation theory is faced with a number of serious difficulties. I outline two of these difficulties and argue that they continue to pose a threat. I then present ‘corruption theory’, an alternative theory of evil reconstructed from some of Augustine's writings on the subject. I argue that this theory shares the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  79
    Moral Evil, Privation, and God.W. Matthews Grant - 2017 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 9 (1):125--145.
    On a traditional account, God causes sinful acts and their properties, insofar as they are real, but God does not cause sin, since only the sinner causes the privations in virtue of which such acts are sinful. After explicating this privation solution, I defend it against two objections: (1) that God would cause the sinful act’s privation simply by causing the act and its positive features; and (2) that there is no principled way to deny that God causes (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. A Thomistic Answer to the Evil‐God Challenge.B. Kyle Keltz - 2019 - Heythrop Journal 60 (5):689-698.
    Stephen Law’s evil-god challenge is the argument that since an evil god is just as likely as the God of theism, there is no reason to believe that theism is true over believing there is a god who is omnipotent, omniscient, and omnimalevolent. There have been several attempts to answer the challenge, but recently John Collins has defended the evil-god challenge and also extended the argument past Law’s original formulation. In this article, I defend the classical theism (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  16.  11
    Moral evil.Andrew Michael Flescher - 2013 - Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press.
    The idea of moral evil has always held a special place in philosophy and theology because the existence of evil has implications for the dignity of the human and the limits of human action. Andrew M. Flescher proposes four interpretations of evil, drawing on philosophical and theological sources and using them to trace through history the moral traditions that are associated with them. The first model, evil as the presence of badness, offers a traditional dualistic model (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Is All Evil Really Only Privation?John F. Crosby - 2001 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 75:197-209.
    It is proposed to test the privation theory of evil by examining three kinds of evil: (1) the evil of the complete destruction of some good (as distinct from the wounding of that good); (2) the evil of physical pain; and (3) certain forms of moral evil in which the evildoer is hostile to some good. It is shown that in none of these cases does evil seem to fit the privation scheme, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  18. Doubts About the Privation Theory That Will Not Go Away.John F. Crosby - 2007 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 81 (3):489-505.
    Towards the end of his response to me, Lee presents an argument for the necessity of interpreting all evil as privation. I counter this argument by showingthat it works only for what I call “formal” good and evil, but not for what I call “contentful” good and evil. In fact, evil that is “contentful” presents a challenge tothe privation theory that I had not discussed in my article. I then proceed, in the second part (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19. Is Animal Suffering Evil? A Thomistic Perspective.B. Kyle Keltz - 2020 - Journal of Value Inquiry 54 (1):1-19.
    The problem of animal suffering considers whether God would allow millions of years of animal pain, disease, and death. Philosophers who debate this issue often assume that pain and suffering are evils a loving God would not allow without good reason. Moreover, a considerable amount of the debate regarding the problem of animal suffering involves whether animals are capable of experiencing pain and suffering. But this raises the question of whether pain and suffering are intrinsically evil. In this essay (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. On Pain and the Privation Theory of Evil.Irit Samet - 2012 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 4 (1):19--34.
    The paper argues that pain is not a good counter-example to the privation theory of evil. Objectors to the privation thesis see pain as too real to be accounted for in privative terms. However, the properties for which pain is intuitively thought of as real, i.e. its localised nature, intensity, and quality are features of the senso-somatic aspect of pain. This is a problem for the objectors because, as findings of modern science clearly demonstrate, the senso-somatic aspect (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  18
    Of Evil and Other Figures of the Liminal.Leonhard Praeg - 2010 - Theory, Culture and Society 27 (5):107-134.
    Inspired by research on the Rwanda genocide and the decapitation, in July 2008, of a passenger on a Canadian Greyhound bus, this occasional paper explores the shared agitation with which we may respond to two seemingly disparate instances of evil such as these. Arguing against discontinuous claims that distinguish between pre- and post-metaphysical conceptions of evil pivoting around the figure of Kant, the article identifies three logics suggestive of continuity in Western thought on evil: negativity, functionalism and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  27
    Aquinas's Disputed Questions on Evil: A Critical Guide.M. V. Dougherty (ed.) - 2015 - Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press.
    Thomas Aquinas's Disputed Questions on Evil is a careful and detailed analysis of the general topic of evil, including discussions on evil as privation, human free choice, the cause of moral evil, moral failure, and the so-called seven deadly sins. This collection of ten, specially commissioned new essays, the first book-length English-language study of Disputed Questions on Evil, examines the most interesting and philosophically relevant aspects of Aquinas's work, highlighting what is distinctive about it (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23. Privation, parasite et perversion de la volonté.Seamus O’Neill - 2017 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 73 (1):31-52.
    Augustin est bien connu comme défenseur d’une « théorie privative » du mal. On peut lire, par exemple, dans les Confessions que « le mal n’est que la privation du bien, à la limite du pur néant ». Le problème, cependant, avec les théories privatives du mal est qu’elles ne nous offrent pas, généralement, une explication robuste ni de l’activité du mal, ni de son pouvoir à causer des effets bien réels ; effets desquels l’expérience demande, malgré tout, une (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Evil in Schelling and Schopenhauer.Alistair Welchman - 2018 - In Douglas Hedley (ed.), The History of Evil in the Eighteenth and Nineteenth Centuries 1700–1900 CE. Routledge. pp. 150-166.
    Schelling and Schopenhauer both operate in the German idealist tradition initiated by Kant, although both are critical of some of its developments. Schelling's interest in evil – which is at its most intense in his 1809 Freedom essay – stems from his belief that Kant's account of morality. In the Freedom essay Schelling links these theories with the traditional Christian conception of evil as a privation, and attempts by contrast to develop a concept of "radical" or "positive" (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. A philosophy of evil.Lars Fr H. Svendsen - 2010 - Champaign, IL: Dalkey Archive Press.
    Introduction: What is evil and how can we understand it? -- The theology of evil -- Theodicies -- The privation theodicy -- The free will theodicy -- The Iraenean theodicy -- The totality theodicy -- History as secular theodicy -- Job's insight-the theodicy of the hereafter -- Anthropology of evil -- Are people good or evil? -- The typologies of evil -- Demonic evil -- Evil for evil's sake -- Evil's (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  26.  47
    The 'origin' of evil according to Anselm of canterbury.Daniel Deme - 2002 - Heythrop Journal 43 (2):170–184.
    Theological debate about the origin of evil derives from the quest after God’s goodness and justice. This problem can be constructively discussed only within the framework of a universe that has been created good, and within a corresponding anthropology. Anselm’s enquiry proceeds much along these tracks, and is based on the premises of the Platonic‐Augustinian view of evil as the privation of good, yet it concludes with a reference to the domain of the irrational and contradiction in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27. The Evil-God Challenge: Extended and Defended.John M. Collins - 2019 - Religious Studies 55 (1):85-109.
    Stephen Law developed a challenge to theism, known as the evil-god challenge (Law (2010) ). The evil-god challenge to theism is to explain why the theist’s responses to the problem of evil are any better than the diabolist’s – who believes in a supremely evil god – rejoinders to the problem of good, when all the theist’s ploys (theodicy, sceptical theism, etc.) can be parodied by the diabolist. In the first part of this article, I extend (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  28.  17
    Kant’s Theory of Radical Evil and its Franciscan Forebears.Lydia Schumacher - 2023 - Neue Zeitschrift für Systematicsche Theologie Und Religionsphilosophie 65 (2):113-133.
    This article argues that Kant’s famous theory of ‘radical evil’, according to which there is a natural propensity for evil as well as good in all human beings, has precedent in the medieval Franciscan intellectual tradition. In the early thirteenth century, members of this tradition, inspired by its founder Alexander of Hales, developed a novel account of free will, according to which the will is capable of choosing between equally legitimate options of good and evil. In affirming (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Providence and Evil.Carlos Steel - 2016 - In Pieter D'Hoine & Marije Martijn (eds.), All From One: A Guide to Proclus. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    How can evil exist in a world governed by providence? That is the main question addressed in this chapter. To answer it, the author first sets out Proclus’ defence of providence, which combines the gods’ transcendence with their sharing goodness. The next step is to show that despite providence, evils have reality as well. There is, however, no substance or principle of evil, and only human and irrational souls and material bodies are susceptible to it. Evil’s having (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30. Deficient Good as a Cause of Evil: Translation and Analysis of S.Th. I, q.49, a.1 and De malo q.1, a.3. 이상섭 - 2024 - philosophia medii aevi 30:219-282.
    이 연구는 토마스 아퀴나스의 『신학대전』 제1부 제49문 제1절과 『악론』 제1문제3절의 번역 및 해제를 목적으로 한다. 비슷한 시기의 작품으로 보이는 두 텍스트는 모두 ‘선이 악의 원인인가?’라는 문제를 다루면서, 모두 ‘악의 원인’에 대해‘형이상학적’ 관점에서 고찰한다. 이 연구는 두 텍스트를 특히 ‘어떤 의미에서 결함있는 선으로서 의지가 도덕적 악의 원인이 되는가’라는 문제에 집중해서 번역하고 해제를 하였다. 토마스는 『신학대전』과 『악론』에서 모두 도덕적 악이라는 행위의 결함 이전에 그것의 원인으로서 의지 안에서 발견되는 어떤 결함을 전제한다고 주장한다. 즉 『신학대전』에의 텍스트에 따르면 죄과는 의지가 자기의 규칙에 복종하지 않는 한에서 (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  22
    On the existence of evils. Proclus, Jan Opsomer & Carlos G. Steel - 2003 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. Edited by Jan Opsomer & Carlos G. Steel.
    He also protected higher causes from responsibility by saying that evil may result from a combination of goods. Proclus objects: evil is real, and not the mere privation of form. Rather, it is a parasite feeding off good. Parasites have no proper cause, and higher beings are thus vindicated as being the causes only of the good off which evil feeds."--BOOK JACKET.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  23
    Internal Relations and the Possibility of Evil.Martin Shuster - 2010 - European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 2 (2):74-84.
    In this article, I examine Cavell’s understanding and deployment of the categories of ‘evil’ and the ‘monstrous’ in The Claim of Reason. Arguing that these notions cannot be understood apart from Cavell’s reliance on the notion of an ‘internal relation,’ I trace this notion to its Wittgensteinian roots. Ultimately, I show that Cavell’s view of evil allows us to navigate between two horns of a classic dilemma in thinking about evil: it allows us to see evil (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33.  39
    Matière et privation chez Alexandre d'Aphrodise et Plotin.Laurent Lavaud - 2008 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 86 (3):399.
    Résumé — L’influence d’Alexandre d’Aphrodise sur la pensée de Plotin reste encore à évaluer avec précision. Le projet de cet article est de confronter ces deux auteurs sur un point déterminé qui est celui de la définition de la matière. Certains passages des Quaestiones d’Alexandre d’Aphrodise semblent avoir exercé une influence directe sur le traité II, 4 de Plotin, intitulé Sur les deux matières. Mais les différences restent profondes entre le péripatéticien et le platonicien. Le premier voit dans la matière (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  65
    Choice of Evils: In Search of a Viable Rationale.Vera Bergelson - 2012 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 6 (3):289-305.
    The defense of necessity, also known as the “choice of evils,” reflects popular moral intuitions and common sense: sometimes, breaking the rules is the right—indeed, the only—thing to do in order to avoid a greater evil. Citing a classic example, mountain climbers may break into a cabin to wait out a deadly snow storm and appropriate the owner’s provisions because their property violations are a lesser evil compared to the loss of life. At the same time, this defense (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35.  33
    Colloquium 4 Proclus on Evil.Dmitri Nikulin - 2016 - In Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy. pp. 119-146.
    This paper considers the problem of evil as it has been discussed and formulated by Plotinus and polemically taken over by Proclus. Contrary to Plotinus, Proclus does not consider matter as evil. Rather, evil in its elusive indefinite nature has to be characterized by the redefined concepts of privation, subcontrary and parypostasis. In its inescapable deficiency, evil, then, is the privation and subcontrary of the good that exists parypostatically, that is, as elusively present in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  7
    Superstition as Ideology in Iranian Politics: From Majlesi to Ahmadinejad.Ali Rahnema - 2011 - Cambridge University Press.
    A superstitious reading of the world based on religion may be harmless at a private level, yet employed as a political tool it can have more sinister implications. As this fascinating book by Ali Rahnema, a distinguished Iranian intellectual, relates, superstition and mystical beliefs have endured and influenced ideology and political strategy in Iran from the founding of the Safavid dynasty in the sixteenth century to the present day. As Rahnema demonstrates through a close reading of the Persian sources and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37. Reality and the Meaning of Evil: On the Moral Causality of Signs.Kirk G. Kanzelberger - 2020 - Reality 1 (1):146-204.
    ABSTRACT: “Evil is really only a privation.” This philosophical commonplace reflects an ancient solution to the problem of theodicy in one of its dimensions: is evil of such a nature that it must have God as its author? Stated in this particular way, it also reflects the commonplace identification of the real with natural being—the realm of what exists independently of human thought and perspectives—as opposed to all that is termed, by comparison, “merely subjective” and “unreal”. If (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  23
    The Banality of (Automated) Evil: Critical Reflections on the Concept of Forbidden Knowledge in Machine Learning Research.Rosa Marina Senent Julián & Diego Bueso Acevedo - 2022 - Recerca.Revista de Pensament I Anàlisi 27 (2).
    The development of computer science has raised ethical concerns regarding the potential negative impacts of machine learning tools on people and society. Some examples are pornographic deepfakes used as weapons of war against women; pattern recognition designed to uncover sexual orientation; and misuse of data and deep learning by private companies to influence democratic elections. We contend that these three examples are cases of automated evil. In this article, we defend that the concept of forbidden knowledge can help to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  34
    Is Pain Metaphysically Evil (Malum Simpliciter)?Mariusz Tabaczek - 2024 - Scientia et Fides 12 (1):143-162.
    Contrary to the commonly assumed opinion that Christianity sees pain as intrinsically evil – where evil is defined as the lack of something good – Aquinas defines pain not as a privation but rather a passion of the soul, i.e., an emotion that depends on sensual and/or intellective cognition of something evil, is good in itself, and may serve a purpose. This article offers a formalized version of the Thomistic definition of pain and related negative (unpleasant) (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  14
    The Geography of Good and Evil: Philosophical Investigations.Andreas Kinneging - 2009 - Wilmington, Del.: Intercollegiate Studies Institute. Edited by Ineke Hardy & Jonathan Price.
    _Do good and evil exist? Absolutely._ In this bracing book, the eminent Dutch philosopher Andreas Kinneging turns fashionable thinking on its head, revealing how good and evil are objective, universal, and unchanging—and how they must be rediscovered in our age. In mapping the geography of good and evil, Kinneging reclaims, and reintroduces us to, the great tradition of ancient and Christian thought. Traditional wisdom enables us to address the eternal questions of good and evil that confront (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. All for the good.David S. Oderberg - unknown
    The Guise of the Good thesis has received much attention since Anscombe's brief defence in her book Intention. I approach it here from a less common perspective - indirectly, via a theory explaining how it is that moral behaviour is even possible. After setting out how morality requires the employment of a fundamental test, I argue that moral behaviour involves orientation toward the good. Immoral behaviour cannot, however, involve orientation to evil as such, given the theory of evil (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42.  31
    Bumbling idiots or evil masterminds? Challenging cold war stereotypes about women, sexuality and state socialism.Kristen Ghodsee & Kateřina Lisková - 2016 - Filozofija I Društvo 27 (3):489-503.
    In academic writing, facts about the past generally require the citation of relevant sources unless the fact or idea is considered?common knowledge:? bits of information or dates upon which there is a wide scholarly consensus. This brief article reflects on the use of?common knowledge? claims in contemporary scholarship about women, families, and sexuality as experienced during 20th century, East European, state socialist regimes. We focus on several key stereotypes about the communist state and the situation of women that are often (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  82
    The Metaphysics of Good and Evil.David S. Oderberg - 2019 - New York, NY: Routledge.
    The Metaphysics of Good and Evil is the first, full-length contemporary defence, from the perspective of analytic philosophy, of the Scholastic theory of good and evil - the theory of Aristotle, Augustine, Aquinas, and most medieval and Thomistic philosophers. Goodness is analysed as obedience to nature. Evil is analysed as the privation of goodness. Goodness, surprisingly, is found in the non-living world, but in the living world it takes on a special character. The book analyses various (...)
    No categories
  44.  20
    Une conception de l'objectivité du mal.Daniel Schulthess - 1986 - In J. Hainard & Rudolf Kaehr (eds.), Le mal et la douleur. Musée d'ethnographie. pp. p.171-180.
    The article sketches a possible argument for the objectivity of the evil. In a first stage the author deals with the emotivist thesis according to which evaluative judgments are nothing other than the expression of our positive or negative emotions toward an object. Although this thesis is rejected, the idea that emotions play a central role by the uttering of an evaluative judgement is retained. It is only by critically examining such judgments that one can eviscerate the objective core (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  21
    Malum: theologische Hermeneutik des Bösen.Ingolf U. Dalferth - 2008 - Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.
    Ingolf U. Dalferth studies the complexity of this procedure in three thought processes which deal with the central concepts in the Christian understanding of malum as privation (a lack of good), as evil-doing and as a lack of faith.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46.  44
    “Where Were You when I Laid Earth’s Foundations?” Levinas and the Book of Job.Nicolas de Warren - 2021 - Levinas Studies 15:203-234.
    Although Levinas’s thinking has generated substantial attention for its emphasis on the irreducibility of alterity, an unconditional responsibility for others, and “ethics as first philosophy,” his accentuation of war and suffering, and hence “evil” in a capacious sense, as endemic to existence, has attracted less notice. In this paper, I explore the originality of Levinas’s reflections on evil in his essay “Transcendence and Evil” against the backdrop of his earlier identification of the “evil of being” and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  28
    Aquinas on the Sources of Wrongdoing.Thomas Williams - 2019 - Oxford Studies in Medieval Philosophy 7 (1).
    Colleen McCluskey begins Thomas Aquinas on Moral Wrongdoing with an overview of Aquinas’s account of human nature and his theory of human action. She discusses the powers of the soul, including the sensory appetite and its passions, the intellect, and the will. Crucially, she devotes considerable attention to the ways in which the passions can affect the intellect’s judgment and, thereby, the will. She then explores Aquinas’s account of the ontological status of evil as a privation, arguing that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  9
    The wise man is never merely a private citizen: The Roman Stoa in Hugo Grotius’ De Jure Praedae (1604–1608).Martine van Ittersum - 2010 - History of European Ideas 36 (1):1-18.
    The possible Stoic origins of the natural rights and natural law theories of the Dutch jurist Hugo Grotius (1583–1645) has been a subject of scholarly debate in recent years. Yet discussions about Grotian sociability tend to focus exclusively on the meaning of appetitus societatis in De Jure Praedae (written in 1604–1608) and De Jure Belli ac Pacis (1625), with little reference to the historical context. Insufficient consideration has been given to the intended audience(s) of these works, Grotius’ purpose in writing (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Pursuing Pankalia: The Aesthetic Theodicy of St. Augustine.A. G. Holdier - 2015 - In Benjamin McCraw & Robert Arp (eds.), The Problem of Evil: New Philosophical Directions. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books. pp. 69-83.
    This chapter summarizes Augustine’s often-neglected aesthetic theodicy that balances his metaphysical definitions of evil and human agency against the ultimately beautiful story Augustine sees God, as the author of all Creation, writing. First, Augustine’s neo-Platonic conception of evil as the “privation of goodness” is explained which effectively eliminates much of the apparent evil in the world under the guise of a preeminent God’s loving care of the Creation which He fashions as good, but is later corrupted. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  51
    Plotinus on the Making of Matter Part III: The Essential Background.Denis O’Brien - 2012 - International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 6 (1):27-80.
    Abstract Plotinus did not set out to be obscure. Difficulties of interpretation arise partly from his style of writing, compressed, elliptical, allusive. The allusions, easily enough recognisable by those he was writing for, are often not recognised at all by the modern reader who no longer has at his fingertips the texts of Plato and Aristotle that Plotinus undoubtedly alludes to, but whose authors he has no need to name. So it is pre-eminently with his subtle use of earlier ideas (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 974